Results for 'simple-if question'

999 found
Order:
  1. Simple-If Question and Essence’s Being Existent; Mullā Sadrā v.s. Mīr Dāmād.Davood Hosseini - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Investigations 12 (25):95-111.
    Mīr Dāmād, in Qabasāt argues that existence cannot be a real property for essences. If existence, he argues, were a real property of an essence, there would remain no distinction between simple-if and compound-if questions. It is well-known that Mullā Sadrā has given three different accounts in order to explain essence’s being existent: first that existence is an analytical property for essence; second that none of existence or essence is a property of the other one; and third that essence (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  49
    Simples and gunk.Kris McDaniel - unknown
    An object is a simple if and only if it has no proper parts. An object is gunk if and only if every proper part of that object itself has a proper part. In my dissertation, I address the following questions. The concepts of simples and gunk presuppose the concept of parthood. What is the status of this concept? his question itself divides into the following: does the concept of parthood have universal applicability, so that, just as every (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3. A Simple Theory of Introspection.Declan Smithies - 2012 - In Declan Smithies & Daniel Stoljar (eds.), Introspection and Consciousness. Oxford University Press.
    This chapter develops a simple theory of introspection on which a mental state is introspectively accessible just by virtue of the fact that one is in that mental state. This theory raises two questions: first, a generalization question: which mental states are introspectively accessible; and second, an explanatory question: why are some mental states introspectively accessible, rather than others, or none at all? In response to the generalization question, I argue that a mental state is introspectively (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  4.  24
    The Service Conception: Just One Simple Question.Nikolas Kirby - 2017 - Law and Philosophy 36 (3):255-278.
    It is crystal clear that the Service Conception includes at least three conditions, what I shall call: the ‘normal justification condition’, the ‘independence condition’ and the ‘dependence condition’. The overarching rationale of these conditions is that they ensure that authority is only justified when it provides the best means for the subject to conform to the reasons for action that she actually has. However, it is difficult to clarify whether Raz implicitly presupposes a fourth necessary condition. This condition might be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. You Needn't Be Simple.Andrew M. Bailey - 2014 - Philosophical Papers 43 (2):145-160.
    Here's an interesting question: what are we? David Barnett has claimed that reflection on consciousness suggests an answer: we are simple. Barnett argues that the mereological simplicity of conscious beings best explains the Datum: that no pair of persons can itself be conscious. In this paper, I offer two alternative explanations of the Datum. If either is correct, Barnett's argument fails. First, there aren't any such things as pairs of persons. Second, consciousness is maximal; no conscious thing is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  6. Against maxcon simples.Kris McDaniel - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2):265 – 275.
    In a recent paper titled ' Simples ', Ned Markosian asks and answers the Simple Question, which is, 'under what circumstances is it true of some object that it has no proper parts?' Markosian 's answer to the simple question is MaxCon, which states that an object is a simple if and only if it is a maximally continuous object. I present several arguments against MaxCon.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  7.  82
    A simple solution to the puzzles of end of life? Voluntary palliated starvation.Julian Savulescu - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (2):110-113.
    Should people be assisted to die or be given euthanasia when they are suffering from terminal medical conditions? Should they be assisted to die when they are suffering but do not have a ‘diagnosable medical illness?’ What about assisted dying for psychiatric conditions? And is there a difference morally between assisted suicide, voluntary active euthanasia and voluntary passive euthanasia?These are deep questions directly addressed or in the background of the productive discussion between Varelius and Young.1 ,2 Their focus is whether (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8. Simple rape and the risks of sex.George E. Panichas - 2006 - Law and Philosophy 25 (6):613 - 661.
    This paper addresses the question of whether rape-law reform should treat all cases of simple rape—nonconsensual sex that does not involve the use or credible threat of physical force—as a serious crime. Of primary concern here are those sexual interactions, often referred to as “date rape” or “acquaintance rape,” where the coercive element is not physical force as evidenced by reasonable resistance. Should, as some feminist reformers have urged, felony rape include sexual interactions that may not be fully (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  45
    Simple rationality? The law of healthcare resource allocation in England.C. Foster - 2007 - Journal of Medical Ethics 33 (7):404-407.
