Results for 'Aristotle NE 3.5'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3.5, 1113b7-8 and Free Choice.Susanne Bobzien - 2014 - In R. Salles P. Destree (ed.), What is up to us? Studies on Causality and Responsibility in Ancient Philosophy. Academia Verlag.
    ABSTRACT: This is a short companion piece to my ‘Found in Translation – Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics III.5 1113b7-8 and its Reception’ in which I examine in close textual analysis the philosophical question whether these two lines from the Nicomachean Ethics provide any evidence that Aristotle discussed free choice – as is not infrequently assumed. The result is that they do not, and that the claim that they do tends to be based on a mistranslation of the Greek. (There (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2. Why There Are No Fresh Starts in Metaphysics Epsilon or Nicomachean Ethics III 5.Tim O'Keefe - manuscript
    Metaphysics Epsilon 2-3 and Nicomachean Ethics III 5 (1114b3-25) are often cited in favor of indeterminist interpretations of Aristotle. In Metaphysics Epsilon Aristotle denies that the coincidental has an aitia, and some (e.g., Sorabji) take this as a denial that coincidences have causes. In NE III 5 Aristotle says a person's actions and character must have their origin (archê) in the agent for him to be responsible for them. From this, some conclude that Aristotle thinks a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Choice and Moral Responsibility in Nichomachean Ethics III 1–5.Susanne Bobzien - 2014 - In Ronald Polansky (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. New York, New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 81-109.
    ABSTRACT: This paper serves two purposes: (i) it can be used by students as an introduction to chapters 1-5 of book iii of the NE; (ii) it suggests an answer to the unresolved question what overall objective this section of the NE has. The paper focuses primarily on Aristotle’s theory of what makes us responsible for our actions and character. After some preliminary observations about praise, blame and responsibility (Section 2), it sets out in detail how all the key (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  67
    Aristotle, De Anima III.3-5.Seth Benardete - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (4):611 - 622.
    The physicist defines anger in terms of heart, blood, and heat; the dialectician says it is the desire to inflict pain in retaliation. Both give fairly sure signs for its recognition; but neither can show why these signs must go together and in what they can cohere. Aristotelian physics is presumably a way to avoid such a split, and whatever defects his account of perception or intellection suffers from cannot be traced to it. Phantasia, however, seems to be dialectically distinguished (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. Found in Translation: Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3.5, 1113b7-8 and its Reception.Susanne Bobzien - 2013 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 45:103-148.
    ABSTRACT: This paper is distinctly odd. It demonstrates what happens when an analytical philosopher and historian of philosophy tries their hand at the topic of reception. For a novice to this genre, it seemed advisable to start small. Rather than researching the reception of an author, book, chapter, section or paragraph, the focus of the paper is on one sentence: Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3.5, 1113b7-8. This sentence has markedly shaped scholarly and general opinion alike with regard to Aristotle’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  7
    On Aristotle's "On the soul 1.3-5".John Philoponus - 2006 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Edited by van der Eijk, J. Ph & Aristotle.
    In chapter 5, Philoponus endorses Aristotle's rejection of the idea that the soul is particles and of Empedocles's idea that the soul must be made of all four elements in order to know what is made of the same elements."--Jacket.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  77
    Choice and Virtue in the Nicomachean Ethics.Alfred R. Mele - 1981 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 19 (4):405-423.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content: Choice and Virtue in the Nicomachean Ethics ALFRED R. MELE COM~rNTATORS ON THr Nicomachean Ethics (NE) have long been laboring under the influence of a serious misunderstanding of one of the key terms in Aristotle's moral philosophy and theory of action. This term is prohairesis (choice), the importance of which is indicated by Aristotle's assertions that choice is the proximate efficient cause of action (NE 6. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8. Aristotle contra Plato on the Voluntariness of Vice: The Arguments of Nicomachean Ethics 3.5.Rachana Kamtekar - 2019 - Phronesis 64 (1):57-83.
  9. Aporia 3-5.Frans De Haas - 2009 - In Michel Crubellier & André Laks (eds.), Aristotle's Metaphysics Beta: Symposium Aristotelicum. New York: Oxford University Press UK.
