Results for 'Knowledge for its own sake'

989 found
Order:
  1. Pursuing Knowledge for Its Own Sake amidst a World of Poverty: Reconsidering Balogun on Philosophy’s Relevance.Thaddeus Metz - 2019 - Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 8 (2):1-18.
    In this article I critically discuss Professor Oladele Abiodun Balogun’s reflections on the proper final ends of doing philosophy and related sorts of abstract, speculative, or theoretical inquiry. Professor Balogun appears to argue that one should undertake philosophical studies only insofar as they are likely to make a practical difference to people’s lives, particularly by contributing to politico-economic development, or, in other words, that one should eschew seeking knowledge for its own sake. However, there is one line of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2. Higher Education, Knowledge For Its Own Sake, and an African Moral Theory.Thaddeus Metz - 2009 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 28 (6):517-536.
    I seek to answer the question of whether publicly funded higher education ought to aim intrinsically to promote certain kinds of ‘‘blue-sky’’ knowledge, knowledge that is unlikely to result in ‘‘tangible’’ or ‘‘concrete’’ social benefits such as health, wealth and liberty. I approach this question in light of an African moral theory, which contrasts with dominant Western philosophies and has not yet been applied to pedagogical issues. According to this communitarian theory, grounded on salient sub-Saharan beliefs and practices, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  3.  48
    Doing Something for Its Own Sake.T. S. Champlin - 1987 - Philosophy 62 (239):31 - 47.
    The idea of doing something for its own sake interests me for two reasons. First, I should like to understand better two opposing reactions that I have felt on coming across the phrase ‘for its own sake’ used in earnest. When told that knowledge is worth pursuing for its own sake and that this is what the study of science at a university ought to be like—not an adjunct to commercially motivated research in a product I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  31
    Doing Something for its Own Sake.T. S. Champlin - 1987 - Philosophy 62 (239):31-47.
    The idea of doing something for its own sake interests me for two reasons. First, I should like to understand better two opposing reactions that I have felt on coming across the phrase ‘for its own sake’ used in earnest. When told that knowledge is worth pursuing for its own sake and that this is what the study of science at a university ought to be like—not an adjunct to commercially motivated research in a product I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5. A distinction in value: Intrinsic and for its own sake.Wlodek Rabinowicz & Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen - 2000 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (1):33–51.
    The paper argues that the final value of an object-i.e., its value for its own sake-need not be intrinsic. Extrinsic final value, which accrues to things (or persons) in virtue of their relational rather than internal features, cannot be traced back to the intrinsic value of states that involve these things together with their relations. On the contrary, such states, insofar as they are valuable at all, derive their value from the things involved. The endeavour to reduce thing-values to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  6.  55
    Does inequality matter—for its own sake?Alan Ryan - 2002 - Social Philosophy and Policy 19 (1):225-243.
    This is a simple essay. It raises a familiar question about equality, adduces a very small amount of empirical evidence about the social consequences of equality as distinct from prosperity, and broods on the difficulty of providing a really persuasive answer to the question raised. I begin with the view that there simply cannot be anything intrinsically wrong with inequality, move on to the view that there are extrinsic reasons for anxiety, dividing these into conceptual and empirical reasons, though without (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. A Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and for its own sake.Wlodek Rabinowicz & Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen - 2000 - In Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen & Michael J. Zimmerman (eds.), Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. Springer. pp. 115--129.
    The paper argues that the final value of an object-i.e., its value for its own sake-need not be intrinsic. Extrinsic final value, which accrues to things in virtue of their relational rather than internal features, cannot be traced back to the intrinsic value of states that involve these things together with their relations. On the contrary, such states, insofar as they are valuable at all, derive their value from the things involved. The endeavour to reduce thing-values to state-values is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  8.  45
    II-A Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and For Its Own Sake.Wlodek Rabinowicz & Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen - 2000 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (1):33-51.
    The paper argues that the final value of an object, i.e., its value for its own sake, need not be intrinsic. It need not supervene on the object’s internal properties. Extrinsic final value, which accrues to things in virtue of their relational features, cannot be traced back to the intrinsic value of states that involve these things together with their relations. On the opposite, such states, insofar as they are valuable at all, derive their value from the things involved. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  9.  11
    Does reason command itself for its own sake?Frederick Kraenzel - 1991 - Journal of Value Inquiry 25 (3):263-270.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. History of science for its own sake?Steve Fuller - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (4):95-99.