    This paper examines the law relating to healthcare resource allocation in England. The National Health Service Act 1977 does not impose an absolute duty to provide specified healthcare services. The courts will only interfere with a resource allocation decision made by an NHS body if that decision is frankly irrational is engaged). Such irrationality is very difficult to establish. The ECHR has made no significant contribution to domestic English law in the arena of healthcare provision. The decision of the European (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. One Very Simple Principle.Jonathan Riley - 1991 - Utilitas 3 (1):1.
    John Gray, much influenced by Isaiah Berlin and building on work by the late John Rees and the late Fred Berger, has recently stated three ‘fatal’ objections which virtually all analysts seem to find persuasive against John Stuart Mill's classic doctrine of liberty. First, Gray thinks it ‘an obvious objection to Mill's project that conceptions of harm vary with competing moral outlooks, so that no Principle of Liberty whose application turns on judgements about harm can expect to resolve disputes between (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  11.  25
    On co-simple isols and their intersection types.Rod Downey & Theodore A. Slaman - 1992 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 56 (1-3):221-237.
    We solve a question of McLaughlin by showing that if A is a regressive co-simple isol, there is a co-simple regressive isol B such that the intersection type of A and B is trivial. The proof is a nonuniform 0 priority argument that can be viewed as the execution of a single strategy from a 0-argument. We establish some limit on the properties of such pairs by showing that if AxB has low degree, then the intersection type (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Could extended objects be made out of simple parts? An argument for "atomless gunk".Dean W. Zimmerman - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (1):1-29.
    Let us say that an extended object is “composed wholly of simples” just in case it is an aggregate of absolutely unextended parts spread throughout an extended region—that is, just in case there is a set S such that: every member is a point-sized part of the object, and for every x, x is part of the object if and only if it has a part in common with some member of S. Could a truly extended substance be composed entirely (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  13.  45
    Are Bolzano’s Substances Simple?Andrej Krause - 2006 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 80 (4):543-562.
    This article analyzes one aspect of Bolzano’s metaphysics. It discusses the question of whether, according to Bolzano, substances are simple or not. In theopinion of some commentators, he accepts composed substances, that is, substances having substances as proper parts. However, it is easily possible to misinterpret his position. This paper first tries to reconstruct Bolzano’s definitions of the concept of substance and suggests that he should be able to agree with the following final definition: x is a substance (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  18
    Are Bolzano’s Substances Simple?Andrej Krause - 2006 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 80 (4):543-562.
    This article analyzes one aspect of Bolzano’s metaphysics. It discusses the question of whether, according to Bolzano, substances are simple or not. In theopinion of some commentators, he accepts composed substances, that is, substances having substances as proper parts. However, it is easily possible to misinterpret his position. This paper first tries to reconstruct Bolzano’s definitions of the concept of substance and suggests that he should be able to agree with the following final definition: x is a substance (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15. What, If anything, Is Biological Altruism?Topaz Halperin & Arnon Levy - forthcoming - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    The study of biological altruism is a cornerstone of modern evolutionary biology. Associated with foundational issues about natural selection, it is often supposed that explaining altruism is key to understanding social behavior more generally. Typically, biological altruism is defined in purely effects-based, behavioral terms – as an interaction in which one organism contributes fitness to another, at its own expense. Crucially, such a definition isn’t meant to rest on psychological or intentional assumptions. We show that, appearances and official definitions notwithstanding, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  17
    What if worms were sentient? Insights into subjective experience from the Caenorhabditis elegans connectome.Oressia Zalucki, Deborah J. Brown & Brian Key - 2023 - Biology and Philosophy 38 (5):1-25.
    Deciphering the neural basis of subjective experience remains one of the great challenges in the natural sciences. The structural complexity and the limitations around invasive experimental manipulations of the human brain have impeded progress towards this goal. While animals cannot directly report first-person subjective experiences, their ability to exhibit flexible behaviours such as motivational trade-offs are generally considered evidence of sentience. The worm _Caenorhabditis elegans_ affords the unique opportunity to describe the circuitry underlying subjective experience at a single cell level (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  59
    Could Extended Objects Be Made Out of Simple Parts?Dean W. Zimmerman - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (1):1-29.