  10.  5
    Monism in Aristotle’s Metaphysics I.3–5.Thomas Kjeller Johansen - unknown
    Scholars have often seen Parmenides as entirely opposed to earlier materialistic philosophy. In this paper I argue that what is more striking in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Book I is the degree of continuity that he sees between Parmenides and the material monists. I explore this coupling of Parmenides with the material monists to understand better what he takes to be distinctive and problematic with Parmenides’ monism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  15
    On Aristotle’s Physics 5. [REVIEW]Leo J. Elders - 1997 - Review of Metaphysics 51 (2):444-445.
    Book 5 stands between the first four books of the Physics and Books 6, 7, and 8, which are traditionally called the treatise On motion. Simplicius, however, attaches it to the first four books on the principles of physical reality, describing it as a supplement to Book 3. David Ross, in his monumental Aristotle’s Physics prefers to consider Books 5, 6, and 8 a coherent group of pragmateiai on motion, while 7 is a comparatively isolated book, a view shared (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  88
    Colloquium 5: Aristotle’s Account of Agency in Physics III 3.Ursula Coope - 2004 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 20 (1):201-227.
  13. Aquinas as a Commentator on De Anima 3.5.James Th Martin - 1993 - The Thomist 57 (4):621-640.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:AQUINAS AS A COMMENTATOR ON DE ANIMA 3.5 JAMES T. H. MARTIN St. John's University Jamaica, New York DOES ST. THOMAS AQUINAS in his commentary on De Anima 3.5 provide an acceptable gloss on Aristotle 's cryptic remarks about active mind? That is, can one accept.that what Aquinas says about active mind is what Aristotle meant but for some reason did not say? Many modern commentators, among (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  9
    3. Aristotle on Eudaimonia (I 1–3 und 5–6).John L. Ackrill - 2006 - In Otfried Höffe (ed.), Aristoteles: Nikomachische Ethik. Boston: Akademie Verlag. pp. 39-62.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  5
    On Aristotle's "On the Soul 3.1-5". Simplicius & Of Simplicius - 2000 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Edited by H. J. Blumenthal.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  52
    Aristotle on How Pleasure Perfects Activity (Nicomachean Ethics x.5 1175a29-b14): The Optimising-View.David Machek - 2022 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 104 (3):448-467.
    This article offers a new interpretation of Aristotle’s ambiguous and much-discussed claim that pleasure perfects activity. This interpretation provides an alternative to the two main competing readings of this claim in the scholarship: the addition-view, which envisages the perfection conferred by pleasure as an extra perfection beyond the perfection of activity itself; and the identity-view, according to which pleasure just is the perfect activity itself. The proposed interpretation departs from both these views in rejecting their assumption that pleasure cannot (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  5
    On Aristotle Physics 5.J. O. Simplicius, Peter Urmson & Lautner - 1997 - Bristol Classical Press.
    "Aristotle's Physics Book 3 covers two subjects: the definition of change and the finitude of the universe. Change, which enters into the very definition of nature as an internal source of change, receives two definitions in chapters 1 and 2, as involving the actualization of the potential or of the changeable. Alexander of Aphrodisias is reported as thinking that the second version is designed to show that Book 3, like Book 5, means to disqualify change in relations from being (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Aristotle devotes a significant portion of the Nicomachean Ethics and the Eudemian Ethics to the topic of virtue of character (ethike arete). In each workhe precedes his detailed treatment of the particular virtues of char-acter (courage, temperance, liberality, and so on) with a general account of ethical virtue (NE II–III. 5; EE II; cf. MM I. 5–19). The general account concludes, in both cases, with an extended discussion of voluntariness (to hekousion) and related notions (NE III. 1–5; EE II. 6–11; cf. MM I. 9–19). In order to understand Aristotle's views on voluntariness, we must first understand why he thinks that an account of the voluntary belongs in a treatise on virtue of character. [REVIEW]Susan Sauvé Meyer - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  14
    What can Maimonides' understanding of the shamefulness of touch teach us about Aristotle's NE III.10, 1118b1–3?Mor Segev - 2023 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31 (3):405-420.
