Results for 'Friedman's logical interpretation'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Friedman's Methodological Stance and Popper's Situational Logic.Robert Nadeau - unknown
    It has already been argued by Frazer and Boland (1983) that, interpreted in an instrumentalist fashion, Milton Friedman’s well known and much criticized 1953 paper on “The Methodology of Positive Economics”1 proved to be convergent with Popper's falsificationist philosophy of science2. I think that this comparison is flawed. For one can assuredly contest this interpretation in view of the fact that Popper always opposed any kind of instrumentalist philosophy of science3. It is not even clear that what Friedman has (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  18
    The ant colony as a test for scientific theories of consciousness.Daniel A. Friedman & Eirik Søvik - 2021 - Synthese 198 (2):1457-1480.
    The appearance of consciousness in the universe remains one of the major mysteries unsolved by science or philosophy. Absent an agreed-upon definition of consciousness or even a convenient system to test theories of consciousness, a confusing heterogeneity of theories proliferate. In pursuit of clarifying this complicated discourse, we here interpret various frameworks for the scientific and philosophical study of consciousness through the lens of social insect evolutionary biology. To do so, we first discuss the notion of a forward test versus (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  12
    Predictive simplicity: induction exhum'd.Kenneth S. Friedman - 1990 - New York: Pergamon Press.
    The book attempts to develop an account of simplicity in terms of testability, and to use this account to provide an adequate characterization of induction, one immune to the class of problems suggested by Nelson Goodman. It is then shown that the past success of induction, thus characterized, constitutes evidence for its future success. A qualitative measure of confirmation is developed, and this measure - along with the considerations of simplicity - is used to provide an account of the consilience (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Poincaré's conventionalism and the logical positivists.Michael Friedman - 1995 - Foundations of Science 1 (2):299-314.
    The logical positivists adopted Poincare's doctrine of the conventionality of geometry and made it a key part of their philosophical interpretation of relativity theory. I argue, however, that the positivists deeply misunderstood Poincare's doctrine. For Poincare's own conception was based on the group-theoretical picture of geometry expressed in the Helmholtz-Lie solution of the space problem, and also on a hierarchical picture of the sciences according to which geometry must be presupposed be any properly physical theory. But both of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  5.  65
    Modal Platonism: an Easy Way to Avoid Ontological Commitment to Abstract Entities.Joel I. Friedman - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (3):227-273.
    Modal Platonism utilizes "weak" logical possibility, such that it is logically possible there are abstract entities, and logically possible there are none. Modal Platonism also utilizes a non-indexical actuality operator. Modal Platonism is the EASY WAY, neither reductionist nor eliminativist, but embracing the Platonistic language of abstract entities while eliminating ontological commitment to them. Statement of Modal Platonism. Any consistent statement B ontologically committed to abstract entities may be replaced by an empirically equivalent modalization, MOD(B), not so ontologically committed. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  20
    Israel Bar-Yehuda Idalovichi, Symbolic Forms as the Metaphysical Groundwork for the Organon of the Cultural Sciences. Reviewed by.Asaf Friedman - 2015 - Philosophy in Review 35 (3):146-148.
    This ambitious work reclassifies and restructures the history of ideas and the philosophy of culture through a wide-ranging and novel use of the idea of the organon. It does so by radically revising standard interpretations and theories of all branches of philosophy, and by providing an intellectual and philosophical foundation for the new organon of the cultural sciences. The seeded idea that saw its growth in the form of this book is the unshakable conviction that the only way by which (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  39
    European and American Philosophers.John Marenbon, Douglas Kellner, Richard D. Parry, Gregory Schufreider, Ralph McInerny, Andrea Nye, R. M. Dancy, Vernon J. Bourke, A. A. Long, James F. Harris, Thomas Oberdan, Paul S. MacDonald, Véronique M. Fóti, F. Rosen, James Dye, Pete A. Y. Gunter, Lisa J. Downing, W. J. Mander, Peter Simons, Maurice Friedman, Robert C. Solomon, Nigel Love, Mary Pickering, Andrew Reck, Simon J. Evnine, Iakovos Vasiliou, John C. Coker, Georges Dicker, James Gouinlock, Paul J. Welty, Gianluigi Oliveri, Jack Zupko, Tom Rockmore, Wayne M. Martin, Ladelle McWhorter, Hans-Johann Glock, Georgia Warnke, John Haldane, Joseph S. Ullian, Steven Rieber, David Ingram, Nick Fotion, George Rainbolt, Thomas Sheehan, Gerald J. Massey, Barbara D. Massey, David E. Cooper, David Gauthier, James M. Humber, J. N. Mohanty, Michael H. Dearmey, Oswald O. Schrag, Ralf Meerbote, George J. Stack, John P. Burgess, Paul Hoyningen-Huene, Nicholas Jolley, Adriaan T. Peperzak, E. J. Lowe, William D. Richardson, Stephen Mulhall & C. - 1991 - In Robert L. Arrington (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophers. Malden, Mass.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 109–557.