    Let us say that an extended object is “composed wholly of simples” just in case it is an aggregate of absolutely unextended parts spread throughout an extended region—that is, just in case there is a set S such that: every member is a point-sized part of the object, and for every x, x is part of the object if and only if it has a part in common with some member of S. Could a truly extended substance be composed entirely (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  18.  21
    More on simple forcing notions and forcings with ideals.M. Gitik & S. Shelah - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 59 (3):219-238.
    It is shown that cardinals below a real-valued measurable cardinal can be split into finitely many intervals so that the powers of cardinals from the same interval are the same. This generalizes a theorem of Prikry [9]. Suppose that the forcing with a κ-complete ideal over κ is isomorphic to the forcing of λ-Cohen or random reals. Then for some τ<κ, λτ2κ and λ2<κ implies that 2κ=2τ= cov. In particular, if 2κ<κ+ω, then λ=2κ. This answers a question from [3]. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  40
    Courts as communicators: Can doctors learn from judges' decisions?: The doctor's question: ‘Will I be all right if I …? [REVIEW]Loane Skene - 2004 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 1 (1):49-56.
    The role of the courts in ‘communicating’ with those affected by their decisions is contentious. Some legal commentators maintain that courts and legislators are able to communicate decisions effectively and that attempts to ‘dumb down’ the law will not make such decisions more accessible to doctors and other professionals. Justice Michael Kirby, on the other hand, seems to share the present author's view that judges could improve their communication of their decisions to a wider audience: ‘In future, it seems inevitable (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  34
    If Everything Can Not-Be There Would Be Nothing: Another Look at the Third Way.Martin J. De Nys - 2002 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (1):99-122.
    IN A DISCUSSION OF ARGUMENTS concerning the existence of God, James Ross comments that we know that the premises of such arguments “are infinitely analysable, that they can be subject to an illimitable series of questions and that every question can be answered in more than one way.” The record of disputes over the “third way” of Aquinas certainly confirms these statements. Those disputes revolve around issues about which questions are continually raised in spite of strenuous attempts made at (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  25
    On a simple-minded solution.James N. Hullett - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (3):452-454.
    Mr. Bartley's remark that Goodman's puzzle is “an interesting variant of the possibility... that the next instance may be different” rather badly misrepresents matters. One might say that the “new riddle” arises just because no matter what the nature of the next instance, it will be as much like all previously examined cases as any other instance. Suppose “Hester” is the name of the first emerald examined after time t. If Hester is green, then Hester is like previously examined emeralds (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  91
    Consistency Among Intentions and the ‘Simple View’.Steven Sverdlik - 1996 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (4):515-522.
    What is the relation between the intention to A and doing A intentionally? It is natural to suppose that the latter entails the former. That is, it is natural to accept what Michael Bratman has called the ‘Simple View’ of the relation between acting intentionally and having an intention. Bratman is one noteworthy writer who has denied that the Simple View is true. In the present paper I do not defend this view. I contend that one well-known argument (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  23.  71
    Mutually Exclusive Planning and the Simple View.Lilian O’Brien - 2014 - Topoi 33 (1):47-55.
    There have been a number of challenges to the Simple View—the view that an intention to A is necessary if an agent is to A intentionally. Michael Bratman’s celebrated video game case has convinced many that the view is false. This article presents a novel objection to Bratman’s case. It is argued, first, that the Simple View is not undermined by the case, and second, that the real import of the case is that it raises the question (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  7
    Trading transforms of non-weighted simple games and integer weights of weighted simple games.Tomomi Matsui & Akihiro Kawana - 2021 - Theory and Decision 93 (1):131-150.
    This study investigates simple games. A fundamental research question in this field is to determine necessary and sufficient conditions for a simple game to be a weighted majority game. Taylor and Zwicker showed that a simple game is non-weighted if and only if there exists a trading transform of finite size. They also provided an upper bound on the size of such a trading transform, if it exists. Gvozdeva and Slinko improved that upper bound; their proof (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Beth too, but only if.Achille C. Varzi - 2005 - Analysis 65 (3):224-229.
    On the difficulty of extracting the logical form of a seemingly simple sentence such as ‘If Andy went to the movie then Beth went too, but only if she found a taxi cab’, with some morals and questions on the nature of the difficulty.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  89
    Sense and simplicity: Wittgenstein's argument for simple objects.Chon Tejedor - 2003 - Ratio 16 (3):272–289.
