Contents
53 found
Order:
1 — 50 / 53
  1. Aristotle on Similarity, Pleasure, and the Justification of our Choices of Friends.Vakirtzis Andreas - manuscript
  2. Protrepticus. Aristotle, Monte Ransome Johnson & D. S. Hutchinson - manuscript
    A new translation and edition of Aristotle's Protrepticus (with critical comments on the fragments) -/- Welcome -/- The Protrepticus was an early work of Aristotle, written while he was still a member of Plato's Academy, but it soon became one of the most famous works in the whole history of philosophy. Unfortunately it was not directly copied in the middle ages and so did not survive in its own manuscript tradition. But substantial fragments of it have been preserved in several (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  3. Aristotle and the pain of animals: Nicomachean Ethics 1154b7–9.Wei Cheng - 2023 - Classical Quarterly (1):1-8.
    This paper explains the motivation behind Aristotle’s appeal in Nicomachean Ethics 1154b7–9 to the physiologoi, who notoriously declare that animals are constantly in pain. It argues that the physiologoi are neither the critical target of this chapter nor invoked to verify Aristotle’s commitment to the imperfection of the human condition. Rather, despite doctrinal disagreement, they help Aristotle develop a naturalistic story about how ordinary people easily indulge in sensory pleasures.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. On Becoming Fearful Quickly: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle's Somatic Model of Socratean Akrasia.Brian Andrew Lightbody - 2023 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):134-161.
    The Protagoras is the touchstone of Socrates’ moral intellectualist stance. The position in a nutshell stipulates that the proper reevaluation of a desire is enough to neutralize it.[1] The implication of this position is that akrasia or weakness of will is not the result of desire (or fear for that matter) overpowering reason but is due to ignorance. -/- Socrates’ eliminativist position on weakness of will, however, flies in the face of the common-sense experience regarding akratic action and thus Aristotle (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Review of Marta Jimenez, Aristotle on Shame and Learning to Be Good.Howard Curzer - 2022 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.
  6. Thought and Imagination: Aristotle’s Dual Process Psychology of Action.Jessica Moss - 2022 - In Caleb M. Cohoe (ed.), Aristotle's on the Soul: A Critical Guide. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. pp. 247-264.
    Aristotle's De Anima discusses the psychological causes of what he calls locomotion – i.e, roughly, purpose-driven behavior. One cause is desire. The other is cognition, which falls into two kinds: thought (nous) and imagination (phantasia). Aristotle’s discussion is dense and confusing, but I argue that we can extract from it an account that is coherent, compelling, and that in many ways closely anticipates modern psychological theories, in particular Dual Processing theory. Animals and humans are driven to pursue objects that attract (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Aristotle's Empiricism.Marc Gasser-Wingate - 2021 - Oxford University Press.
    Aristotle is famous for thinking that all our knowledge comes from perception. But it's not immediately clear what this view is meant to entail. It's not clear, for instance, what perception is supposed to contribute to the more advanced forms of knowledge that derive from it. Nor is it clear how we should understand the nature of its contribution—what it might mean to say that these more advanced forms of knowledge are "derived from" or "based on" what we perceive. Aristotle (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Review of Marta Jimenez, Aristotle on Shame and Learning to Be Good. [REVIEW]Duane Long - 2021 - Bryn Mawr Classical Review 202106.
  9. Emoções quotidianas e emoções éticas em Aristóteles e Heidegger.Hélder Telo - 2020 - Filosofia Unisinos 21 (2):218-227.
    This article studies an aspect of the relation between emotions and ethics that is usually neglected in the recent debate on moral emotions. By focusing on the contributions of common or everyday emotions to the development of moral behaviours and attitudes, the debate loses sight of the emotional side of the ethical attitude and the way it involves different, specifically ethical emotions. In contrast, such emotions play an important role in Aristotle’s and Heidegger’s thought. As will be shown, both authors (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Aristotle on the Good Man’s Desire for Pleasant Friends.Andreas Vakirtzis - 2018 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 12 (2):74-88.
  11. The characterization of the sphere of temperance in EN III.10.Bernardo César Diniz Athayde Vasconcelos - 2018 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 24:207-227.
    Our article deals with Aristotle’s account of the sphere of temperance in the Nicomachean Ethics. The goal is to provide a detailed analysis of NE III.10 in order to identify the difficulties this chapter presents us with and to introduce and discuss the interpretations set forth by the secondary literature. Of special interest to us are Aristotle’s intense dialogue with Plato; the difficulty in understanding touch as the most common of the senses and Aristotle’s severe judgment of the pleasures of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. The Pleasures of Reason in Plato, Aristotle, and the Hellenistic Hedonists, written by James Warren. [REVIEW]Emily Austin - 2017 - Polis 34 (1):168-171.