    In NE III.10, 1118b1–3, Aristotle says that the “most shared of the senses is that according to which intemperance [comes about], and it would seem justifiably to be shameful, because it inheres [in us] not insofar as we are human beings, but insofar as we are animals”. This statement appears to describe the sense of touch as shameful. This may seem like a strange position for Aristotle to hold, since elsewhere he describes human touch as the most accurate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  36
    PS.-ARISTOTLE, DE MUNDO_- J.C. Thom (ed.) Cosmic Order and Divine Power. Pseudo-Aristotle, _On the Cosmos. (SAPERE 23.) Pp. x + 230. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2014. Cased, €49. ISBN: 978-3-16-152809-5. [REVIEW]Pavel Gregoric - 2016 - The Classical Review 66 (1):68-70.
  21.  26
    Hylémorphisme et causalité des intelligibles.Riccardo Chiaradonna - 2008 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 86 (3):379-397.
    Résumé — En Enn., VI, 3 [44], 5, Plotin fait usage de doctrines péripatéticiennes concernant la substance, l’inhérence et la prédication. Ces doctrines correspondent de manière frappante à l’interprétation anti-extensionaliste de la substance physique développée par Alexandre d’Aphrodise contre les thèses des commentateurs plus anciens . Le parallèle entre Plotin et Alexandre ne doit cependant pas conduire à penser que Plotin se borne à suivre les thèses du commentateur, et que leurs doctrines soient donc identiques. Plotin vise plutôt à transposer (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  33
    Aristotle on Incidental Causes and Teleological Determinism: Resolving The Puzzles of Metaphysics E. 3.Christos Y. Panayides - 2012 - Journal of Philosophical Research 37:25-50.
    In Metaphysics E. 3. 1027a29–30 Aristotle states that there are some causes, the incidental ones, that are generable and destructible but they have no coming to be. Furthermore, he asserts that if we deny this thesis, then we will have to give into determinism . There are three persistent puzzles surrounding this chapter. First, what does it mean to say that a cause is generable and destructible but it has no coming to be? Second, what exactly is the connection (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  12
    From Aristotle to Freud: Terence Cave's Recognitions and the subjective turn Terence Cave, Recognitions: A Study in Poetics . xii + 5 3 0 pp. [REVIEW]Christopher Butler - 1990 - Paragraph 13 (3):326-334.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  23
    Aristotle on the Cause of Unity: the Argument of Metaphysics H.3–6.Christian Pfeiffer - forthcoming - Phronesis:1-35.
    I argue that Metaphysics H.6 is not an isolated chapter but the conclusion of an argument begun in H.3. This view will provide further and better arguments for the following view about long-standing interpretative debates: first, Aristotle provides a substantive account of the unity of the composite substance (although he also briefly addresses the unity of the form); second, neither Aristotle’s conception of matter nor his account of form changes between H.1–5 and H.6; and third, H does not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Aristotle's Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.Victor Caston - 1999 - Phronesis 44 (3):199-227.
    In "De anima" 3.5, Aristotle argues for the existence of a second intellect, the so-called "Agent Intellect." The logical structure of his argument turns on a distinction between different types of soul, rather than different faculties within a given soul; and the attributes he assigns to the second species make it clear that his concern here -- as at the climax of his other great works, such as the "Metaphysics," the "Nicomachean" and the "Eudemian Ethics" -- is the difference (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  26.  24
    Colloquium 3 Aristotle on the Voluntariness of Vice.Jay R. Elliott - 2021 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 36 (1):65-88.
    In Nicomachean Ethics III.5, Aristotle argues that virtue and vice are “up to us and voluntary.” Readers have long struggled to make sense of Aristotle’s arguments in this chapter and to explain how they cohere with the rest of his ethical project. Among the most influential lines of complaint is that the argument of III.5 appears to contradict his emphasis elsewhere on the power of upbringing to shape character, beginning in childhood. Scholars have developed two main interpretive approaches (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Reason in Action in Aristotle: A Reading of EE V.12/NE VI.12.Juan S. Piñeros Glasscock - 2019 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 57 (3):391-417.