  11.  19
    Reimagining “Learning for Its Own Sake” in Liberal Education.Caitlin Brust - 2021 - Philosophy of Education 77 (1):150-163.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Does equality matter for its own sake? : an experimental examination of the leveling down objection.Christopher Freiman & Adam Lerner - 2023 - In Matthew Lindauer, James R. Beebe & Justin Sytsma (eds.), Advances in Experimental Political Philosophy. New York: Bloomsbury.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  35
    A Distinction in Value: Intrinsic and for Its Own Sake.Wlodek Rabinowicz & Toni R.?Nnow-Rasmussen - 2000 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 100 (1):33 - 51.
    The paper argues that the final value of an object-i.e., its value for its own sake-need not be intrinsic. Extrinsic final value, which accrues to things (or persons) in virtue of their relational rather than internal features, cannot be traced back to the intrinsic value of states that involve these things together with their relations. On the contrary, such states, insofar as they are valuable at all, derive their value from the things involved. The endeavour to reduce thing-values to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  14.  57
    Aristotle on Choosing Virtuous Action for its Own Sake.Yannig Luthra - 2015 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96 (3):423-441.
    While Aristotle claims that virtuous actions are choiceworthy for their own sakes, he also claims that many virtuous actions are to be chosen as instrumental means to securing further ends. It would seem that an action is choiceworthy for its own sake only if it would be choiceworthy whether or not it served further ends. How, then, can such virtuous actions be choiceworthy for their own sakes? This article criticizes John Ackrill's and Jennifer Whiting's answers to this question. I (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  41
    Cruelty, Sadism, and the Joy of Inflicting Pain for its Own Sake.Daniel Statman - 2022 - Journal of Philosophical Research 47:23-42.
    The paper offers a theory of cruelty that includes the following claims: First, cruelty is best understood as a disposition to take delight in the very infliction of suffering on others. Thus understood, cruelty is the same phenomenon as that studied and operationalized by psychologists in the last decade or so under the heading of everyday sadism. Second, for people to be cruel, they need not have proper understanding of the moral standing of their victims. Third, ascriptions of cruelty do (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. On the Desire to Do One's Duty for Its Own Sake.John Ladd - 1958 - In Abraham Irving Melden (ed.), Essays in moral philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  28
    Whether and to What Extent Consumers Demand Fair Pricing Behavior for Its Own Sake.Adam Nguyen & Juan Meng - 2013 - Journal of Business Ethics 114 (3):529-547.
    This article contributes to scholarly understanding of the significance of procedural fairness in pricing contexts. It has been widely recognized that price fairness judgments concern both the outcome (fair price) and the procedure leading to the outcome (fair pricing). However, extant research has traditionally viewed procedural fairness as a means to outcome fairness. According to this instrumental view, procedural fairness is a component or antecedent of outcome fairness, but has no direct effects on consumers’ responses to prices. Building on the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  26
    Not for Their Own Sake: Species and the Riddle of Individuality.Gary Borjesson - 1999 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (4):867 - 896.
    SPECIES INITIALLY APPEAR TO US AS OMNIPRESENT, familiar, even as rather simple objects of our experience. On closer inspection, however, the appearance of intelligibility is supplanted by mystery. Although scientists now possess a commanding grasp of the general structure and function of biological species, there is as yet no consensus on the philosophical question of exactly what kind of entity species are. Are they class entities, as a traditional view has it? Or are species actual, substantial beings? If they are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  20
    Not for Their Own Sake.Gary Borjesson - 1999 - Review of Metaphysics 52 (4):867-896.
    SPECIES INITIALLY APPEAR TO US AS OMNIPRESENT, familiar, even as rather simple objects of our experience. On closer inspection, however, the appearance of intelligibility is supplanted by mystery. Although scientists now possess a commanding grasp of the general structure and function of biological species, there is as yet no consensus on the philosophical question of exactly what kind of entity species are. Are they class entities, as a traditional view has it? Or are species actual, substantial beings? If they are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  51
    Attending to Works of Art for Their Own Sake in Art Evaluation and Analysis: Carroll and Stecker on Aesthetic Experience.Víctor Durà-Vilà - 2016 - British Journal of Aesthetics 56 (1):83-99.