  13. Eudaimonia and Neltiliztli: Aristotle and the Aztecs on the Good Life.Lynn Sebastian Purcell - 2017 - APA Newsletter on Hispanic/Latino Issues in Philosophy 16 (2):10-21.
    This essay takes a first step in comparative ethics by looking to Aristotle and the Aztec's conceptions of the good life. It argues that the Aztec conception of a rooted life, neltiliztli, functions for ethical purposes in a way that is like Aristotle's eudaimonia. To develop this claim, it not only shows just in what their conceptions of the good consist, but also in what way the Aztecs conceived of the virtues (in qualli, in yectli).
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Prazer, dor e a virtude da temperança na Ética Nicomaquéia.Bernardo César Diniz Athayde Vasconcelos - 2017 - Dissertation, Ufmg, Brazil
  15. The Limits of Eudaimonia in the Nicomachean Ethics.Schwartz Daniel - 2016 - Journal of Greco-Roman Studies 55 (3):35-52.
    In Book I of his Nicomachean Ethics (NE), Aristotle defines happiness, or eudaimonia, in accordance with an argument he makes regarding the distinctive function of human beings. In this paper, I argue that, despite this argument, there are moments in the NE where Aristotle appeals to elements of happiness that don’t follow from the function argument itself. The place of these elements in Aristotle’s account of happiness should, therefore, be a matter of perplexity. For, how can Aristotle appeal to elements (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Notes on Nicomachean Ethics 1173 a 2–5.Grönroos Gösta - 2016 - Classical Quarterly 66 (2):484–490.
    In Nicomachean Ethics (= Eth. Nic.) 10.2, Aristotle addresses Eudoxus’ argument that pleasure is the chief good in his characteristically dialectical manner. The argument is that pleasure is the chief good, since all creatures, rational (ἔλλογα) and non-rational (ἄλογα) alike, are perceived to aim at pleasure (1172b9–11).1 At 1172b35–1173a5, Aristotle turns to an objection against Eudoxus’ argument. For some object (οἱ δ᾽ἐνιστάμενοι) to the argument by questioning one of its premisses, namely that what all creatures aim at is the good (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. What Aristotelian Decisions Cannot Be.Jozef Müller - 2016 - Ancient Philosophy 36 (1):173-195.
    I argue that Aristotelian decisions (προαιρέσεις) cannot be conceived of as based solely on wish (βούλησις) and deliberation (βούλευσις), as the standard picture (most influentially argued for in Anscombe's "Thought and Action in Aristotle", in R. Bambrough ed. New Essays on Plato and Aristotle. London: Routledge, 1965) suggests. Although some features of the standard view are correct (such as that decisions have essential connection to deliberation and that wish always plays a crucial role in the formation of a decision), Aristotelian (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. Aristotle on “Steering the Young by Pleasure and Pain”.Marta Jimenez - 2015 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 29 (2):137-164.
    At least since Burnyeat’s “Aristotle on Learning to Be Good,” one of the most popular ways of explaining moral development in Aristotle is by appealing to mechanisms of pleasure and pain. Aristotle himself suggests this kind of explanation when he says that “in educating the young we steer them by the rudders of pleasure and pain” (Nicomachean Ethics X.1, 1172a21). However, I argue that, contrary to the dominant view, Aristotle’s view on moral development in the Nicomachean Ethics is not mainly (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  19. Aristotle on Actions from Lack of Control.Jozef Müller - 2015 - Philosophers' Imprint 15.
    The paper defends three claims about Aristotle’s theory of uncontrolled actions (akrasia) in NE 7.3. First, I argue that the first part of NE 7.3 contains the description of the overall state of mind of the agent while she acts without control. Aristotle’s solution to the problem of uncontrolled action lies in the analogy between the uncontrolled agent and people who are drunk, mad, or asleep. This analogy is interpreted as meaning that the uncontrolled agent, while acting without control, is (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20. Warren, The Pleasures of Reason in Plato, Aristotle, and the Hellenistic Hedonists. [REVIEW]Tim O'Keefe - 2015 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 1.
  21. Mimesis, Friendship, and Moral Development in Aristotle’s Ethics.Andreas Vakirtzis - 2015 - Rhizomata 3 (2):125-142.
    The significance of imitation for moral development during childhood, in Aristotle’s ethics, has been recognized and studied. However, what role does imitation play in the morally mature agent’s character development? In this paper, I argue that moral development is possible for the advanced moral agent, when she imitates her character-friend. But the mature agent’s imitation is of a thoroughly different type than the imitation of the young moral agent; the mature imitation mechanism is selective and interpretative. The agent selects from (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Pleasure.Cory Wimberly - 2015 - In M. T. Gibbons, D. Coole, W. E. Connolly & E. Ellis (eds.), Blackwell Encyclopedia of Political Thought. Blackwell. pp. 2716-2720.