    This paper puts forward an alternative interpretation of the argument for simple objects advanced in the 2.0s of the Tractatus. In my view, Wittgenstein derives the simplicity of objects directly from his account of possible states, complex objects and senseful propositions. The key to Wittgenstein's argument is the idea that, if there were no simple objects, possible states would not be necessarily possible. If this were the case, however, there would be no senseful language, in Wittgenstein's view. One (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  32
    On the Weak Non-Finite Cover Property and the n-Tuples of Simple Structures.Evgueni Vassiliev - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (1):235 - 251.
    The weak non-finite cover property (wnfcp) was introduced in [1] in connection with "axiomatizability" of lovely pairs of models of a simple theory. We find a combinatorial condition on a simple theory equivalent to the wnfcp, yielding a direct proof that the non-finite cover property implies the wnfcp, and that the wnfcp is preserved under reducts. We also study the question whether the wnfcp is preserved when passing from a simple theory T to the theory TP (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  55
    Can Hume's Use of a Simple/Complex Distinction Be Made Consistent?David B. Hausman - 1988 - Hume Studies 14 (2):424-428.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:424 CAN HUME'S USE OF A SIMPLE/COMPLEX DISTINCTION BE MADE CONSISTENT? There is little doubt that Hume equivocates on the distinction between simple and complex impressions and ideas. Sometimes he identifies properties such as colors and shapes as simples. This is what he does, in fact, when he first introduces the distinction: Simple perceptions or impressions and ideas are such as admit of no distinction nor (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Prufrock's question and roquentin's answer.William Irwin - 2009 - Philosophy and Literature 33 (1):pp. 184-192.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Prufrock's Question and Roquentin's AnswerWilliam IrwinThere could not be two more different literary figures than the right-wing, religious T. S. Eliot and the left-wing, atheistic Jean-Paul Sartre. Yet there are striking connections between their first major publications, The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock (1917) and Nausea (1938). Eliot was aware of and critical of Sartre, especially in the commentary on No Exit in The Cocktail Party, and, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  61
    Interpreting Signatures (Nietzsche/Heidegger): Two Questions.Jacques Derrida, Diane Michelfelder & Richard E. Palmer - 1986 - Philosophy and Literature 10 (2):246-262.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Jacques Derrida INTERPRETING SIGNATURES (NIETZSCHE/HEIDEGGER): TWO QUESTIONS T1HE first question concerns die name Nietzsche, die second has to do with the concept of totality. Let us begin widi chapters 2 and 3 of Heidegger's Nietzsche — dealing with "The Eternal Recurrence of the Same" and "The Will to Power as Knowledge," respectively. We will be turning especially to the subsection on chaos ["The Concept of Chaos," I, pp. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  31. Is There a “Pessimistic” Bias in Individual Beliefs? Evidence from a Simple Survey.Selima Ben Mansour, Elyès Jouini & Clotilde Napp - 2006 - Theory and Decision 61 (4):345-362.
    It is an important issue for economic and finance applications to determine whether individuals exhibit a behavioral bias toward pessimism in their beliefs, in a lottery or more generally in an investment opportunities framework. In this paper, we analyze the answers of a sample of 1,540 individuals to the following question “Imagine that a coin will be flipped 10 times. Each time, if heads, you win \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$10\texttt{C}\!\!\!\rule[2.3pt]{.4em}{.3pt}\!\!\rule[3.3pt]{.4em}{.3pt}$$\end{docum ent}. How many times do (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  79
    The Man Blind from Birth and the Subversion of Sin: Some Questions About Fundamental Morals.James Alison - 1997 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 4 (1):26-46.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:THE MAN BLIND FROM BIRTH AND THE SUBVERSION OF SIN: SOME QUESTIONS ABOUT FUNDAMENTAL MORALS1 James Alison I would like to undertake with you a reading of a passage from the Bible, John Chapter 9. I hope that we will see this chapter yield some interesting insights in the light of my attempt to apply to it the mimetic theory ofRené Girard. I'm not going to expound mimetic theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Is there a 'pessimistic' bias in individual beliefs ? Evidence from a simple survey.Clotilde Napp, Elyès Jouini & Selima Benmansour - 2006 - Theory and Decision 61 (4):345-362.