    Peter Abelard (1079–1142 ce) was the most wide‐ranging philosopher of the twelfth century. He quickly established himself as a leading teacher of logic in and near Paris shortly after 1100. After his affair with Heloise, and his subsequent castration, Abelard became a monk, but he returned to teaching in the Paris schools until 1140, when his work was condemned by a Church Council at Sens. His logical writings were based around discussion of the “Old Logic”: Porphyry's Isagoge, aristotle'S Categories (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Carnap's logical structure of the world.Chris Pincock - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (6):951-961.
    This article aims to give an overview of Carnap's 1928 book Logical Structure of the World or Aufbau and the most influential interpretations of its significance. After giving an outline of the book in Section 2 , I turn to the first sustained interpretations of the book offered by Goodman and Quine in Section 3 . Section 4 explains how this empirical reductionist interpretation was largely displaced by its main competitor. This is the line of interpretation offered (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  19
    S. Feferman. Reflecting on incompleteness. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 56 , no. 1, pp. 1–49. - W. N. Reinhardt. Some remarks on extending and interpreting theories with a partial predicate for truth. Journal of Philosophical Logic, vol. 15 , no. 2, pp. 219–251. - V. Halbach and L. Horsten. Axiomatizing Kripke’s theory of truth. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 71 , no. 2, pp. 667–712 - H. Friedman and M. Sheard. An axiomatic approach to self-referential truth.Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 33 , no. 1, pp. 1–21. - V. Halbach. A system of complete and consistent truth. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 35 , no. 3, pp. 311–327. [REVIEW]Graham E. Leigh - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):424-428.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  6
    Epistemology of Geometry: Structure-Constructivism (Ⅰ) - Beyond the Argument Between the Logical and the Phenomenological Interpretation on the Role of Intuition in Kant’s Theory of Geometry -. 문장수 - 2022 - Journal of the New Korean Philosophical Association 108:23-52.
    본 연구는 기하학에 대한 구조-구성주의 인식론을 정당화하는 것이다. 즉 구조주의와 구성주의를 융합하는 필자의 고유한 인식론으로 기하학적 인식의 본성을 해명하는 것이다. 그러나 현재의 연구는 이러한 큰 주제에 접근하기 위한 예비적 연구로서 칸트의 기하학적 직관 개념에 대한 역사-비판적 분석을 제공하는 데 한정된다. 잘 알려져 있는 것처럼, 칸트는 수학적 인식, 특히 기하학적 인식을 위해서 직관이 핵심적으로 중요하다고 주장했다. 그런데 칸트가 말하는 기하학적 인식을 위한 직관의 역할이 무엇인지는 여전히 논쟁적이다. 이점과 관련해서 역사적으로 대립적인 두 가지 해석이 있다. 하나는 베스(E. Beth), 힌티카(J. Hintikka), 프리드만(M. Fridman) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  19
    Downey, R., Gasarch, W. and Moses, M., The structure.S. D. Friedman, W. G. Handley, S. S. Wainer, A. Joyal, I. Moerdijk, L. Newelski, F. van Engelen & J. van Oosten - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 70 (1):287.
  12.  55
    Carnap’s Logical Structure of the World. [REVIEW]Christopher Pincock - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (6):951-961.
    This article aims to give an overview of Carnap’s 1928 book Logical Structure of the World or Aufbau and the most influential interpretations of its significance. After giving an outline of the book in Section 2, I turn to the first sustained interpretations of the book offered by Goodman and Quine in Section 3. Section 4 explains how this empirical reductionist interpretation was largely displaced by its main competitor. This is the line of interpretation offered by Friedman (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  19
    Universally Baire sets and definable well-orderings of the reals.S. Y. D. Friedman & Ralf Schindler - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (4):1065-1081.