    Noël Carroll denies and Robert Stecker affirms that it is a necessary condition of aesthetic experience that it should be valued for its own sake. I make use of their controversy to argue for the psychological impossibility of discharging very common practices of art evaluation and analysis without undergoing an aesthetic experience valued for its own sake. By way of supporting my thesis and also making progress in Stecker and Carroll’s dispute about aesthetic experience, I analyse their methodological (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  63
    How to Value the Liberal Arts for Their Own Sake without Intrinsic Values.Erik W. Schmidt - 2010 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 17 (2):37-47.
    I argue that there is an important problem with framing the value of a liberal arts education through a contrast between intrinsic and instrumental value. The paper breaks down into three sections. First, I argue that the traditional divide between intrinsic and instrumental value conflates two pairs of related concepts and that distinguishing those concepts frees us from an important impasse found in contemporary discussions about the liberal arts. Second, I argue that a liberal arts education is only intelligible as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. The Search for Relevance in Knowledge Management: An Ontological Perspective.Sidharta Chatterjee & Sujoy Dey - 2019 - IUP Journal of Knowledge Management 17 (1):53-66.
    The significance of and the role played by Knowledge Management (KM) is ever increasing in today's business and organizational decision-making environment. This paper attempts to underline the importance of organizing knowledge not for its own sake, but for its efficient use in organizational decision making. The tremendous explosion of knowledge resources, both electronic and conventional, within the last few decades calls for an understanding of how knowledge is organized for management of data and information. This (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  18
    A Russellian Plea for ‘Useless’ Knowledge: Role of Freedom in Education.Jahnabi Deka - 2020 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 40 (1):23-37.
    While thrusting the importance of knowledge, Bertrand Russell highlights one special utility of it, i.e., knowledge promotes a widely contemplative habit of mind; and such knowledge, he terms ‘useless’. For Russell, the habit of contemplation is the capacity of rationalized enquiry which enables individuals to consider all questions in a tentative and impartial manner, frees them from dogmas and encourages the expression of a wide diversity of views. Besides ‘useless’ knowledge, Russell admits the importance of ‘useful’ (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  4
    Knowledge as value: illumination through critical prisms.Ian Morley & Mira Crouch (eds.) - 2008 - New York, NY: Rodopi.
    This book considers the place and value of knowledge in contemporary society. “Knowledge” is not a self-evident concept: both its denotations and connotations are historically situated. Since the Enlightenment, knowledge has been a matter of discovery through effort, and “knowledge for its own sake” a taken-for-granted ideal underwriting progressive education as a process which not only taught “for” and “about” something, but also ennobled the soul. While this ideal has not been explicitly rejected, in recent (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. What is in it for me? The benefits of diversity in scientific communities.Carla Fehr - 2011 - In Heidi Grasswick (ed.), Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science: Power in Knowledge. New York: Springer. pp. 133-154.
    I investigate the reciprocal relationship between social accounts of knowledge production and efforts to increase the representation of women and some minorities in the academy. In particular, I consider the extent to which feminist social epistemologies such as Helen Longino’s critical contextual empiricism can be employed to argue that it is in researchers’ epistemic interests to take active steps to increase gender diversity. As it stands, critical contextual empiricism does not provide enough resources to succeed at this task. However, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  26.  11
    Cardinal John Henry Newman and ‘the ideal state and purpose of a university’: nurse education, research and practice development for the twenty‐first century.Gary Rolfe - 2012 - Nursing Inquiry 19 (2):98-106.
    ROLFE G. Nursing Inquiry 2012; 19: 98–106 [Epub ahead of print]Cardinal John Henry Newman and ‘the ideal state and purpose of a university’: nurse education, research and practice development for the twenty‐first centuryCardinal John Henry Newman’s book, The Idea of a University, first published in the mid nineteenth century, is often invoked as the epitome of the liberal Enlightenment University in discussions and debates about the role and purpose of nurse education. In this article I will examine Newman’s book in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27. Knowledge of Our Own Beliefs.Sherrilyn Roush - 2016 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (3):45-69.