    I present a reading of EE 5.12/NE 6.12 according to which Aristotle argues for an executive account of φρόνησις (practical wisdom) to show why it is useful to possess this virtue. On this account, the practically wise person's actions are expressive of his knowledge of the fine, a knowledge that only the practically wise person has. This is why he must not only be a good deliberator, but also cunning (δεινότης), able to execute his actions well. An important consequence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  10
    5. Aristotelian Rhythm in Rome – part 3.Pascal Michon - forthcoming - Rhuthmos.
    Previous chapter Rhythm as Prolongation of Breath – Cicero's De oratore Then Cicero comes back to Aristotle's naturalistic definition of the period as “that which can be rounded forth in one breath” and Plato's view which he abruptly re-introduces by praising the order of the universe and tying the functioning of language with that of nature. In oratory, rhythm must follow the compass of the breath, “for the stoppage of the breath, and the confined play of the lungs, - (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  7
    Aristote et la question du monde: essai sur le contexte cosmologique et anthropologique de l'ontologie.Rémi Brague - 1988 - Paris: Presses universitaires de France.
    Plusieurs aspects de la métaphysique, de la physique, de l'éthique et de la psychologie d’Aristote peuvent s'interpréter comme des affleurements d'un concept non-thématisé, celui d'être-dans-le-monde (l'in-der-welt-sein de heidegger). L’ensemble de la pensée grecque classique, même si elle était fascinée par l'ordre du cosmos, ne s'est guère demande ce que signifiait "être-dans-le-monde". L’expérience de la facticité, qui est un des traits fondamentaux de celle-ci, est ce qui permet à Aristote dans le protreptique, de justifier la vie philosophique ; mais il conçoit (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Nous in Aristotle's De Anima.Caleb Murray Cohoe - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (9):594-604.
    I lay out and examine two sharply conflicting interpretations of Aristotle's claims about nous in the De Anima (DA). On the human separability approach, Aristotle is taken to have identified reasons for thinking that the intellect can, in some way, exist on its own. On the naturalist approach, the soul, including intellectual soul, is inseparable from the body of which it is the form. I discuss how proponents of each approach deal with the key texts from the DA, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  9
    Refining the Material Substance: Aristotle’s Program in Metaphysics H1-5.Fabián Mié - 2018 - Síntesis Revista de Filosofía 1 (2):54.
    En _Metaph_. Z17, Aristóteles toma un nuevo punto de partida (1041a6) en su discusión sobre la sustancia: la forma sustancial es principio y causa (1041a6-10, 1041b8), mientras que la mate­ria es un elemento (1041b31) de las sustancias mate­riales. Además, un compromiso de Aristóteles, quizá no totalmente acla­rado en Z17, es que las sustancias materiales son todos unificados (1041b11-12). Éstas son dos tesis centrales de Z17, cuya aparente ausencia en el resu­men de H1 (1042a3-23) ha despertado dudas entre los co­menta­do­res acerca (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  20
    Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life by Sylvia Berryman.Elizabeth C. Shaw & Staff - 2020 - Review of Metaphysics 74 (2):381-383.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life by Sylvia BerrymanElizabeth C. Shaw and Staff*BERRYMAN, Sylvia. Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019. vii + 220 pp. Cloth, $70.00—Berryman’s goals in Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life are threefold: to establish that Aristotle practiced what contemporary philosophers call metaethics; to refute the idea that Aristotle (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Aristotle’s Critique of Timaean Psychology.Jason W. Carter - 2017 - Rhizomata 5 (1):51-78.
    Of all the criticisms that Aristotle gives of his predecessors’ theories of soul in De anima I.3–5, none seems more unmotivated than the ones directed against the world soul of Plato’s Timaeus. Against the current scholarly consensus, I claim that the status of Aristotle’s criticisms is philosophical rather than eristical, and that they provide important philosophical reasons, independent of Phys. VIII.10 and Metaph. Λ.6, for believing that νοῦς is without spatial extension, and that its thinking is not a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. The Nicomachean Ethics is framed by a beginning (NEI. 1–3) and an ending (NE X. 9) which, in rather different ways, communicate a single message: politics is the activity and branch of study that deals with the subject matter of the work. For us, ethics and politics signify two distinct, if overlapping, spheres. For Aristotle, there is just one sphere–politics–conceived in ethical terms. This startling truth is generally downplayed (if not totally ignored) in many presenta-tions of the Nicomachean ... [REVIEW]Malcolm Schofield - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 305.
  35.  60
    Aristotle on Circular Proof.Marko Malink - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (3):215-248.
