Results for 'procreative justice'

988 found
Order:
  1. Procreative Justice Reconceived: Shifting the Moral Gaze.Emmalon Davis - 2024 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association (First View):1-23.
    This paper reconsiders Tommie Shelby's (2016) analysis of procreation in poor black communities. I identify three conceptual frames within which Shelby situates his analysis—feminization, choice-as-control, and moralization. I argue that these frames should be rejected on conceptual, empirical, and moral grounds. As I show, this framing engenders a flawed understanding of poor black women's procreative lives. I propose an alternative framework for reconceiving the relationship between poverty and procreative justice, one oriented around reproductive flourishing instead of reproductive (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  20
    Procreative Justice and genetic selection for skin colour.Herjeet Kaur Marway - 2023 - Bioethics 37 (4):389-398.
    Should nonprejudiced reproducers genetically select embryos for light skin under background conditions of racism and colourism, given that darker skin will be disadvantageous for their child? Many intuit that there are strong moral reasons not to select light skin in these contexts. I argue that existing procreative principles cannot adequately account for this judgement. Instead, I argue that a more compelling rationale for this intuition is that such selection completes an instance of race or colour injustice. Given this, I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. A Critical Take on Procreative Justice.Joona Räsänen, Andreas Bengtson, Hugo Cossette-Lefebvre & Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen - 2024 - Bioethics 38 (4):367-374.
    Herjeet Kaur Marway recently proposed the Principle of Procreative Justice, which says that reproducers have a strong moral obligation to avoid completing race and colour injustices through their selection choices. In this article, we analyze this principle and argue, appealing to a series of counterexamples, that some of the implications of Marway's Principle of Procreative Justice are difficult to accept. This casts doubt on whether the principle should be adopted. Also, we show that there are some (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Procreative Justice: A Contractualist Approach.Rivka M. Weinberg - 2001 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    My dissertation investigates the requirements of procreative justice. The procreative justice problem is that parents' interest in procreation conflicts with children's interest in optimal birth conditions. Intergenerational reciprocity is the principle that adjudicates this conflict: reciprocity dictates that children demand no more of their parents' procreative practices than they themselves are willing to abide by as adults and dig parents only procreate in accordance with principles dig they would have wanted their own parents to have (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  49
    Procreative justice: A contractualist account.Rivka M. Weinberg - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16 (4):405-425.
  6.  18
    Fairness, Costs, and Procreative Justice.Gideon Elford - 2023 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 24 (2).
    A commitment to holding persons responsible for the consequences of their choices has come to find a central expression in certain popular liberal egalitarian views. However, the basis for their commitment to responsibility remains imprecisely understood. Specifically, there is a failure to distinguish between two distinct grounds for holding persons responsible for the consequences of their choices. On the one hand there is a fairness-type basis for responsibility – that an agent’s being better or worse off than others in virtue (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Equality of resources and procreative justice.Paula Casal & Andrew Williams - 2004 - In Ronald Dworkin & Justine Burley (eds.), Dworkin and His Critics: With Replies by Dworkin. Blackwell. pp. 150--169.
  8.  15
    Equality of Resources and Procreative Justice.Paula Casal & Andrew Williams - 2004-01-01 - In Justine Burley (ed.), Dworkin and His Critics. Blackwell. pp. 150–169.
    This chapter contains section titled: I Welfarist and Resourcist Egalitarianism II Resource Egalitarianism and Procreation III Equality of Fortune IV Procreation and the Appeal to Fairness V Internalizing the Effects of Procreation VI Tolerating Externalities Acknowledgement.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9. Procreative-parenting, love's reasons and the demands of morality.Luara Ferracioli - 2018 - Philosophical Quarterly 68 (270):77-97.