    There is a widespread view that in order to be rational we must mostly know what we believe. In the probabilistic tradition this is defended by arguments that a person who failed to have this knowledge would be vulnerable to sure loss, or probabilistically incoherent. I argue that even gross failure to know one's own beliefs need not expose one to sure loss, and does not if we follow a generalization of the standard bridge principle between first-order and second-order (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  28.  73
    Curiosity, Forbidden Knowledge, and the Reformation of Natural Philosophy in Early Modern England.Peter Harrison - 2001 - Isis 92:265-290.
    [Introduction]: Curiosity is now widely regarded, with some justification, as a vital ingredient of the inquiring mind and, more particularly, as a crucial virtue for the practitioner of the pure sciences. We have become accustomed to associate curiosity with innocence and, in its more mature manifestations, with the pursuit of truth for its own sake. It was not always so. The sentiments expressed in Sir John Davies's poem, published on the eve of the seventeenth century, paint a somewhat different (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  29. Knowledge of Goodness.Colin McGinn - 1997 - In Ethics, evil, and fiction. New York: Oxford University Press.
    In this chapter, McGinn argues that ethical knowledge belongs to a distinct epistemological category from scientific knowledge. Pursuing an analogy with mathematics and modern linguistics, McGinn argues that ethical truths are a priori, innate truths, and in this respect ethics is at least as respectable as science; indeed, epistemologically, it is on a par with logic and mathematics. A key difference between science and ethics is that moral truth, unlike scientific truth, is not coercive. Therefore, moral truth has (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  20
    Some Reflections on the Ethics of Knowledge and Belief.Jonathan Harrison - 1987 - Religious Studies 23 (3):325 - 336.
    Knowledge is desirable both for its own sake and because without it we will not be able to take the right means to whatever ends we happen to have. Much knowledge is interesting to oneself and others as well as useful, and a man without it will be an impoverished bore, as well as being unsuccessful in his enterprises.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  36
    Universities in the New Knowledge Landscape: Tensions, Challenges, Change—An Introduction.Andrea Bonaccorsi, Cinzia Daraio & Aldo Geuna - 2010 - Minerva 48 (1):1-4.
    In the last decades of the twentieth century universities in Europe and other OECD countries have undergone a profound transformation. They have evolved from mainly élite institutions for teaching and research to large (public and private) organisations responsible for mass higher education and the production and distribution of new knowledge. Increasingly, new knowledge is produced by universities not only for its own sake but also for potential economic gains.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32.  24
    Can ‘Philosophy for Children’ Improve Primary School Attainment?Stephen Gorard, Nadia Siddiqui & Beng Huat See - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (4).
    There are tensions within formal education between imparting knowledge and the development of skills for handling that knowledge. In the primary school sector, the latter can also be squeezed out of the curriculum by a focus on basic skills such as literacy and numeracy. What happens when an explicit attempt is made to develop young children's reasoning—both in terms of their apparent cognitive abilities and their basic skills? This paper reports an independent evaluation of an in-class intervention called (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33.  61
    Can ‘Philosophy for Children’ Improve Primary School Attainment?Stephen Gorard, Nadia Siddiqui & Beng Huat See - 2017 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 51 (1):5-22.
    There are tensions within formal education between imparting knowledge and the development of skills for handling that knowledge. In the primary school sector, the latter can also be squeezed out of the curriculum by a focus on basic skills such as literacy and numeracy. What happens when an explicit attempt is made to develop young children's reasoning—both in terms of their apparent cognitive abilities and their basic skills? This paper reports an independent evaluation of an in-class intervention called (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34.  32
    Can ‘Philosophy for Children’ Improve Primary School Attainment?Gorard Stephen, Siddiqui Nadia & S. E. E. Beng Huat - 2017 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 51 (1):5-22.
    There are tensions within formal education between imparting knowledge and the development of skills for handling that knowledge. In the primary school sector, the latter can also be squeezed out of the curriculum by a focus on basic skills such as literacy and numeracy. What happens when an explicit attempt is made to develop young children's reasoning—both in terms of their apparent cognitive abilities and their basic skills? This paper reports an independent evaluation of an in-class intervention called (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35. Why We Should Prefer Knowledge.Steven L. Reynolds - 1981 - In Felicia Ackerman (ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 79–93.
