Results for 'Could Have'

989 found
Order:
  1. “I could have been you”: Existential Envy and the Self.Íngrid Vendrell-Ferran - 2022 - In Sara Protasi (ed.), The Moral Psychology of Envy. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. pp. 77-92.
    This paper explores “existential envy” as a kind of envy in which the subject targets the rival’s entire being rather than one of her possessions, achievements or talents. It argues that existential envy is characterized by a weakening of the distinction between good and rival and by a strong focus on the envious self. In existential envy, the subject becomes aware that another person is closer to her ideal self than she is, such that the rival painfully reminds her of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. I could have done that.Guy Rohrbaugh - 2005 - British Journal of Aesthetics 45 (3):209-228.
    Could a work of art actually authored by one artist have been authored, instead, by another? This is the question of the necessity of authorship. After distinguishing this question from another, regarding individuation, with which it is often confused, this paper offers an argument that authorship is indeed a necessary feature of most artworks. The argument proceeds from ‘independence principles’, which govern the processes by which artworks are produced. Independence principles are motivated, in turn, by metaphysical reflections on (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  3. 'Could have done otherwise', action sentences and anaphora.Helen Steward - 2006 - Analysis 66 (2):95–101.
    This paper argues that there are a number of different things that could be meant by the claim that a given agent 'could have done otherwise', because there are multiple ways of disambiguating the various anaphoric devices which are contained in the phrase. It goes on to suggest that on at least one of these disambiguations, the claim that a Frankfurtian agent could have done otherwise might be defensible, even given the presence of a counterfactual (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  4. Could have but did not.Krister Segerberg - 1983 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 64 (July):230-241.
  5. Compatibilists could have done otherwise: Responsibility and negative agency.Alison Mclntyre - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (3):453-488.
  6. How Carnap Could Have Replied to Gödel.Steve Awodey & A. W. Carus - unknown
    Steve Awodey and A. W. Carus. How Carnap Could Have Replied to Gödel.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  7.  45
    What could have happened.David H. Sanford - 1976 - Noûs 10 (3):313-326.
    Morton White proposes two patterns of expansion for sentences of the form "Possible (x is Q)" in "On What Could Have Happened" (Philosophical Review, 1968). His attempts in "Ands and Cans" (Mind, 1974) and in "Positive Freedom, Negative Freedom, and Possibility" (Journal of Philosophy, 1973) to simplify these two patterns and his argument for abandoning the first pattern are mistaken. Although I question a number of White's claims, my purpose is to improve his treatment of possibility rather than (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  54
    I could have done otherwise: Availability of counterfactual comparisons informs the sense of agency.Eugenia Kulakova, Nima Khalighinejad & Patrick Haggard - 2017 - Consciousness and Cognition 49:237-244.
  9.  44
    What could have been done (but wasn’t). On the counterfactual status of action in Alva Noë’s theory of perception.Gunnar Declerck - 2017 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 16 (5):765-784.
    Alva Noë’s strategy to solve the puzzle of perceptual presence entirely relies on the principle of presence as access. Unaccessed or unattended parts or details of objects are perceptually present insofar as they are accessible, and they are accessible insofar as one possesses sensorimotor skills that can secure their access. In this paper, I consider several arguments that can be opposed to this claim and that are chiefly related to the modal status of action, i.e. the fact that the action (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. What could have saved John Worthy.B. J. Crigger - 1998 - Hastings Center Report 28 (4).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Could Have_ and _Would Have.Nathan Salmón - manuscript
    An alternative to the classical Stalnaker-Lewis account of subjunctive conditionals is outlined. A distinction is drawn between a basic notion of “wouldness” and a more full-bloodedly modal variant, each with its own logic. Previous philosophers have challenged the alleged vacuity of counterpossibles using logico-mathematically impossible worlds. Here the vacuity thesis as well as other orthodox alleged logical principles are challenged instead through consideration of a logico-mathematically possible world. The impossible-world theorist’s Strangeness of Impossibility Condition is also challenged using the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. It Could Have Been Worse: Walter Benjamin as Opera.E. Leslie - forthcoming - Radical Philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  19
    I Could Have Retched All Night.Charles Darwin & His Body - 1998 - In Christopher Lawrence & Steven Shapin (eds.), Science incarnate: historical embodiments of natural knowledge. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press. pp. 240.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. He could have done otherwise.Roderick M. Chisholm - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (13):409-417.