    In Posterior Analytics 1.3, Aristotle advances three arguments against circular proof. The third argument relies on his discussion of circular proof in Prior Analytics 2.5. This is problematic because the two chapters seem to deal with two rather disparate conceptions of circular proof. In Posterior Analytics 1.3, Aristotle gives a purely propositional account of circular proof, whereas in Prior Analytics 2.5 he gives a more complex, syllogistic account. My aim is to show that these problems can be solved, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36.  5
    “If There Were an Eye on the Back of the Heaven…” (Plotinus, Ennead 4.5,3 and 8).Andrei Cornea - 2007 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 63 (3):459-472.
    Notre article analyse deux passages curieux du traité Sur les difficultés relatives à l’âme III. De la vision (Enn. IV.5,3 et 8), dans lesquels Plotin paraît concevoir la possibilité d’un autre univers, situé en dehors du nôtre. Or, cet autre univers doit rester inconnu pour nous à jamais, quand bien même il y aurait un « oeil placé sur le dos du Ciel » qui voudrait le voir. En outre, nous ne saurons même pas décider si cet univers existe ou (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Machine generated contents note: Introduction1. The pre-socratic philosophers: Sixth and fifth centuries B.c.E. Thales / anaximander / anaximenes / Pythagoras / xenophanes / Heraclitus / parmenides / Zeno / empedocles / anaxagoras / leucippus and democritus 2. the athenian period: Fifth and fourth centuries B.c.E. The sophists: Protagoras, gorgias, thrasymachus, callicles and critias / socrates / Plato / Aristotle 3. the hellenistic and Roman periods: Fourth century B.c.E through fourth century C.e. Epicureanism / stoicism / skepticism / neoPlatonism 4. medieval and renaissance philosophy: Fifth through fifteenth centuries saint Augustine / the encyclopediasts / John scotus eriugena / saint Anselm / muslim and jewish philosophies: Averroës, Maimonides / the problem of faith and reason / the problem of the universals / saint Thomas Aquinas / William of ockham / renaissance philosophers 5. continental rationalism and british empiricism: The seventeenth and eighteenth centuries Descartes. [REVIEW]Farewell to the Twentieth Century: Nussbaum Glossary of Philosophical Terms Selected Bibliography Index - 2009 - In Donald Palmer (ed.), Looking at philosophy: the unbearable heaviness of philosophy made lighter. New York: McGraw-Hill.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  33
    Dunaton as ‘Capable’ versus ‘Possible’ in Aristotle’s Metaphysics ix 3-4.Francisco Gonzalez - 2022 - Ancient Philosophy 42 (2):453-470.
    While Aristotle’s explicit focus in Metaphysics Theta 1-5 is dunamis in the sense of the ‘capability’ a thing has to originate change in something else or in itself qua other, practically all translators, when they arrive at chapter four, switch to ‘possible’ and ‘impossible’ as translations of dunaton and adunaton. Such a switch is neither defensible nor necessary and the relevance of Theta 4 is understood only without it.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Machine generated contents note: Introduction1. The pre-socratic philosophers: Sixth and fifth centuries B.c.E. Thales / anaximander / anaximenes / Pythagoras / xenophanes / Heraclitus / parmenides / Zeno / empedocles / anaxagoras / leucippus and democritus 2. the athenian period: Fifth and fourth centuries B.c.E. The sophists: Protagoras, gorgias, thrasymachus, callicles and critias / socrates / Plato / Aristotle 3. the hellenistic and Roman periods: Fourth century B.c.E through fourth century C.e. Epicureanism / stoicism / skepticism / neoPlatonism 4. medieval and renaissance philosophy: Fifth through fifteenth centuries saint Augustine / the encyclopediasts / John scotus eriugena / saint Anselm / muslim and jewish philosophies: Averroës, Maimonides / the problem of faith and reason / the problem of the universals / saint Thomas Aquinas / William of ockham / renaissance philosophers 5. continental rationalism and british empiricism: The seventeenth and eighteenth centuries Descartes. [REVIEW]Farewell to the Twentieth Century: Nussbaum Glossary of Philosophical Terms Selected Bibliography Index - 2009 - In Donald Palmer (ed.), Looking at philosophy: the unbearable heaviness of philosophy made lighter. New York: McGraw-Hill.