    This chapter contains sections titled: References.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  90
    On the Value of Scientific Knowledge.Lars Bergström - 1987 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 30 (1):53-63.
    Presumably, most scientists believe that scientific knowledge is intrinsically good, i.e. good in itself, apart from consequences. This doctrine should be rejected. The arguments which are usually given for it — e.g. by philosophers like W.D. Ross, R. Brandt, and W. Frankena — are quite inconclusive. In particular, it may be doubted whether knowledge is in fact desired for its own sake, and even i f it is, this would not support the doctrine. However, the doctrine is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  14
    Translation on its own terms? Toward education for global culture.Naoko Saito - 2017 - Ethics and Education 12 (1):18-22.
    Roger Ames’ keynote provides a powerful orientation for thinking about translation. Against the background of his outstanding research career as a mediator between East and West, he offers a clear vision of global cultivation through what he calls ‘cultural translation.’ Encouraging and insightful as Ames’ account of translation is, and although I am sympathetic to his attempt to do justice to the excluded, peripheral voice of philosophy in the canon of global culture, I would like to address some further philosophical (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  18
    On the Value of Scientific Knowledge.Lars Bergström - 1987 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 30 (1):53-63.
    Presumably, most scientists believe that scientific knowledge is intrinsically good, i.e. good in itself, apart from consequences. This doctrine should be rejected. The arguments which are usually given for it — e.g. by philosophers like W.D. Ross, R. Brandt, and W. Frankena — are quite inconclusive. In particular, it may be doubted whether knowledge is in fact desired for its own sake, and even i f it is, this would not support the doctrine. However, the doctrine is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Hidden Costs of Inquiry: Exploitation, World-Travelling and Marginalized Lives.Audrey Yap - 2021 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 31 (2):153-173.
    There are many good reasons to learn about the lives of people who have less social privilege than we do. We might want to understand their circumstances in order to have informed opinions on social policy, or to make our institutions more inclusive. We might also want to cultivate empathy for its own sake. Much of this knowledge is gained through social scientific or humanistic research into others' lives. The entitlement to theorize about or study the lives of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  22
    Pritchard’s Case for Veritism.John Greco - 2021 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 58 (4):46-53.
    In his “In Defense of Veritism”, Duncan Pritchard reconsiders the case for epistemic value truth monism, or the thesis that truth is the sole fundamental epistemic good. I begin by clarifying Pritchard’s thesis, and then turn to an evaluation of Pritchard’s defense. By way of clarification, Pritchard understands “fundamental” value to be non-instrumental value. Accordingly, Pritchard’s veritism turns out to be the thesis that truth is the sole epistemic good with non-instrumental epistemic value, all other epistemic goods being valuable in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  46
    Descartes’s Language Test for Rationality.Marie I. George - 2009 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 83 (1):107-125.
    Contrary to Michael Miller, I maintain that Descartes’s language test adequately distinguishes humans from non-human animals, and that the bonobosKanzi and Panbanisha have not passed it. Miller accepts Descartes’s language test as a good test for true language usage, but denies that it is an adequate test for the presence or absence of reason. I argue that it is a good test for reason, for normal rational beings eventually recognize the desirableness of knowledge of the world for its own (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  26
    A Critique of Science Education as Sociopolitical Action from the Perspective of Liberal Education.Yannis Hadzigeorgiou - 2015 - Science & Education 24 (3):259-280.
    This paper outlines the rationale underpinning the conception of science education as sociopolitical action, and then presents a critique of such a conception from the perspective of liberal education. More specifically, the paper discusses the importance of the conception of science education as sociopolitical action and then raises questions about the content of school science, about the place and value of scientific inquiry, and about the opportunities students have for self-directed inquiry. The central idea behind the critique is that a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43. How Uncertainty Interacts with Ethical Values in Climate Change Research.Casey Helgeson, Wendy Parker & Nancy Tuana - forthcoming - In Linda Mearns, Chris Forest, Hayley Fowler, Robert Lempert & Robert Wilby (eds.), Uncertainty in Climate Change Research: An Integrated Approach. Springer.
