Results for 'Craig Richardson'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  10
    Face on: Photography as Social Exchange.Mark Durden & Craig Richardson - 2000 - Black Dog Publishing.
    This study examines new and existing photographic and lens-based art focusing upon the theme of social exchange. The text explores the history of documentary photography and maps out current solutions and strategies to problems in the discourse between photographer and subject.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Worship and Veneration.Brandon Warmke & Craig Warmke - forthcoming - In Aaron Segal & Samuel Lebens (eds.), The Philosophy of Worship: Divine and Human Aspects. Cambridge University Press.
    Various strands of religious thought distinguish veneration from worship. According to these traditions, believers ought to worship God alone. To worship anything else, they say, is idolatry. And yet many of these same believers also claim to venerate—but not worship—saints, angels, images, relics, tombs, and even each other. But what's the difference? Tim Bayne and Yujin Nagasawa (2006: 302) are correct that “it seems to be extremely difficult to distinguish veneration from worship.” Many have argued throughout history that veneration collapses (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The Problem of Perception.Tim Crane & Craig French - 2021 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The Problem of Perception is a pervasive and traditional problem about our ordinary conception of perceptual experience. The problem is created by the phenomena of perceptual illusion and hallucination: if these kinds of error are possible, how can perceptual experience be what we ordinarily understand it to be: something that enables direct perception of the world? These possibilities of error challenge the intelligibility of our ordinary conception of perceptual experience; the major theories of experience are responses to this challenge.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  4. The Formulation of Epistemological Disjunctivism.Craig French - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92 (1):86-104.
    I argue that we should question the orthodox way of thinking about epistemological disjunctivism. I suggest that we can formulate epistemological disjunctivism in terms of states of seeing things as opposed to states of seeing that p. Not only does this alternative formulation capture the core aspects of epistemological disjunctivism as standardly formulated, it has two salient advantages. First, it avoids a crucial problem that arises for a standard formulation of epistemological disjunctivism—the basis problem. And second, it is less committed (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  5.  11
    Heidegger.William J. Richardson - 1967 - The Hague,: Martinus Nijhoff.
  6.  12
    Specifying norms as a way to resolve concrete ethical problems.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (4):279-310.
  7. Homeric professors in the age of the sophists.N. J. Richardson - 2006 - In Andrew Laird (ed.), Ancient Literary Criticism. Oxford University Press.
  8. VII—Naive Realism and Diaphaneity.Craig French - 2018 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 118 (2):149-175.
    Naïve Realists think that the ordinary mind-independent objects that we perceive are constitutive of the character of experience. Some understand this in terms of the idea that experience is diaphanous: that the conscious character of a perceptual experience is entirely constituted by its objects. My main goal here is to argue that Naïve Realists should reject this, but I’ll also highlight some suggestions as to how Naïve Realism might be developed in a non-diaphanous direction.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  11
    Non sense-specific perception and the distinction between the senses.Louise Richardson - 2014 - Res Philosophica 91 (2):215-239.
    How should interaction between the senses affect thought about them? I try to capture some ways in which non sense-specific perception might be thought to make it impossible or pointless or explanatorily idle to distinguish between senses. This task is complicated by there being more than one view of the nature of the senses, and more than one kind of non sense-specific perception. I argue, in particular, that provided we are willing to forgo certain assumptions about, for instance, the relationship (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  13
    Specifying, balancing, and interpreting bioethical principles.Henry S. Richardson - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (3):285 – 307.
    The notion that it is useful to specify norms progressively in order to resolve doubts about what to do, which I developed initially in a 1990 article, has been only partly assimilated by the bioethics literature. The thought is not just that it is helpful to work with relatively specific norms. It is more than that: specification can replace deductive subsumption and balancing. Here I argue against two versions of reliance on balancing that are prominent in recent bioethical discussions. Without (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  11. VII—The Straight-edge of Virtue: Aristotle on the Rational Significance of Beauty-in-Action.Gabriel Richardson Lear - forthcoming - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society.