    It is an important issue for economic and finance applications to determine whether individuals exhibit a behavioral bias toward pessimism in their beliefs, in a lottery or more generally in an investment opportunities framework. In this paper, we analyze the answers of a sample of 1,540 individuals to the following question: Imagine that a coin will be flipped 10 times. Each time, if heads, you win 10 Euros. How many times do you think that you will win? The average (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  42
    Vasubandhu’s Refutation of the Aggregate of Atoms: a Reading Inspired by Van Inwagen’s Objection to Series-Style Answers to the Special Composition Question.Yufan Mao - forthcoming - Sophia:1-16.
    Vasubandhu’s arguments against atomism in Viṃśikā stanzas 12–13 are not strong enough to disprove that atoms are simple partless substances. However, if we take the special composition question into consideration, Viṃśikā stanza 13ab can be regarded as an objection to so-called series-style answers, which results in an undesirable conclusion for the opponents, i.e. the Vaibhāṣikas. A step back to a simple bonding answer is not a good choice for the Vaibhāṣikas in responding to this objection because the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Is "Why Be Moral?" A Pseudo-Question?: Hospers and Thornton on the Amoralist's Challenge.John J. Tilley - 2006 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (4):549-66.
    Many arguments have been advanced for the view that "Why be moral?" is a pseudo-question. In this paper I address one of the most widely known and influential of them, one that comes from John Hospers and J. C. Thornton. I do so partly because, strangely, an important phase of that argument has escaped close attention. It warrants such attention because, firstly, not only is it important to the argument in which it appears, it is important in wider respects. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. What if ? Questions about conditionals.Dorothy Edgington - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (4):380–401.
    Section 1 briefly examines three theories of indicative conditionals. The Suppositional Theory is defended, and shown to be incompatible with understanding conditionals in terms of truth conditions. Section 2 discusses the psychological evidence about conditionals reported by Over and Evans (this volume). Section 3 discusses the syntactic grounds offered by Haegeman (this volume) for distinguishing two sorts of conditional.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  37.  13
    What if? Questions About Conditionals.Dorothy Edgington - 2003 - Mind and Language 18 (4):380-401.
    Section 1 briefly examines three theories of indicative conditionals. The Suppositional Theory is defended, and shown to be incompatible with understanding conditionals in terms of truth conditions. Section 2 discusses the psychological evidence about conditionals reported by Over and Evans (this volume). Section 3 discusses the syntactic grounds offered by Haegeman (this volume) for distinguishing two sorts of conditional.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  38.  14
    The Kingdom of Childhood: Seven Lectures and Answers to Questions Given in Torquay, 12-20 August 1924.Rudolf Steiner - 1964 - London: Anthroposophic Press.
    7 lectures, Torquay, UK, August 12-20, 1924 (CW 311) These seven intimate, aphoristic talks were presented to a small group on Steiner's final visit to England. Because they were given to "pioneers" dedicated to opening a new Waldorf school, these talks are often considered one of the best introductions to Waldorf education. Steiner shows the necessity for teachers to work on themselves first, in order to transform their own inherent gifts. He explains the need to use humor to keep their (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  3
    Does God like being God?: and other tricky questions about God: a guide for teachers, catechists, and parents.John Honner - 2019 - New York: Paulist Press.
    Foundations of theology -- Can theology be made simple? -- Why is the Bible important? -- Is faith reasonable? -- Can expressions of faith change? -- Questions about God -- Why is God called God? -- If God made the world, who made God? -- Did God really make the world in seven days? -- So where is God? -- If God is almighty, why is there so much suffering? -- Does God have a plan for me? -- Can (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Connectivity in a unified analysis of specificational subjects and concealed questions.Maribel Romero - manuscript
    Connectivity, found in a number of constructions involving typically a trace of movement or gap, is the effect by which a constituent behaves grammatically as if it occupied not its surface position but the position of the gap. The phenomenon is central to the debate between defendants of Direct Compositionality –where the semantics is read off the ‘visible’, surface syntax– and the defendants of the so-called Logical Form (LF) –according to which semantics is computed on an abstract syntactic representation, LF, (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  5
    To Cut or Not to Cut? That is the Question.Tracy Wilson - 2023 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 13 (2):85-86.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:To Cut or Not to Cut?That is the QuestionTracy WilsonWhat is circumcision? In simple terms, it is the removal or excision of the foreskin of the penis. Seems so simple, right? In some families, it is that simple. In other families, it is a religious exercise. I am a doctorally-prepared Family Nurse Practitioner and started my nursing career in the NICU. I have seen my fair (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Indivisible Parts and Extended Objects.Dean W. Zimmerman - 1996 - The Monist 79 (1):148-180.