  15.  17
    Could Have Done Otherwise.Robert Cummins - 1979 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 60 (4):411.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  55
    It could have been otherwise: contingency and necessity in Dominican theology at Oxford, 1300-1350.Hester Gelber - 2004 - Boston: Brill.
    Hester Goodenough Gelber is Associate Professor of Religious Studies, Stanford University.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  17. Wasted Potential: The Value of a Life and the Significance of What Could Have Been.Michal Masny - 2023 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 51 (1):6-32.
    According to the orthodox view, the goodness of a life depends exclusively on the things that actually happened within it, such as its pleasures and pains, the satisfaction of its subject’s preferences, or the presence of various objective goods and bads. In this paper, I argue that the goodness of a life also depends on what could have happened, but didn’t. I then propose that this view helps us resolve ethical puzzles concerning the standards for a life worth (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  69
    Ought to Have' and 'Could Have.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong - 1985 - Analysis 45 (1):44 - 48.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19. This wooden table could have been made from plastic.David Barnett - manuscript
    In defense of de re necessity, Saul Kripke proposes that a material object could not have originated in a substance different in kind from the substance in which it actually originated. I give a counterexample to this proposal.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Killing people: what Kant could have said about suicide and euthanasia but did not.I. Brassington - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (10):571-574.
    An agent who takes his own life acts in violation of the moral law, according to Kant; suicide, and, by extension, assisted suicide are therefore wrong. By a similar argument, and with a few important exceptions, killing is wrong; implicitly, then, voluntary euthanasia is also wrong. Kant's conclusions are uncompelling and his argument in these matters is undermined on considering other areas of his thought. Kant, in forbidding suicide and euthanasia, is conflating respect for persons and respect for people, and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21. Ought Implies Can Or Could Have.Andrew Dennis Bassford - 2022 - Review of Metaphysics 75 (4):779-807.
    The moral principle that Ought Implies Can (“OIC”) is often assumed without argument in normative discourse. Is this assumption defensible? Some would argue that it is not, as there are many purported counterexamples against it in the literature. However, OIC is not so much a single principle as rather a family of them. In this paper, I will argue that, while not every OIC-type principle is defensible, at least one of them may be. I defend the cognate moral principle that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Luckily, We Are Only Responsible for What We Could Have Avoided.Philip Swenson - 2019 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 43 (1):106-118.
    This paper has two goals: (1) to defend a particular response to the problem of resultant moral luck and (2) to defend the claim that we are only responsible for what we could have avoided. Cases of overdetermination threaten to undermine the claim that we are only responsible for what we could have avoided. To deal with this issue, I will motivate a particular way of responding to the problem of resultant moral luck. I defend the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  23.  84
    Who you could have known: divine hiddenness, epistemic counterfactuals, and the recalcitrant nature of natural theology.Brandon L. Rickabaugh & Derek L. McAllister - 2017 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 82 (3):337-348.
    We argue there is a deep conflict in Paul Moser’s work on divine hiddenness. Moser’s treatment of DH adopts a thesis we call SEEK: DH often results from failing to seek God on His terms. One way in which people err, according to Moser, is by trusting arguments of traditional natural theology to lead to filial knowledge of God. We argue that Moser’s SEEK thesis commits him to the counterfactual ACCESS: had the atheist sought after God in harmony with how (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24. Ceteris Paribus, I Could Have Done Otherwise.Ann Whittle - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92 (1):73-85.