    The history of the political thought on pleasure is not a cloistered affair in which scholars only engage one another. In political thought, one commonly finds a critical engagement with the wider public and the ruling classes, which are both perceived to be dangerously hedonistic. The effort of many political thinkers is directed towards showing that other political ends are more worthy than pleasure: Plato battles vigorously against Calicles' pleasure seeking in the Gorgias, Augustine argues in The City of God (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. David Wolfsdorf: Pleasure in Ancient Greek Philosophy. [REVIEW]John V. Garner - 2014 - Ancient Philosophy 34 (2):462-467.
  24. The Nicomachean Ethics on Pleasure.Verity Harte - 2014 - In Ronald Polansky (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 288-318.
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25. Topical Bibliography to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics.Thornton Lockwood - 2014 - In Ronald Polansky (ed.), Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. New York, NY, USA: pp. 428-464.
  26. The Pleasures of Reason in Plato, Aristotle, and the Hellenistic Hedonists.James Warren - 2014 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Human lives are full of pleasures and pains. And humans are creatures that are able to think: to learn, understand, remember and recall, plan and anticipate. Ancient philosophers were interested in both of these facts and, what is more, were interested in how these two facts are related to one another. There appear to be, after all, pleasures and pains associated with learning and inquiring, recollecting and anticipating. We enjoy finding something out. We are pained to discover that a belief (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  27. Processes as pleasures in EN vii 11-14.Joachim Aufderheide - 2013 - Ancient Philosophy 33 (1):135-157.
  28. Getting Serious about Seriousness: On the Meaning of Spoudaios in Aristotle’s Ethics.Mathew Lu - 2013 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 87:285-293.
    In the following paper I discuss the under-appreciated role that the concept of the morally serious person plays in Aristotle’s moral philosophy. I argue that the conventional English rendering of spoudaios as “good” has a tendency to cut us off from important nuances in Aristotle’s consideration of the virtuous person. After discussing aspects of his use of the concept in the Nicomachean Ethics and the Politics I dismiss a misunderstanding of seriousness as a kind of morally indifferent personality trait. I (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Review of Miller, ed., Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. A Critical Guide. [REVIEW]Thornton Lockwood - 2012 - Bryn Mawr Classical Review 6:32.
    The nature of the edited scholarly collection has undergone a sea change. Whereas once upon a time edited collections brought together conference papers or previously published landmark studies—whose mark of excellence is scholarly rigor—more recently libraries have been inundated by Guides, Companions, and Handbooks. The Guide/Companion/Handbook model has its uses, perhaps especially for introductory essays or overviews of topics in which clarity, rather than cutting-edge scholarship, is the mark of excellence. Between these two models falls a new and somewhat unprecedented (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Pleasure as Perfection: Nicomachean Ethics X.4-5.Strohl Matthew - 2011 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 41:257-287.
    I argue that Aristotle took pleasure to be a certain aspect of perfect activities of awareness, namely, their very perfection. I also argue that this reading facilitates an attractive interpretation of his view that pleasures differ in kind along with the activities they arise in connection with.
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. Rediscovering the Sense of Pleasure in Morality.M. Lorenz Moises J. Festin - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 10:101-108.
    Pleasure has always been an important issue in morality. And although ethical systems tend to focus the discussion on human action, this agreeable sentiment has remained a recurrent question in moral philosophy. In this paper, I go back to Aristotle’s treatment of pleasure in his writings, particularly in the Nicomachean Ethics. I will argue that the distinction he draws between bodily pleasures and those of the mind represents an important point not only in understanding eudaimonia but also in situating the (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Pleasure in Aristotle’s Ethics. [REVIEW]Erick Raphael Jiménez - 2008 - Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 29 (1):277-281.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Like the Bloom on Youths: How pleasure completes our lives.Johan Brannmark - 2006 - In Timothy Chappell (ed.), Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics. Oxford University Press.
  34. Habituation as mimesis.Hallvard J. Fossheim - 2006 - In Timothy Chappell (ed.), Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics. Oxford University Press.
  35. The Functions of Pleasure in Nicomachean Ethics x 4-5.Peter Hadreas - 2004 - Ancient Philosophy 24 (1):155-167.
  36. Aristotle’s Definition of Pleasure: a Refutation of the Platonic Account.Gerd Van Riel - 2000 - Ancient Philosophy 20 (1):119-138.