    Physical boundaries and the earliest topologists. Topology has a relatively short history; but its 19th century roots are embedded in philosophical problems about the nature of extended substances and their boundaries which go back to Zeno and Aristotle. Although it seems that there have always been philosophers interested in these matters, questions about the boundaries of three-dimensional objects were closest to center stage during the later medieval and modern periods. Are the boundaries of an object actually existing, less-than-three-dimensional parts of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  43. If mirror neurons are the answer, what was the question?Emma Borg - 2007 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 14 (8):5-19.
    Mirror neurons are neurons which fire in two distinct conditions: (i) when an agent performs a specific action, like a precision grasp of an object using fingers, and (ii) when an agent observes that action performed by another. Some theorists have suggested that the existence of such neurons may lend support to the simulation approach to mindreading (e.g. Gallese and Goldman, 1998, 'Mirror neurons and the simulation theory of mind reading'). In this note I critically examine this suggestion, in both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  44. Manipulation Arguments and the Freedom to do Otherwise.Patrick Todd - 2017 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 95 (2):395-407.
    I provide a manipulation-style argument against classical compatibilism—the claim that freedom to do otherwise is consistent with determinism. My question is simple: if Diana really gave Ernie free will, why isn't she worried that he won't use it precisely as she would like? Diana's non-nervousness, I argue, indicates Ernie's non-freedom. Arguably, the intuition that Ernie lacks freedom to do otherwise is stronger than the direct intuition that he is simply not responsible; this result highlights the importance of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  45.  29
    ‘If things were simple...’: complexity in education.Brent Davis & Dennis Sumara - 2010 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 16 (4):856-860.
  46.  28
    Indivisible Parts and Extended Objects.Dean W. Zimmerman - 1996 - The Monist 79 (1):148-180.
    Physical boundaries and the earliest topologists. Topology has a relatively short history; but its 19th century roots are embedded in philosophical problems about the nature of extended substances and their boundaries which go back to Zeno and Aristotle. Although it seems that there have always been philosophers interested in these matters, questions about the boundaries of three-dimensional objects were closest to center stage during the later medieval and modern periods. Are the boundaries of an object actually existing, less-than-three-dimensional parts of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  47. A simple question?Rodney Bomford - 2006 - In David M. Black (ed.), Psychoanalysis and Religion in the Twenty-First Century: Competitors or Collaborators? Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Concepts, communication, and the relevance of philosophy to human rights: A response to Randall Peerenboom.Stephen C. Angle - 2005 - Philosophy East and West 55 (2):320-324.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Concepts, Communication, and the Relevance of Philosophy to Human Rights:A Response to Randall PeerenboomStephen C. AngleRandy Peerenboom has paid me the enormous compliment of thinking it worthwhile to engage in sustained, critical dialogue with my book. In this response to his review essay, I attempt to return the compliment. I focus on issues surrounding concepts and communication, since that is where Peerenboom puts his emphasis. Near the end, I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  13
    Simple Questions.Talat Abbasi - 1987 - Feminist Studies 13 (1):83.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. On the Very Idea of Sex with Robots.Mark Migotti & Nicole Wyatt - 2018 - In John Danaher & Neil McArthur (eds.), Robot Sex: Social Implications and Ethical. MIT. pp. 15-27.
    In this chapter, we focus on the simple sounding question: What is it to have sex? On the assumption that having sex is what you do with all and only your sexual part-ners, this offers a way of focusing the question: What would it take for a sex robot to be a sex partner? In order to understand the significance of the development of robots with whom (or which) we can have sex, we need to know what (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 999