    Let n ≥ 3 be an integer. We show that it is consistent that every σ1n-set of reals is universally Baire yet there is a projective well-ordering of the reals. The proof uses “David’s trick” in the presence of inner models with strong cardinals.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  22
    0# and inner models.S. Y. D. Friedman - 2002 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 67 (3):924-932.
  15. Reconsidering Kant, Friedman, logical positivism, and the exact sciences.Robert DiSalle - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (2):191-211.
    This essay considers the nature of conceptual frameworks in science, and suggests a reconsideration of the role played by philosophy in radical conceptual change. On Kuhn's view of conceptual conflict, the scientist's appeal to philosophical principles is an obvious symptom of incommensurability; philosophical preferences are merely “subjective factors” that play a part in the “necessarily circular” arguments that scientists offer for their own conceptual commitments. Recent work by Friedman has persuasively challenged this view, revealing the roles that philosophical concerns have (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  16. Carnap's Tolerance and Friedman's Revenge.Noah Friedman-Biglin - 2015 - In Pavel Arazim & Michal Dancak (eds.), Logica Yearbook 2014. College Publications. pp. 109 -- 125.
    In this paper, I defend Rudolf Carnap's Principle of Tolerance from an accusation, due to Michael Friedman, that it is self-defeating by prejudicing any debate towards the logically stronger theory. In particular, Friedman attempts to show that Carnap's reconstruction of the debate between classicists and intuitionists over the foundations of mathematics in his book The Logical Syntax of Language, is biased towards the classical standpoint since the metalanguage he constructs to adjudicate between the rival positions is fully classical. I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  18
    Interpreting weak Kőnig's lemma in theories of nonstandard arithmetic.Bruno Dinis & Fernando Ferreira - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (1-2):114-123.
    We show how to interpret weak Kőnig's lemma in some recently defined theories of nonstandard arithmetic in all finite types. Two types of interpretations are described, with very different verifications. The celebrated conservation result of Friedman's about weak Kőnig's lemma can be proved using these interpretations. We also address some issues concerning the collecting of witnesses in herbrandized functional interpretations.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  25
    Cardinal characteristics at κ in a small u ( κ ) model.A. D. Brooke-Taylor, V. Fischer, S. D. Friedman & D. C. Montoya - 2017 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (1):37-49.
  19.  23
    Choice principles, the bar rule and autonomously iterated comprehension schemes in analysis.S. Feferman & G. Jäger - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (1):63-70.
    In [10] Friedman showed that is a conservative extension of <ε0for-sentences wherei= min, i.e.,i= 2, 3, 4 forn= 0, 1, 2 +m. Feferman [5], [7] and Tait [11], [12] reobtained this result forn= 0, 1 and even with instead of. Feferman and Sieg established in [9] the conservativeness of over <ε0for-sentences for alln. In each paper, different methods of proof have been used. In particular, Feferman and Sieg showed how to apply familiar proof-theoretical techniques by passing through languages with Skolem (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  20. The Logic of Logical Necessity.Andrew Bacon & Kit Fine - manuscript
    Prior to Kripke's seminal work on the semantics of modal logic, McKinsey offered an alternative interpretation of the necessity operator, inspired by the Bolzano-Tarski notion of logical truth. According to this interpretation, `it is necessary that A' is true just in case every sentence with the same logical form as A is true. In our paper, we investigate this interpretation of the modal operator, resolving some technical questions, and relating it to the logical (...) of modality and some views in modal metaphysics. In particular, we present an hitherto unpublished solution to problems 41 and 42 from Friedman's 102 problems, which uses a different method of proof from the solution presented in the paper of Tadeusz Prucnal. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  50
    Interpreting Friedman's View of Business.Darlene O'Leary - 2004 - Journal of Macrodynamic Analysis 4:40-52.