    In this paper, I explore an alternative to the Principle of Alternate Possibilities for Moral Responsibility—the Ceteris Paribus Principle of Alternative Possibilities for Moral Responsibility. I consider motivations for this principle and answer some objections to it.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  25. How it makes a moral difference that one is worse off than one could have been.Michael Otsuka - 2018 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 17 (2):192-215.
    In this article, I argue that it makes a moral difference whether an individual is worse off than she could have been. Here, I part company with consequentialists such as Parfit and side with contractualists such as Scanlon. But, unlike some contractualists, I reject the view that all that matters is whether a principle can be justified to each particular individual, where such a justification is attentive to her interests, complaints and other claims. The anonymous goodness of a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  26.  40
    How thinking about what could have been affects how we feel about what was.Felipe De Brigard, Eleanor Hanna, Peggy L. St Jacques & Daniel L. Schacter - 2019 - Cognition and Emotion 33 (4):646-659.
    ABSTRACTEpisodic counterfactual thoughts and autobiographical memories involve the reactivation and recombination of episodic memory components into mental simulations. Upon reactivation, memories become labile and prone to modification. Thus, reactivating AM in the context of mentally generating CFT may provide an opportunity for editing processes to modify the content of the original memory. To examine this idea, this paper reports the results of two studies that investigated the effect of reactivating negative and positive AM in the context of either imagining a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  20
    What is and what could have been: Experiencing regret and relief across childhood.Anna C. K. Van Duijvenvoorde, Hilde M. Huizenga & Brenda R. J. Jansen - 2014 - Cognition and Emotion 28 (5):926-935.
  28. Oh, All the Wrongs I Could Have Performed! Or: Why Care about Morality, Robustly Realistically Understood.David Enoch & Itamar Weinshtock Saadon - 2023 - In Paul Bloomfield & David Copp (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism. Oxford University Press. pp. 434-462.
    Suppose someone is brought up as an orthodox Jew, and so only eats kosher, is very conservative sexually, etc. Suppose they then find out that this Judaism stuff is just all a big mistake. If they then regret all the shrimp they could have eaten, all the sex!, this makes perfect sense. Not so, however, if someone finds out that moral realism is false, and they now regret all the fun they could have had hurting people’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  29.  25
    `Could' and `could have': A reply.M. R. Ayers - 1968 - Philosophical Quarterly 18 (71):144-150.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  78
    ‘But You Could Have Hurt Me!’: Risk and Harm.Joseph Bowen - 2022 - Law and Philosophy 41 (4):517-546.
    This paper answers two questions. First, on the assumption that risk of harm is of moral significance, does risk’s moral significance lay in its being harmful? Second, is risk of harm itself harmful? I argue that either risk is not harmful or that risk is harmful only in a small range of cases. If risk is not harmful, and yet risk is of moral significance, risk’s moral significance cannot lie in its being harmful. And if risk is harmful only in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. Slurs, neutral counterparts, and what you could have said.Arianna Falbo - 2021 - Analytic Philosophy 62 (4):359-375.
    Recent pragmatic accounts of slurs argue that the offensiveness of slurs is generated by a speaker's free choice to use a slur opposed to a more appropriate and semantically equivalent neutral counterpart. I argue that the theoretical role of neutral counterparts on such views is overstated. I consider two recent pragmatic analyses, Bolinger (Noûs, 51, 2017, 439) and Nunberg (New work on speech acts, Oxford University Press, 2018), which rely heavily upon the optionality of slurs, namely, that a speaker exercises (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  29
    On what could have happened.Morton White - 1968 - Philosophical Review 77 (1):73-89.
  33.  30
    Analysis of 'X could have acted otherwise'.F. B. Buckley - 1956 - Philosophical Studies 7 (5):69 - 74.
  34.  61
    Aquinas on what could have been.Richard L. Cartwright - 1996 - Philosophical Perspectives 10:447 - 458.