  37. Aristotle’s Simile of Pleasure at NE 1174b33.Peter Hadreas - 1997 - Ancient Philosophy 17 (2):371-374.
  38. Aristotle’s measure doctrine and pleasure.Paula Gottlieb - 1993 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 75 (1):31-46.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Aristotle on Pleasure: Reconciling Three Different Accounts.Mary K. Ducey - 1992 - Dissertation, The Catholic University of America
    "Its difficulty, astonishingly, reduced Aristotle to babble." Thus G. E. M. Anscombe refers to dealing with pleasure in a philosophical way. Anscombe is not alone in criticizing Aristotle in this area: Ryle, Cope, and Ackrill have also claimed that his writings on pleasure are inconsistent. It has been a well-known and often considered problem: Book VII of the Nicomachean Ethics defines 'pleasure' as the equivalent of an energeia, an activity which requires nothing else to complete or perfect it, while Book (...)
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Aristotle on Pleasure and Perfection.Francisco Gonzalez - 1991 - Phronesis 36 (2):141-159.
  41. Aristotle on Pleasure.Robert Scott Stewart - 1990 - Auslegung 16 (1):97-108.
    Aristotle provides two extended discussions on the subject of pleasure within the Nicomachean Ethics. The first, which comprises the last four chapters of Book 7, produces a definition of pleasure in which pleasure is identified with activity (energeia). But in the second discussion of pleasure—provided in the first five chapters of Book 10-this position is characterized as "strange" or "absurd" (1175b 35). Instead of an identification between the two, pleasure is now said to "supervene" upon activity "as the bloom of (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Pleasure and Activity in Aristotle's Ethics.David Bostock - 1988 - Phronesis 33 (1):251-272.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  43. Ethical Pleasure: Aristotle's Two Treatments of Pleasure in the "Nicomachean Ethics".Betty J. Connelly - 1987 - Dissertation, Duquesne University
    This thesis' objective is an understanding of Aristotle's two quite different treatments of pleasure in the Nicomachean Ethics. Both treatments have implications for understanding human action and the role of pleasure in the good life. The thesis shows that differences in the treatments are resolvable if, first, an independent common basis for an Aristotelian notion of pleasure is developed and then the contexts of the passages are considered. ;The De Anima's exposition of locomotion as the characteristic activity of the sensient (...)
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Review of Gosling and Taylor, The Greeks on Pleasure. [REVIEW]Didier Pralon - 1986 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 176 (4):504-506.
  45. Pleasure, Tragedy and Aristotelian Psychology.Elizabeth Belfiore - 1985 - Classical Quarterly 35 (2):349-361.
    Aristotle'sRhetoricdefines fear as a kind of pain (lypē) or disturbance (tarachē) and pity as a kind of pain (2.5.1382 a 21 and 2.8.1385 b 13). In hisPoetics, however, pity and fear are associated with pleasure: ‘ The poet must provide the pleasure that comes from pity and fear by means of imitation’ (τ⋯ν ⋯π⋯ ⋯λέου κα⋯ ɸόβου δι⋯ μιμήσεως δεῖ ⋯δον⋯ν παρασκευάζειν14.1453 b 12–13). The question of the relationship between pleasure and pain in Aristotle's aesthetics has been studied primarily in (...)
    Remove from this list   Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. Aristotle's forbidden sweets.James Bogen & J. M. E. Moravcsik - 1982 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (2):111-127.
  47. The Greeks on pleasure.Justin Cyril Bertrand Gosling & Christopher Charles Whiston Taylor - 1982 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by C. C. W. Taylor.
    Provides a critical and analytical history of ancient Greek theories on the nature of pleasure, and of its value and rolein human lfie, from the ealriest times down to the period of Epicurus and the early Stoics.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  48. The Treatment of Pleasure and Pain in Aristotle's "Nicomachean Ethics".Donald Charles Lindenmuth - 1981 - Dissertation, New School for Social Research
    The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle contains two treatises on pleasure and pain, which present different positions on the nature of pleasure and its relation to the supreme good for man. Contrary to the standard approach, which accounts for these differences by assigning these treatises to different periods of Aristotle's philosophical development, I trace their differences to the general thematic development of the Ethics as a whole. This is achieved by an analysis of the themes of pleasure and pain and their (...)
    Remove from this list  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. II*—More Aristotelian Pleasures.J. Gosling - 1974 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 74 (1):15-34.
    J. Gosling; II*—More Aristotelian Pleasures, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 74, Issue 1, 1 June 1974, Pages 15–34, https://doi.org/10.1093/aris.
    Remove from this list   Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Pleasure and the Two Happinesses in Aristotle.Martin A. Bertman - 1972 - Apeiron 6 (2):30 - 36.
1 — 50 / 53