    Many philosophers believe that the relationship between a parent and a child is objectively valuable, but few believe that there is any objective value in first creating a child in order to parent her. But if it is indeed true that all of the objective value of procreative-parenting comes from parenting, then it is hard to see how procreative-parenting can overcome two particularly pressing philosophical challenges. A first challenge is to show that it is morally permissible for prospective (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  10. Against procreative moral rights.Jake Earl - 2021 - Bioethics 36 (5):569-575.
    Many contemporary ethical debates turn on claims about the nature and extent of our alleged procreative moral rights: moral rights to procreate or not to procreate as we choose. In this article, I argue that there are no procreative moral rights, in that generally we do not have a distinctive moral right to procreate or not to procreate as we choose. However, interference with our procreative choices usually violates our nonprocreative moral rights, such as our moral rights (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  32
    Review essay / Procreative liberty.Bonnie Steinbock - 1996 - Criminal Justice Ethics 15 (1):67-74.
    John Robertson, Children of Choice: Freedom and the New Reproductive Technologies Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994, 281 pp.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  23
    Which “New Eugenics”? Expanding Access to Art, Respecting Procreative Liberty, and Protecting the Moral Equality of All Persons in an Era of Neoliberal Choice.Karey Harwood - 2020 - International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 13 (2):148-173.
    In The New Eugenics: Selective Breeding in an Era of Reproductive Technologies, Judith Daar advocates for increased access to assisted reproductive technologies and minimizes concerns about the potential “eugenic logic” of some procreative choices. Although Daar’s goal of expanded access is laudable, her argument suggests an unresolved tension between the moral equality of persons and individual reproductive freedom. Exploring that tension, this paper argues that efforts to expand access to ART must still grapple with the “eugenic mentality” of quality (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  88
    Beneficence, determinism and justice: An engagement with the argument for the genetic selection of intelligence.Kean Birch - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (1):12–28.
    ABSTRACTIn 2001, Julian Savulescu wrote an article entitled ‘Procreative Beneficence: Why We Should Select the Best Children’, in which he argued for the genetic selection of intelligence in children. That article contributes to a debate on whether genetic research on intelligence should be undertaken at all and, if so, should intelligence selection be available to potential parents. As such, the question of intelligence selection relates to wider issues concerning the genetic determination of behavioural traits, i.e. alcoholism. This article is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  14. Privacy and the.Justice William O. Douglas - 2001 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 68 (1).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Louis Althusser.Justice Duty - 1999 - In Jessica Evans & Stuart Hall (eds.), Visual Culture: The Reader. Sage Publications in Association with the Open University. pp. 317.
  16.  18
    The bible of justice.Justice T. Reason - 1970 - Green Bay, Wis.,: Justice T. Reason Publications.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. On Sense and Reflexivity.John Justice - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (7):351.
    Frege’s claim that proper names have senses has come to seem untenable following Kripke’s argument that names are rigid designators. It is commonly thought that if names had senses, their referents would vary with circumstances of evaluation. The article defends Frege’s claim by arguing that names have word-reflexive senses. This analysis of names’ senses does not violate Kripke’s noncircularity condition, and it differs crucially from related views of Bach and Katz. That names have reflexive senses confirms Frege’s own solution to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18.  91
    On sense and reflexivity.John Justice - 2001 - Journal of Philosophy 98 (7):351-364.
    "On Sense and Reflexivity" offers the answer to a crucial question that was posed, and left without a satisfactory answer, by Gottlob Frege in "On Sense and Reference" (1892): What is the sense of a proper name? The century-long failure to answer this question has been the main motivation and support for recent nondescriptional accounts of lexical singular terms.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  19.  25
    The Semantics of Rigid Designation.John Justice - 2004 - Ratio 16 (1):33-48.