  35.  18
    Imagining What Could Have Happened: Types and Vividness of Counterfactual Thoughts and the Relationship With Post-traumatic Stress Reactions.Ines Blix, Alf Børre Kanten, Marianne Skogbrott Birkeland & Siri Thoresen - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  15
    Special Supplement: What Could Have Saved John Worthy?Fran Davis, Edward R. Post, Connie S. Rogers, Michael Depp, Peter Ferrell & Jane Worthy - 1998 - Hastings Center Report 28 (4):S1.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  79
    On the Meaning of 'Could Have'.Clement Dore - 1962 - Analysis 23 (2):41 - 43.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  21
    Ayers on `could' and `could have'.David Gallop - 1967 - Philosophical Quarterly 17 (68):255-256.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  10
    The Man Who Could Have Been King: a Storyteller's Guide for Character Education.Tony R. Sanchez - 2006 - Journal of Social Studies Research 30 (2).
  40.  62
    What he could have said (but did not say) about Gödel’s second theorem: A note on Floyd-Putnam’s Wittgenstein.Kaave Lajevardi - 2021 - Wittgenstein-Studien 12 (1):121-129.
    In several publications, Juliet Floyd and Hilary Putnam have argued that the so-called ‘notorious paragraph’ of the Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics contains a valuable philosophical insight about Gödel’s informal proof of the first incompleteness theorem – in a nutshell, the idea they attribute to Wittgenstein is that if the Gödel sentence of a system is refutable, then, because of the resulting ω-inconsistency of the system, we should give up the translation of Gödel’s sentence by the English sentence (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  85
    On an Analysis of 'Could Have'.David S. Scarrow - 1963 - Analysis 23 (5):118 - 120.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  36
    Gelber, Hester G.: It could have been otherwise. Contingency and necessity in Dominican theology at oxford, 1300–1350.Jacob Schmutz - 2008 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 90 (1):131-133.
  43.  35
    Compatibilism, Values, and “Could Have Done Otherwise”.David Shatz - 1988 - Philosophical Topics 16 (1):151-200.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  82
    Dennett on `could have done otherwise'.Peter van Inwagen - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (10):565-567.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  19
    What sort of person could have a radically extended lifespan?Rebecca Roache - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics Recent Issues 44 (4):217-218.
    The literature on human enhancement is awash with discussions about whether it really would be desirable to increase our lifespan, cognitive power, physical strength above and beyond that which we currently consider to be healthy or normal. Almost all of these discussions hang on the question of whether it makes sense to draw a morally relevant distinction between those interventions that count as therapies and those that count as enhancements. Roughly, therapies are interventions that aim to restore health or normality (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. On an analysis of 'could have'.David S. Scarrow - 1963 - Analysis 23 (5):118.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. What God Could Have Made.Michael Losonsky & Heimir Geirsson - 2005 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 43 (3):355-376.
    Plantinga grants that there are possible worlds with freedom and no moral evil, but he argues that it is possible that although God is omnipotent, it is not within God’s power to actualize a world containing freedom and no moral evil. Plantinga believes that the atheologian assumes that it is necessary that it is within an omnipotent God’s power to actualize these better worlds, but in fact, Plantinga argues, this is demonstrably not the case. Since so many philosophers have (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  10
    Compatibilism, Values, and “Could Have Done Otherwise”.David Shatz - 1988 - Philosophical Topics 16 (1):151-200.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  34
    Analyses of: “P could have decided differently in the situation S”.Harald Ofstad - 1953 - Proceedings of the XIth International Congress of Philosophy 14:128-135.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  78
    Doing for circular time what Shoemaker did for time without change: How one could have evidence that time is circular rather than linear and infinitely repeating.Cody Gilmore & Brian Kierland - forthcoming - Philosophies.
    There are possible worlds in which time is circular and finite in duration, forming a loop of, say, 12,000 years. There are also possible worlds in which time is linear and infinite in both directions, and in which history is repetitive, consisting of infinitely many 12,000 year epochs, each two of which are exactly alike with respect to all intrinsic, purely qualitative properties. Could one ever have empirical evidence that one inhabits a world of the first kind rather (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 989