Indivisible Parts and Extended Objects

The Monist 79 (1):148-180 (1996)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Physical boundaries and the earliest topologists. Topology has a relatively short history; but its 19th century roots are embedded in philosophical problems about the nature of extended substances and their boundaries which go back to Zeno and Aristotle. Although it seems that there have always been philosophers interested in these matters, questions about the boundaries of three-dimensional objects were closest to center stage during the later medieval and modern periods. Are the boundaries of an object actually existing, less-than-three-dimensional parts of the object—that is, are solids bounded by two-dimensional surfaces, surfaces by one-dimensional “edges” or “physical lines”, edges by dimensionless “simples”? If not, how does a perfectly spherical object manage to touch a perfectly flat object—what part of the sphere is in immediate contact with the plane, if the sphere has no unextended parts? But if such parts be admitted, are we not then saddled with “actual infinities” of simples, lines, and surfaces spread throughout each continuous object—the boundaries of all the object’s internal parts? Does it help to say that these internal boundaries exist only “potentially”?

Similar books and articles

Hudson on Location. [REVIEW]Josh Parsons - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2):427 - 435.
Objects, Their Parts, and Essences.Karol Polcyn - 2012 - Filozofia Nauki 20 (3).
Zeno objects and supervenience.Simon Prosser - 2009 - Analysis 69 (1):18 - 26.
Henry More and Nicolas Malebranche's Critiques of Spinoza.Jasper Reid - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (3):764-792.
Simply possible.Theodore Sider - 2000 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (3):585-590.
On Stages, Worms, and Relativity.Yuri Balashov - 2002 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 50:223-.
Relativity and persistence.Yuri Balashov - 2000 - Philosophy of Science 67 (3):562.
Composition as a fiction.Gideon Rosen & Cian Dorr - 2002 - In Richard Gale (ed.), The Blackwell Companion to Metaphysics. Blackwell. pp. 151--174.
Endurantist and perdurantist accounts of persistence.Maureen Donnelly - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 154 (1):27 - 51.
A tale of two simples.Joshua Spencer - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 148 (2):167 - 181.
Parts and wholes.Kris McDaniel - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (5):412-425.

Analytics

Added to PP
2011-01-09

Downloads
1,618 (#6,055)

6 months
163 (#17,770)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Dean Zimmerman
Rutgers University - New Brunswick

Citations of this work

Location and Mereology.Cody Gilmore, Claudio Calosi & Damiano Costa - 2013 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Mereological commitments.Achille C. Varzi - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (4):283–305.
Simples and gunk.Hud Hudson - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (2):291–302.
Spatial Reasoning and Ontology: Parts, Wholes, and Locations.Achille C. Varzi - 2007 - In Marco Aiello, Ian E. Pratt-Hartmann & Johan van Benthem (eds.), Handbook of Spatial Logics. Springer Verlag. pp. 945-1038.

View all 32 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Theories of masses and problems of constitution.Dean W. Zimmerman - 1995 - Philosophical Review 104 (1):53-110.
Could Extended Objects Be Made Out of Simple Parts?Dean W. Zimmerman - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (1):1-29.
Individuals and points.Bowman L. Clark - 1985 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 26 (1):61-75.

View all 15 references / Add more references