    Like all human activities, scientific research is infused with values. Scientific discovery can, for example, be valued as an end in itself. The phrase ethical values is an umbrella term for much of what people care about aside from knowledge for its own sake. Ethical values encompass reasons for caring about the harms caused by climate impacts or the injustice of how those harms are distributed. The closer that research gets to informing real-world actions, the more the design (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. A Dilemma about the Final Ends of Higher Education -- and a Resolution.Thaddeus Metz - 2013 - Kagisano (The Higher Education Discussion Series) 9:23-41.
    In this article, written for the generally educated reader, I summarize my latest thinking about a dilemma that I believe current theoretical reflection faces about the proper ultimate aims of a public university. Specifically, I make the following three major points: (1) On the one hand, all dominant theories of how properly to spend public resources entail that academics should not pursue knowledge for its own sake and should rather devote their energies toward promoting some concrete public good (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  65
    The boundaries of law and the purpose of legal philosophy.Danny Priel - 2008 - Law and Philosophy 27 (6):643 - 695.
    Many of the current debates in jurisprudence focus on articulating the boundaries of law. In this essay I challenge this approach on two separate grounds. I first argue that if such debates are to be about law, their purported subject, they ought to pay closer attention to the practice. When such attention is taken it turns out that most of the debates on the boundaries of law are probably indeterminate. I show this in particular with regard to the debate between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  63
    A Dilemma Regarding Academic Freedom and Public Accountability in Higher Education.Thaddeus Metz - 2010 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 44 (4):529-549.
    The aim of this article is to establish that current thought about the point of a publicly funded university faces a dilemma. On the one hand, influential and attractive ‘macro’-level principles about how state resources ought to be accountably used entail that academic freedom should be utilised solely for the sake of social justice or some other concrete public good. Standard theories of public morality entail that an academic’s responsibility is entirely to be ‘responsive’ or ‘relevant’ to her social (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  13
    On Fundamentals: an Adventure: PHILOSOPHY.Douglas Fawcett - 1932 - Philosophy 7 (28):381-393.
    Most men experience from time to time a wish to know something about the character of the larger reality in which they live, move, and have their being; something much more fundamental than any department of research classed as “scientific” can provide. And the most incurably practical of us has good reason for cherishing this wish. Metaphysics, i.e. inquiry into the general nature of reality, makes appeal first to the contemplative student interested in knowledge for its own sake, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  10
    Science in a Democratic Society by Philip Kitcher (review).Henry S. Richardson - 2014 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 24 (1):106-109.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Science in a Democratic Society by Philip KitcherHenry S. RichardsonReview: Philip Kitcher, Science in a Democratic Society, Prometheus Books, 2011In examining the place of science in a democratic society, Philip Kitcher is ultimately asking what standards scientific activity is answerable to. Here, as in Science, Truth, and Democracy (Oxford University Press, 2001), he rejects two extreme possibilities: first, the suggestion that science is autonomous, in the sense that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. For Community's Sake: A (Self-Respecting) Kantian Account of Forgiveness.Kate A. Moran - forthcoming - Proceedings of the XI International Kant-Kongress.
    This paper sketches a Kantian account of forgiveness and argues that it is distinguished by three features. First, Kantian forgiveness is best understood as the revision of the actions one takes toward an offender, rather than a change of feeling toward an offender. Second, Kant’s claim that forgiveness is a duty of virtue tells us that we have two reasons to sometimes be forgiving: forgiveness promotes both our own moral perfection and the happiness of our moral community. Third, we have (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50. Knowing Yourself and Being Worth Knowing.Jordan Mackenzie - 2018 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 4 (2):243-261.
    Philosophers have often understood self-knowledge's value in instrumentalist terms. Self-knowledge may be valuable as a means to moral self-improvement and self-satisfaction, while its absence can lead to viciousness and frustration. These explanations, while compelling, do not fully explain the value that many of us place in self-knowledge. Rather, we have a tendency to treat self-knowledge as its own end. In this article, I vindicate this tendency by identifying a moral reason that we have to value and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 989