    Frege's thesis that each singular term has a sense that determines its reference and serves as its cognitive value has come to be widely doubted. Saul Kripke argued that since names are rigid designators, their referents are not determined by senses. David Kaplan has argued that the rigid designation of indexical terms entails that they also lack referent–determining senses. Kripke's argument about names and Kaplan's argument about indexical terms differ, but each contains a false premise. The referents of both names (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. Dissending Opinion.Justice Scalia Joins As To & Dissenting In Part - 2008 - In Tom L. Beauchamp, Norman E. Bowie & Denis Gordon Arnold (eds.), Ethical Theory and Business. Pearson/Prentice Hall.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Procedural justice, legitimacy and social contexts.Anthony Bottoms & Justice Tankebe - 2021 - In Meyerson Denise, Catriona Mackenzie & Therese MacDermott (eds.), Procedural Justice and Relational Theory: Empirical, Philosophical, and Legal Perspectives. Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. of personality God wants man to possess and the supreme comfort as well as peace in which He wants every society to live.Justice Sheikh Ahmed Lemu - 1986 - In S. O. Abogunrin (ed.), Religion and Ethics in Nigeria. Daystar Press. pp. 172.
  23. Humanism and human rights in the third world.Justice Abdur Rahman Chowdhury - 1992 - In A. B. M. Mafizul Islam Patwari (ed.), Humanism and Human Rights in the Third World. Distributors, Aligarh Library.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Afterword.Justice A. K. Sikri - 2018 - In Salman Khurshid, Lokendra Malik & Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco (eds.), Dignity in the legal and political philosophy of Ronald Dworkin. New Delhi, India: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Supreme court of.Justice Steffen - forthcoming - Contemporary Issues in Bioethics.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Legitimation and Resistance: Police Reform in the (un) making.Justice Tankebe - 2010 - In Leonidas K. Cheliotis (ed.), Roots, Rites and Sites of Resistance: The Banality of Good. Palgrave-Macmillan.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Tarasoff v. Regents of the University of California.Justice Tobriner - 1999 - Bioethics: An Anthology 9.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Willa Boesak.Justice Truth - 1996 - In H. Russel Botman & Robin M. Petersen (eds.), To Remember and to Heal: Theological and Psychological Reflections on Truth and Reconciliation. Thorold's Africana Books [Distributor]. pp. 65.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Unified semantics of singular terms.John Justice - 2007 - Philosophical Quarterly 57 (228):363–373.
    Singular-term semantics has been intractable. Frege took the referents of singular terms to be their semantic values. On his account, vacuous terms lacked values. Russell separated the semantics of definite descriptions from the semantics of proper names, which caused truth-values to be composed in two different ways and still left vacuous names without values. Montague gave all noun phrases sets of verb-phrase extensions for values, which created type mismatches when noun phrases were objects and still left vacuous names without values. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  19
    A shooting room view oj doomsday, William Eckhardt.Temporal Horizons oj Justice - 1997 - Mind 106 (421).
  31. Mill-Frege Compatibalism.John Justice - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Research 27:567-576.
    It is generally accepted that Mill’s classification of names as nonconnotative terms is incompatible with Frege’s thesis that names have senses. However, Milldescribed the senses of nonconnotative terms—without being aware that he was doing so. These are the senses for names that were sought in vain by Frege. When Mill’s and Frege’s doctrines are understood as complementary, they constitute a fully satisfactory theory of names.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  14
    1. Medical Technology and New Frontiers of Family Law.Justice M. D. Kirby - 1986 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 14 (3-4):113-119.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  19
    Medical Technology and New Frontiers of Family Law.Justice M. D. Kirby - 1986 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 14 (3-4):113-119.
  34.  20
    Bhagat Oinam.Distributive Justice - 2010 - In Shashi Motilal (ed.), Applied ethics and human rights: conceptual analysis and contextual applications. New York: Anthem Press. pp. 171.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Cecile Fabre.Global Distributive Justice & An Egalitarian Perspective - 2007 - In Daniel M. Weinstock (ed.), Global Justice, Global Institutions. University of Calgary Press. pp. 139.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Gillian Brock.Global Justice - 2007 - In Daniel M. Weinstock (ed.), Global Justice, Global Institutions. University of Calgary Press. pp. 31--109.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  23
    Gerald Gaus.Retributive Justice & Social Cooperation - 2011 - In Mark White (ed.), Retributivism: Essays on Theory and Policy. Oxford University Press. pp. 73.