    I have decided to focus this discussion on the famous article by Milton Friedman, “The Social Responsibility of Business is to Increase Its Profits.” This article was originally published in 1970 and has been reproduced in many sources since then. So the article is over 30 years old. However, the perspective that Friedman promotes in this article is one that is still very much a part of discussions about business, business ethics, and ethics and economics. It seems legitimate to me (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. The ant colony as a test for scientific theories of consciousness.Daniel A. Friedman & Eirik Søvik - 2019 - Synthese (2):1-24.
    The appearance of consciousness in the universe remains one of the major mysteries unsolved by science or philosophy. Absent an agreed-upon definition of consciousness or even a convenient system to test theories of consciousness, a confusing heterogeneity of theories proliferate. In pursuit of clarifying this complicated discourse, we here interpret various frameworks for the scientific and philosophical study of consciousness through the lens of social insect evolutionary biology. To do so, we first discuss the notion of a forward test versus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  9
    The affirming flame: a poetics of meaning.Maurice S. Friedman - 1999 - Amherst, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.
    Friedman continues an old and longstanding love: a poetics of dialogue with modern literature. Such a poetics sees literature and its interpretation in terms of what philosopher Martin Buber calls "meeting" or "the between." Friedman's powerful study boldly asserts that meaning can be reached through an engagement with classic works of world literature to arrive at a more powerful and purposeful affirmation while holding the tension with what is negative.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Reflecting on incompleteness. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 56.S. Feferman, W. N. Reinhardt, V. Halbach, L. Horsten, H. Friedman & M. Sheard - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):424-428.
  25.  26
    On Friedman's problem in mathematical logic.Tadeusz Prucnal - 1978 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 7 (3):137-140.
  26.  35
    Martin Buber's Theory of Knowledge.Maurice S. Friedman - 1954 - Review of Metaphysics 8 (2):264 - 280.
    In its traditional form epistemology has always rested on the exclusive reality of the subject-object relationship. If one asks how the subject knows the object, one has in brief form the essence of theory of knowledge from Plato to Bergson; the differences between the many schools of philosophy can all be understood as variations on this theme. There are, first of all, differences in emphasis as to whether the subject or the object is the more real--as in rationalism and empiricism, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  39
    Bohm's Metaphors, Causality, and the Quantum Potential.Marcello Guarini, Causality Bohm’S. Metaphors, Steven French, Décio Krause, Michael Friedman, Ludwig Wittgenstein & Clark Glymour - 2003 - Erkenntnis 59 (1):77-95.
    David Bohm's interpretation of quantum mechanics yields a quantum potential, Q. In his early work, the effects of Q are understood in causal terms as acting through a real (quantum) field which pushes particles around. In his later work (with Basil Hiley), the causal understanding of Q appears to have been abandoned. The purpose of this paper is to understand how the use of certain metaphors leads Bohm away from a causal treatment of Q, and to evaluate the use (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  35
    Reply to Flage's On Friedman's Look.Lesley Friedman - 1993 - Hume Studies 19 (1):199-202.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reply to Flage Lesley Friedman "The chiefexercise of the memory," Hume tells us, "is not to preserve the simple ideas, but their order and position."1 On Daniel Flage's interpretation ofHume, however, it is the only exercise ofthe memory (1985a, 1985b, 1990). Flage's account can accommodate onlymemories of complex ideas; he disallows the possibility of 'preserving* a simple idea in its simplicity. Yet there is an example of a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Matter and Necessity in Aristotle's Logical, Physical and Biological Works.Robert Glenn Friedman - 1984 - Dissertation, University of Virginia
    Aristotle's doctrine of the four causes--formal, final, efficient and material--is famous. But Posterior Analytics B 11 lists "if certain things hold, it is necessary that this does" in place of a standard expression for the material cause. This cause has been dubbed the grounding cause. It has interested scholars since the Greek commentators, who simply assumed that Aristotle meant the material cause. This traditional thesis has been challenged by two views: first, that the grounding cause is a special type of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  35
    Generalizations of the Kruskal-Friedman theorems.L. Gordeev - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):157-181.
    Kruskal proved that finite trees are well-quasi-ordered by hom(e)omorphic embeddability. Friedman observed that this statement is not provable in predicative analysis. Friedman also proposed (see in [Simpson]) some stronger variants of the Kruskal theorem dealing with finite labeled trees under home(e)omorphic embeddability with a certain gap-condition, where labels are arbitrary finite ordinals from a fixed initial segment of ω. The corresponding limit statement, expressing that for all initial segments of ω these labeled trees are well-quasi-ordered, is provable in Π 1 (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  97
    Causal Connections, Universals, and Russell’s Hypothetico-Scientific Realism.Herbert Hochberg - 1994 - The Monist 77 (1):71-93.