    Aristotle claims that the virtuous person acts for the sake of to kalon. To understand this idea, I examine the analogy he draws between craft and virtue. I argue that the kalon is a formal feature of well-ordered wholeness and that the virtuous person takes intellectual pleasure in perceiving (or remembering or imagining) the kalon-in-action, akin to pleasure in observing artworks or works of nature. However, the virtuous person’s pleasure in kalon action is primarily a pleasure of practical reason. In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Bálint’s syndrome, Object Seeing, and Spatial Perception.Craig French - 2018 - Mind and Language 33 (3):221-241.
    Ordinary cases of object seeing involve the visual perception of space and spatial location. But does seeing an object require such spatial perception? An empirical challenge to the idea that it does comes from reflection upon Bálint's syndrome, for some suppose that in Bálint's syndrome subjects can see objects without seeing space or spatial location. In this article, I question whether the empirical evidence available to us adequately supports this understanding of Bálint's syndrome, and explain how the aforementioned empirical challenge (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13. Synchrony and swing in conversation: coordination, temporal dynamics and communication.Daniel Richardson, Rick Dale & Schockley & Kevin - 2008 - In Ipke Wachsmuth, Manuela Lenzen & Günther Knoblich (eds.), Embodied Communication in Humans and Machines. Oxford University Press.
  14. Naive realism, representationalism, and the rationalizing role of visual perception.Craig French - 2020 - Philosophical Issues 30 (1):102-119.
    Philosophical Issues, Volume 30, Issue 1, Page 102-119, October 2020.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. The Metaphysics of Sensory Experience.Craig French - 2022 - Philosophical Review 131 (4):523-528.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. The Invalidity of the Argument from Illusion.Craig French & Lee Walters - 2018 - American Philosophical Quarterly 55 (4):357-364.
    The argument from illusion attempts to establish the bold claim that we are never perceptually aware of ordinary material objects. The argument has rightly received a great deal critical of scrutiny. But here we develop a criticism that, to our knowledge, has not hitherto been explored. We consider the canonical form of the argument as it is captured in contemporary expositions. There are two stages to our criticism. First, we show that the argument is invalid. Second, we identify premises that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  31
    Attitudes toward physician-assisted suicide among physicians in Vermont.A. Craig, B. Cronin, W. Eward, J. Metz, L. Murray, G. Rose, E. Suess & M. E. Vergara - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (7):400-403.
    Background: Legislation on physician-assisted suicide is being considered in a number of states since the passage of the Oregon Death With Dignity Act in 1994. Opinion assessment surveys have historically assessed particular subsets of physicians.Objective: To determine variables predictive of physicians’ opinions on PAS in a rural state, Vermont, USA.Design: Cross-sectional mailing survey.Participants: 1052 physicians licensed by the state of Vermont.Results: Of the respondents, 38.2% believed PAS should be legalised, 16.0% believed it should be prohibited and 26.0% believed it should (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  18.  21
    Narrating the history of reason itself: Friedman, Kuhn, and a constitutive a priori for the twenty-first century.Alan W. Richardson - 2002 - Perspectives on Science 10 (3):253-274.
    : This essay explores some themes in use of a relativized Kantian a priori in the work of Thomas Kuhn and Michael Friedman. It teases out some shared and some divergent beliefs and attitudes in these two philosophers by comparing their characteristic questions and problems to the questions and problems that seem most appropriately to attend to an adequate understanding of games and their histories. It argues for a way forward within a relativized Kantian framework that is suggested but not (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  19.  40
    Logical idealism and Carnap's construction of the world.Alan W. Richardson - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):59 - 92.
  20.  18
    The calculus as algebraic analysis: Some observations on mathematical analysis in the 18th century.Craig G. Fraser - 1989 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 39 (4):317-335.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  21.  10
    Some undecidable problems involving elementary functions of a real variable.Daniel Richardson - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (4):514-520.
  22. Annual editions.John E. Richardson - 1992 - Business Ethics 11:12.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  4
    William James: in the maelstrom of American modernism: a biography.Robert D. Richardson - 2006 - Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
    Biographer Richardson has written a moving portrait of James--pivotal member of the Metaphysical Club and author of The Varieties of Religious Experience. The biography, ten years in the making, draws on unpublished letters, journals, and family records. Richardson paints extraordinary scenes from what James himself called the "buzzing blooming confusion" of his life, beginning with childhood, as he struggled to achieve amid the domestic chaos and intellectual brilliance of Father, brother Henry, and sister Alice. James was a beloved (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Communitarian journalism (s): Clearing conceptual landscapes.David A. Craig - 1996 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 11:107-118.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  25.  12
    Naive Realist Perspectives on Seeing Blurrily.Craig French - 2015 - In James Stazicker (ed.), The Structure of Perceptual Experience. Hoboken, NJ, USA: Wiley. pp. 31–51.