  38.  18
    Minimal consequentialism, Peter Caws.Wild Justice - 1995 - Philosophy 70 (3).
  39. Racism and the limits of.Distributive Justice - 2001 - Public Affairs Quarterly 15 (3):271.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Robert J. van der Veen.Of Justice - 1984 - Philosophica 34 (2):103-126.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Thinking About Thinking.C. Justice - 1984 - Gnosis. A Journal of Philosophic Interest Montréal 2 (3):64-77.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  11
    Truth Be Told: Sense, Quantity, and Extension.John Justice - 2015 - New York: Peter Lang.
    Truth Be Told explains how truth and falsity result from relations that sentences and their constituents have to the circumstances at which they are evaluated. It offers a precise analysis of truth and a diagnosis of the Liar paradox. Current semantic theory employs generalized quantifiers as the extensions of noun phrases. The book provides simpler extensions for noun phrases. These permit intuitive compositions of truth-values and a diagnosis of the Liar and Grelling paradoxes.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  17
    The scottish enlightenment.Allegiance Justice - 2011 - In George Klosko (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 319.
  44.  61
    The semantics of rigid designation.John Justice - 2003 - Ratio 16 (1):33–48.
    Frege's thesis that each singular term has a sense that determines its reference and serves as its cognitive value has come to be widely doubted. Saul Kripke argued that since names are rigid designators, their referents are not determined by senses. David Kaplan has argued that the rigid designation of indexical terms entails that they also lack referent–determining senses. Kripke's argument about names and Kaplan's argument about indexical terms differ, but each contains a false premise. The referents of both names (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. Mill-Frege Compatibalism.John Justice - 2002 - Journal of Philosophical Research 27:567-576.
    It is generally accepted that Mill’s classification of names as nonconnotative terms is incompatible with Frege’s thesis that names have senses. However, Milldescribed the senses of nonconnotative terms—without being aware that he was doing so. These are the senses for names that were sought in vain by Frege. When Mill’s and Frege’s doctrines are understood as complementary, they constitute a fully satisfactory theory of names.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  29
    When “I’m Sorry” Cannot Be Said: The Evolution of Political Apology.Jacob Justice & Brett Bricker - 2022 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 55 (1):111-118.
    ABSTRACT Every social order depends on a pathway to atonement for those who breach behavioral expectations. However, observers from a variety of fields now agree that the United States has entered an age of non-apology, where the two words “I’m sorry” simply cannot be said, particularly by powerful men facing allegations of sexual misconduct. This essay draws attention to, and comments upon, this trend. We first identify the sociopolitical factors that have inaugurated the era of non-apology, namely growing political polarization. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  13
    Accentuation: A Key Factor of Native Languages in African Philosophy.John Justice Nwankwo - 2021 - International Journal of Philosophy 9 (3):178.
  48.  22
    African American women educators: a critical examination of their pedagogies, educational ideas, and activism from the nineteenth to the mid-twentieth century.Benjamin Justice - 2015 - British Journal of Educational Studies 63 (1):103-104.
  49.  26
    Another look at “superstitions” in pigeons.Teresa C. Justice & Thomas A. Looney - 1990 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 28 (1):64-66.
  50.  18
    A Unified Theory of Names.John Justice - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 32:41-47.
    Theoreticians of names are currently split into two camps: Fregean and Millian. Fregean theorists hold that names have referent-determining senses that account for such facts as the change of content with the substitution of co-referential names and the meaningfulness of names without bearers. Their enduring problem has been to state these senses. Millian theorists deny that names have senses and take courage from Kripke's arguments that names are rigid designators. If names had senses, it seems that their referents should vary (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 988