    In the years spanning the first half of the 20th century Bertrand Russell wavered between two incompatible accounts of physical reality. On one account, physical objects were taken to be logical constructs of phenomenal entities, the immediate data of sense experience. Such a view roughly fits the familiar characterization of being a combination of “Hume plus mathematical logic.” This type of phenomenalism, in the empiricist tradition, contrasted starkly with a variant of scientific realism, including a realistic account of causal (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  17
    Causal Connections, Universals, and Russell’s Hypothetico-Scientific Realism.Herbert Hochberg - 1994 - The Monist 77 (1):71-92.
    In the years spanning the first half of the 20th century Bertrand Russell wavered between two incompatible accounts of physical reality. On one account, physical objects were taken to be logical constructs of phenomenal entities, the immediate data of sense experience. Such a view roughly fits the familiar characterization of being a combination of “Hume plus mathematical logic.” This type of phenomenalism, in the empiricist tradition, contrasted starkly with a variant of scientific realism, including a realistic account of causal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Logical form and the order of nature: Comments on Beátrice Longuenesse's Kant and the capacity to judge.Michael Friedman - 2000 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 82 (2):202-215.
  34.  64
    A Coalgebraic Perspective on Logical Interpretations.M. A. Martins, A. Madeira & L. S. Barbosa - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (4):783-825.
    In Computer Science stepwise refinement of algebraic specifications is a well-known formal methodology for rigorous program development. This paper illustrates how techniques from Algebraic Logic, in particular that of interpretation, understood as a multifunction that preserves and reflects logical consequence, capture a number of relevant transformations in the context of software design, reuse, and adaptation, difficult to deal with in classical approaches. Examples include data encapsulation and the decomposition of operations into atomic transactions. But if interpretations open such (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  30
    The Unity of the Highest Good: Kant on Systemic Justice.Shterna S. Friedman - 2022 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 3 (3):345-367.
    Kant’s concept of the highest good proportionately unites virtue and happiness—the supreme goods of, respectively, the systems of freedom and of nature. A middle path between theological and secular interpretations of Kant’s highest good is possible if we disentangle two distinct roles played by God: a causal role in promoting the real unity of the highest good, i.e., its actualization; and a conceptual role in modeling its conceptual unity. The highest good is theological in the first case, but neutral—neither directly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  65
    Dewey's logical theory: new studies and interpretations.F. Thomas Burke, D. Micah Hester & Robert B. Talisse (eds.) - 2002 - Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.
    The essays in this collection address different aspects of Dewey's philosophy of logic, from his work at the beginning of the twentieth century to the culmination of his logical thought in the 1938 volume, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Interpretations, according to Tarski.Harvey Friedman - unknown
    The notion of interpretation is absolutely fundamental to mathematical logic and the foundations of mathematics. It is also crucial for the foundations and philosophy of science - although here some crucial conditions generally need to be imposed; e.g., “the interpretation leaves the mathematical concepts unchanged”.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38.  24
    Carnap's conventionalism : logic, science, and tolerance.Noah Friedman-Biglin - 2014 - Dissertation, University of St Andrews
    In broadest terms, this thesis is concerned to answer the question of whether the view that arithmetic is analytic can be maintained consistently. Lest there be much suspense, I will conclude that it can. Those who disagree claim that accounts which defend the analyticity of arithmetic are either unable to give a satisfactory account of the foundations of mathematics due to the incompleteness theorems, or, if steps are taken to mitigate incompleteness, then the view loses the ability to account for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Why Friedman's non-monotonic reasoning defies Hempel's covering law model.M. C. W. Janssen & Y. -H. Tan - 1991 - Synthese 86 (2):255 - 284.
    In this paper we will show that Hempel's covering law model can't deal very well with explanations that are based on incomplete knowledge. In particular the symmetry thesis, which is an important aspect of the covering law model, turns out to be problematic for these explanations. We will discuss an example of an electric circuit, which clearly indicates that the symmetry of explanation and prediction does not always hold. It will be argued that an alternative logic for causal explanation is (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  41
    Hegel's Logic: An Essay in Interpretation.John Grier Hibben - 1903 - Philosophical Review 12 (3):353-357.