    Naive realists hold that experience is to be understood in terms of an intimate perceptual relation between a subject and aspects of the world, relative to a certain standpoint. Those aspects of the world themselves shape the contours of consciousness. But blurriness is an aspect of some of our experiences that does not seem to come from the world. I argue that this constitutes a significant challenge to some forms of naive realism. But I also argue that there is a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  12
    Biology and ideology: The interpenetration of science and values.Robert C. Richardson - 1984 - Philosophy of Science 51 (3):396-420.
    The mutual influence of science and values in biology is exhibited in several cases from the biological literature. It is argued in a number of cases, from R. A. Fisher's argument for the optimality of a 50:50 sex ratio to A. Jensen's defense of a genetic basis for intelligence, and including work on the evolution of sexual dimorphism and muted aggression, that the credence accorded the views is disproportionate with their theoretical and empirical warrant. It is, furthermore, suggested that the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27.  9
    Conceiving, Experiencing, and Conceiving Experiencing: Neo-Kantianism and the History of the Concept of Experience.Alan W. Richardson - 2003 - Topoi 22 (1):55-67.
    It is often claimed that epistemological thought divides around the issue of the place of experience in knowledge: While empiricists argue that experience is the only legitimate source of knowledge, rationalists find other such sources. The trouble with such accounts is not that they are wrong, but that they are incomplete. On occasion, epistemological differences run deeper, raising the very notion of experience as an issue for epistemology. This paper looks at two epistemological debates which concerned not simply the place (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28.  4
    Reply to Professor Robin SmalI.John Richardson - 1989 - International Studies in Philosophy 21 (2):135-138.
  29.  5
    Art Watch: The American Grain, Crosscut.John Adkins Richardson - 1987 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 21 (4):145.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Harman, G. and Thomson, JJ-Moral Relativism and Moral Objectivity.H. S. Richardson - 1997 - Philosophical Books 38:218-220.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Leonardi, P. and Satambrogio, M.(eds.)-On Quine.A. Richardson - 1997 - Philosophical Books 38:112-113.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  10
    Modernism and Its Arriere-Garde.John Adkins Richardson - 1986 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 20 (4):117.
  33. Myself When Young. Melbourne.Henry Handel Richardson - forthcoming - Minerva.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Psychoanalysis and Anti-Humanism: Lacan's Legacy.W. Richardson - 1986 - Krisis 5:61-80.
  35.  2
    The Visual Arts and Cultural Literacy.John Adkins Richardson - 1990 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 24 (1):57.
  36.  3
    Sets of theorems with short proofs.Daniel Richardson - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):235-242.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  37.  12
    Degrees of finality and the highest good in Aristotle.Henry S. Richardson - 1992 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (3):327-352.
    This article develops a uniform interpretation of "pursuit for the sake of an end", explaining what an "unqualified final" end (sought solely for its own sake) offers that a (merely) final one does not and providing an improved account of what Aristotle means by an "ultimate end". This interpretation sheds light on (1) the regress argument at the outset of "N.E." I.2, (2) the way Aristotle argues for the existence of a highest good, (3) the special contribution of "self-sufficiency" (autarkeia) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  38.  14
    Science as Will and Representation: Carnap, Reichenbach, and the Sociology of Science.Alan W. Richardson - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):162.
    This essay explores some of the issues raised as regards the relations of philosophy and sociology of science in the work of Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach. It argues that Hans Reichenbach's distinction between the contexts of discovery and justification should not be seen as erecting a principled normative/descriptive distinction that demarcates philosophy of science from sociology of science. The essay also raises certain issues about the role of volition, decision, and the limits of epistemological concern in the work of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  39.  16
    D'Alembert's Principle: The Original Formulation and Application in Jean d'Alembert'sTraité de Dynamique.Craig Fraser - 1985 - Centaurus 28 (1):31-61.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40. Hellenists and Hebrews: Reappraising Division Within the Earliest Church.Craig C. Hill - 1992
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. In God's Time: The Bible and the Future.Craig C. Hill - 2002
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  9
    Conjoint dissociations reveal involuntary ''perceptual'' priming from generating at study.Alan Richardson-Klavehn, A. J. Benjamin Clarke & John M. Gardiner - 1999 - Consciousness and Cognition 8 (3):271-284.