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Machine generated contents note: Introduction1. The pre-socratic philosophers: Sixth and fifth centuries B.c.E. Thales / anaximander / anaximenes / Pythagoras / xenophanes / Heraclitus / parmenides / Zeno / empedocles / anaxagoras / leucippus and democritus 2. the athenian period: Fifth and fourth centuries B.c.E. The sophists: Protagoras, gorgias, thrasymachus, callicles and critias / socrates / Plato / Aristotle 3. the hellenistic and Roman periods: Fourth century B.c.E through fourth century C.e. Epicureanism / stoicism / skepticism / neoPlatonism 4. medieval and renaissance philosophy: Fifth through fifteenth centuries saint Augustine / the encyclopediasts / John scotus eriugena / saint Anselm / muslim and jewish philosophies: Averroës, Maimonides / the problem of faith and reason / the problem of the universals / saint Thomas Aquinas / William of ockham / renaissance philosophers 5. continental rationalism and british empiricism: The seventeenth and eighteenth centuries Descartes. [REVIEW]Farewell to the Twentieth Century: Nussbaum Glossary of Philosophical Terms Selected Bibliography Index - 2009 - In Donald Palmer (ed.), Looking at philosophy: the unbearable heaviness of philosophy made lighter. New York: McGraw-Hill.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Machine generated contents note: Introduction1. The pre-socratic philosophers: Sixth and fifth centuries B.c.E. Thales / anaximander / anaximenes / Pythagoras / xenophanes / Heraclitus / parmenides / Zeno / empedocles / anaxagoras / leucippus and democritus 2. the athenian period: Fifth and fourth centuries B.c.E. The sophists: Protagoras, gorgias, thrasymachus, callicles and critias / socrates / Plato / Aristotle 3. the hellenistic and Roman periods: Fourth century B.c.E through fourth century C.e. Epicureanism / stoicism / skepticism / neoPlatonism 4. medieval and renaissance philosophy: Fifth through fifteenth centuries saint Augustine / the encyclopediasts / John scotus eriugena / saint Anselm / muslim and jewish philosophies: Averroës, Maimonides / the problem of faith and reason / the problem of the universals / saint Thomas Aquinas / William of ockham / renaissance philosophers 5. continental rationalism and british empiricism: The seventeenth and eighteenth centuries Descartes. [REVIEW]Farewell to the Twentieth Century: Nussbaum Glossary of Philosophical Terms Selected Bibliography Index - 2009 - In Donald Palmer (ed.), Looking at philosophy: the unbearable heaviness of philosophy made lighter. New York: McGraw-Hill.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Competing ways of life and ring-composition in NE x 6-8.Thornton Lockwood - 2014 - In Ronald Polansky (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. New York, New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 350-369.
    The closing chapters of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics x are regularly described as “puzzling,” “extremely abrupt,” “awkward,” or “surprising” to readers. Whereas the previous nine books described—sometimes in lavish detail—the multifold ethical virtues of an embodied person situated within communities of family, friends, and fellow-citizens, NE x 6-8 extol the rarified, god-like and solitary existence of a sophos or sage (1179a32). The ethical virtues that take up approximately the first half of the Ethics describe moral exempla who experience fear fighting (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43. Pt. 1. ancient philosophy and faith, from athens to jerusalem: Lecture 1. introductIon to the problems and scope of philosophy ; lecture 2. the old testament, guest lecture / by Robert Oden ; lecture 3. the gospels of mark and Matthew, guest lecture / by Elizabeth mcnamer ; lecture 4. Paul, his world, guest lecture / by Elizabeth mcnamer ; lecture 5. presocratics, Ionian speculaton and eleatic metaphysics ; lecture 6. republic I, justice, power, and knowledge ; lecture 7. republic II-v, Paul and city ; lecture 8. republic VI-x, the architecture of reality ; lecture 9. Aristotle's metaphysical views ; lecture 10. Aristotle's politics, the golden mean and just rule, guest lecture. [REVIEW]Dennis Dalton, the stoic ideal lecture 11Marcus Aurelius' Meditations & lecture 12Augustine'S. City of God - 2000 - In Darren Staloff, Louis Markos, Jeremy duQuesnay Adams, Phillip Cary, Dennis Dalton, Alan Charles Kors, Jeremy Shearmur, Robert C. Solomon, Robert Kane, Kathleen Marie Higgins, Mark W. Risjord & Douglas Kellner (eds.), Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition. Teaching Co..