  41. Hegel's logic, an essay in interpretation.J. Grier Hibben - 1904 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 57:430-431.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  26
    Logical Pluralism and Paradoxical Assertions in the Philosophy of Religion.Noah Friedman-Biglin & Anand Jayprakash Vaidya - 2023 - Philosophy Compass 19 (1):e12956.
    Many authors show how useful logic can be as a tool for building theories that can account for problems in the philosophy of religion, such as paradoxical assertions. As a consequence, one's philosophy of logic is crucial as well, since it determines which logics, from the set of available and constructible logics, one can use to build a theory. In this paper, we present the relatively recent debate between logical pluralism and monism because the positions in this debate determine (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Interpreting set theory in ordinary thinking: Concept calculus.Harvey Friedman - manuscript
    STARTLING OBSERVATION. Any two natural theories S,T, known to interpret EFA, are known (with small numbers of exceptions) to have: S is interpretable in T or T is interpretable in S. The exceptions are believed to also have comparability.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  70
    A logical interpretation of meinong's principle of independence.Karel Lambert - 1982 - Topoi 1 (1-2):87-96.
  45.  21
    Friedman's Permanent Income Hypothesis as an Example of Diagnostic Reasoning.Maarten C. W. Janssen - 1992 - Economics and Philosophy 8 (1):23-46.
    Many recent developments in artificial intelligence research are relevant for traditional issues in the philosophy of science. One of the developments in AI research we want to focus on in this article is diagnostic reasoning, which we consider to be of interest for the theory of explanation in general and for an understanding of explanatory arguments in economic science in particular. Usually, explanation is primarily discussed in terms of deductive inferences in classical logic. However, in recent AI research it is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  12
    The Critically Loyal Interpreter: Oppenheim on Royce’s Philosophy of Religion.Robin Friedman - 2018 - The Pluralist 13 (3):23-44.
    Over the course of a fifty-year scholarly career, Frank M. Oppenheim, SJ, has devotedly studied and encouraged others to study the American philosopher Josiah Royce. Early in my own study of Royce, I read and learned a great deal from Oppenheim’s book Reverence for the Relations of Life. I met Oppenheim at a 2007 conference at Harvard on Royce and William James, and he encouraged my continued study. Thus, I am honored to participate in this issue of The Pluralist celebrating (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  11
    C. S. Peirce's Rhetorical Turn.Vincent Michael Colapietro - 2007 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43 (1):16-52.
    While the work of such expositors as Max H. Fisch, James J. Liszka, Lucia Santaella, Anne Friedman, and Mats Bergman has helped bring into sharp focus why Peirce took the third branch of semiotic (speculative rhetoric) to be "the highest and most living branch of logic," more needs to be done to show the extent to which the least developed branch of his theory of signs is, at once, its potentially most fruitful and important. The author of this paper thus (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48.  9
    Gordon Baker's Late Interpretation of Wittgenstein.P. M. S. Hacker - 2007 - In Guy Kahane, Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.), Wittgenstein and His Interpreters: Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 88–122.
    This chapter contains section titled: Baker's New Conception Waismann and Wittgenstein Wittgenstein on the Psychoanalytic Analogy Wittgenstein's Methodology Reconsidered Wittgenstein and Ryle 1: Categorial Confusions Wittgenstein and Ryle 2: Logical Geography Baker's Wittgenstein.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49. Dewey's Logical Theory: New Studies and Interpretations.F. Thomas Burke, D. Micah Hester & Robert B. Talisse - 2003 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 39 (2):317-323.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Gordon Baker's late interpretation of Wittgenstein.P. M. S. Hacker - 2007 - In Guy Kahane, Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.), Wittgenstein and His Interpreters: Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 88--122.
    Gordon Baker and I had been colleagues at St John’s for almost ten years when we resolved, in 1976, to undertake the task of writing a commentary on Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations. We had been talking about Wittgenstein since 1969, and when we cooperated in writing a long critical notice on the Philosophical Grammar in 1975, we found that working together was mutually instructive, intellectually stimulating and great fun. We thought that we still had much to say about Wittgenstein’s philosophy, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000