    Incidental perceptual memory tests reveal priming when words are generated orally from a semantic cue at study, and this priming could reflect contamination by voluntary retrieval. We tested this hypothesis using a generate condition and two read conditions that differed in depth of processing (read-phonemic vs read-semantic). An intentional word-stem completion test showed an advantage for the read-semantic over the generate condition and an advantage for the generate over the read-phonemic condition, and completion times were longer than in a control (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  16
    Nietzsche contra Darwin.John Richardson - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):537-575.
    Nietzsche attributes 'will power' to all living things, but this seems in sharp conflict with other positions important to him-and implausible besides. The doctrine smacks of both metaphysics and anthropomorphizing, which he elsewhere derides. Will to power seems to be an intentional end-directedness, involving cognitive or representational powers he is rightly loath to attribute to all organisms, and tends to downplay even in persons. This paper argues that we find a stronger reading of will to power-both more plausible and more (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  18
    Chance and the patterns of drift: A natural experiment.Robert C. Richardson - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (5):642-654.
    Evolutionary models can explain the dynamics of populations, how genetic, genotypic, or phenotypic frequencies change with time. Models incorporating chance, or drift, predict specific patterns of change. These are illustrated using classic work on blood types by Cavalli-Sforza and his collaborators in the Parma Valley of Italy, in which the theoretically predicted patterns are exhibited in human populations. These data and the models display properties of ensembles of populations. The explanatory problem needs to be understood in terms of how likely (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45. Idealization and the Abstractive-Theoretical Model of Scientific Explanation.Craig Dilworth - 1990 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 16:167-181.
  46.  1
    Penicillins and Staphylococci: A Historical Interaction.Craig H. Steffee - 1992 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 35 (4):596-608.
  47.  78
    Francisco Vallés and the Renaissance Reinterpretation of Aristotle's Meteorologica Iv as a Medical Text1.Craig Martin - 2002 - Early Science and Medicine 7 (1):1-30.
    In this paper I describe the context and goals of Francisco Vallés' In IV librum Meteorologicorum commentaria. Vallés' work stands as a landmark because it interprets a work of Aristotle's natural philosophy specifically for medical doctors and medical theory. Vallés' commentary is representative of new understandings of Galenic-Hippocratic medi-cine that emerged as a result of expanding textual knowledge. These approaches are evident in a number of sixteenth-century commentaries on Meteorologica IV; in particular the works of Pietro Pomponazzi, Lodovico Boccadiferro, Jacob (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  11
    The role of community consultation in the ethical conduct of research without consent.Lynne D. Richardson, Rosamond Rhodes, Deborah Fish Ragin & Ilene Wilets - 2006 - American Journal of Bioethics 6 (3):33 – 35.
  49.  11
    Do free-market governments create crisis-ridden societies?Bill Richardson & Peter Curwen - 1995 - Journal of Business Ethics 14 (7):551 - 560.
    The paper is concerned with the potential or actual impact that free-market governmental principles and policies might have, or might have had, in helping to create a more crisis-prone world. It is concerned with organizationally-induced crises where organizations and their environment interact to create disasters. The nature of the crisis-prone organization is discussed in the context of the relevant management literature. It is argued that the disastrous interaction of such an organization with its environment is promoted by a laisser-faire attitude (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  4
    Four standards for teaching ethics in journalism.Brian Richardson - 1994 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 9 (2):109 – 117.
    The tendency among working journalists to view ethics negatively, and ethical decision making as an attempt to inhibit their work by post facto sniping, is in part attributable to the way ethics is still taught in some undergraduate journalism programs - as a compendium of what journalists should not do. By adopting an approach that helps students and working journalists recognize ethics as affirmative, systematic, integrative, and definitive, ethics teachers can help foster a conception of ethics as positive, helpful, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000