  44. Aristotle on Co-causes of One’s Dispositions.Filip Grgić - 2017 - Elenchos 38 (1-2):107-126.
    In this paper I offer a close reading of Aristotle’s argument in the Nicomachean Ethics 3.5.1114a31–b25 and try to show that despite considerable interpretive difficulties, some clear structure can nevertheless be discerned. While Aristotle’s main concern in this passage is to refute the so-called asymmetry thesis – the thesis that virtue is voluntary, but vice is not – there is much more in it than just a dialectical encounter. Aristotle wants to respond to a more general objection, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  13
    Passive Potentiality in the Physical Realm: Plotinus' Critique of Aristotle in Enneads II 5 [25].Cinzia Arruzza - 2011 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (1):24-57.
    This article analyzes the status of passive potentiality of prime matter and sensible objects in Plotinus' Enneads. In particular, it will focus on Enneads II 5 [25] and confront it with other treatises, specifically Enneads III 6 [26]; II 6 [17]; VI 2 [43] and VI 3 [44]. It aims at offering a new interpretation of treatise 25 and at proposing a reconstruction of Plotinus' notion of change in the sensible realm that illustrates both his critique of Aristotle's notion (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Aristotle’s Concept of Mind by Erick Raphael Jiménez. [REVIEW]Noell Birondo - 2019 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 57 (1):162-163.
    In this ambitious first book, Erick Raphael Jiménez argues that a good model for understanding Aristotle’s concept of mind (nous) lies in Aristotle’s account of the perception of time. This “time-perception model” of mind and its activity, thinking, bridges a gap between Jiménez’s unorthodox readings of Aristotelian mind and its objects. The book will attract the interest of specialists in Aristotle’s psychology, as well as other scholars interested in Aristotle’s concept of mind and its influence, for (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Aristotle on Actions from Lack of Control.Jozef Müller - 2015 - Philosophers' Imprint 15.
    The paper defends three claims about Aristotle’s theory of uncontrolled actions (akrasia) in NE 7.3. First, I argue that the first part of NE 7.3 contains the description of the overall state of mind of the agent while she acts without control. Aristotle’s solution to the problem of uncontrolled action lies in the analogy between the uncontrolled agent and people who are drunk, mad, or asleep. This analogy is interpreted as meaning that the uncontrolled agent, while acting without (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  48.  96
    Aristotle on the common sense.Pavel Gregoric - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    I. The framework. 1, Aristotle's project and methods. 2, The perceptual capacity of the soul. 3, The sensory apparatus. 4, The common sense and the related capacities -- II. The terminology. 1, Overlooked occurrences of the phrase 'common sense'. 2, De anima III.1 425a27. 3, De partibus animalium IV.10 686a31. 4, De memoria et reminiscentia 1 450a10. 5, De anima III.7 431b5. 6, Conclusions on the terminology -- III. Functions of the common sense. 1, Simultaneous perception and cross-modal binding. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  49. Aristotle on Necessity, Chance and Explanation.Lindsay Judson - 1986 - Dissertation, University of Oxford (United Kingdom)
    Available from UMI in association with The British Library. Requires signed TDF. ; Aristotle endorses a very striking doctrine connecting necessity with what seems to be a non-modal notion--that of 'being or happening always'. He also forges a connection between the idea of 'happening by chance' and 'happening neither always nor for the most part'. These two connections form the subject of this essay. My guiding aim is to provide an account of what the 'always/necessary' doctrine involves and of (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  21
    The constitution of the athenians in italian and in English - Rhodes aristotele: Costituzione degli ateniesi. Translated by A. zambrini and T. gargiulo. Pp. lii + 402. Rome / Milan: Fondazione Lorenzo valla / arnoldo Mondadori, 2016. Cased, €35. Isbn: 978-88-04-67169-5. - Rhodes the athenian constitution written in the school of Aristotle. Pp. XII + 441, maps. Liverpool: Liverpool university press, 2017. Paper, £19.99 . Isbn: 978-1-78694-837-3. [REVIEW]Alberto Esu - 2018 - The Classical Review 68 (2):366-369.
1 — 50 / 1000