Results for 'moral good'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Christopher Winch.Good Lives & Moral Education - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 25 (1):129.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2. Divine moral goodness, supererogation and The Euthyphro Dilemma.Alfred Archer - 2016 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 79 (2):147-160.
    How can we make sense of God’s moral goodness if God cannot be subject to moral obligations? This question is troubling for divine command theorists, as if we cannot make sense of God’s moral goodness then it seems hard to see how God’s commands could be morally good. Alston argues that the concept of supererogation solves this problem. If we accept the existence of acts that are morally good but not morally required then we should (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  21
    Moral goodness and the truth of religious claims.Mark Smith - 1981 - Sophia 20 (1):17-24.
  4. Moral Goodness.W. D. Ross - 1930 - In The Right and the Good. Some Problems in Ethics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    This is the last of five chapters on good, and examines moral goodness. Ross explains the concept of morally good as either being a certain sort of character or being related in one of certain definite ways to a certain sort of character. The matter of what kinds of things are morally good is then addressed, and further advances made in defining moral goodness. These begin by considering Immanuel Kant's views on the desire to do (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  56
    Moral goodness, esteem, and acting from duty.Noah M. Lemos - 1991 - Journal of Value Inquiry 25 (2):103-117.
    There is a long tradition in moral philosophy which maintains that a necessary condition for moral goodness is that one act from a sense of duty. Kant is perhaps the best known and most discussed representative of this view, but one finds others prior to Kant, such as Butler and Price, and Kant's contemporaries, such as Reid, expressing similar ideas. Price, for example writes, ". . . what I have chiefly insisted on, is, that we characterize as virtuous (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  50
    Morality, goodness and love: A rhetoric for resource management.Craig Millar & Hong-Key Yoon - 2000 - Ethics, Place and Environment 3 (2):155 – 172.
    Resource development takes place through the transformation of social institutions. The moral dimension is of crucial importance in the evolution of associated management regimes. More than just a code of ethics, moralities are predicated on what is understood to be 'the good'. Recognition of the good requires a rhetoric beyond those of power and interest. This paper proposes a rhetoric of love. Within this conception of morality, the management of human relationships becomes understood as an unfolding cycle (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  35
    The Moral Good and the Natural Good in Kant's Ethics.John R. Silber - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 36 (2):397 - 437.
    THE heterogeneity of the good--its division into the moral good, as virtue, and the natural good, as happiness--is central to Kant's philosophy. In order to clarify and sustain this division, Kant was compelled to specify the valuational characteristics of each kind of good and their relation to one another. But in trying to analyze the good in its heterogeneity Kant faced a terminological difficulty. He could no longer speak simply of "the good" without (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  70
    Morally Good and Morally Right.John A. Oesterle - 1970 - The Monist 54 (1):31-39.
    Let us understand at the outset that by “morally good” we mean the state of possessing what is generally regarded as good character, rooted in virtue, in the broad sense of this term that embraces a variety of particular virtues such as courage, justice, temperance and the like. It is the meaning behind such popular expressions as ‘he is a man of upright character’, ‘a solid citizen’, or, simply, ‘he is a good man’. Let us understand by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  17
    The Moral Good and Normative Nature in the Aristotelian Ethics.Robert Geis - 2013 - Review of Metaphysics 67 (2):291-310.
    Nature as the source of moral ordinance in Aristotle received doubt with the publication of J. Donald Monan’s Moral Knowledge and Its Methodology in Aristotle. Arguing for an earlier versus later Aristotle, he opined for the φρόνιμος as Aristotle’s final word on the criterion for ethical right. “Normative Nature and the Moral Good in the Aristotelian Ethics” argues exegetically and on Aristotelian grounds the inaccuracy of such a view. As early as the Protrepticus, Nature as the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  90
    Morally Good Intentions.Michael Stocker - 1970 - The Monist 54 (1):124-141.
    In this paper I present an analysis of morally good intentions. My starting point is one version of what can be called The Traditional Analysis.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Moral Goodness.Richard Swinburne - 1989 - In Responsibility and atonement. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter distinguishes various kinds of moral goodness. Actions may be objectively good and/or subjectively good; and they may be supererogatory or obligatory. Actions may be objectively or subjectively bad, and wrong or merely infrarvetatory. There is goodness either in good actions being done naturally, or in their being done contrary to inclination. There are three kinds of goodness of character: agents may be naturally inclined to do actions that are in fact good, they may (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  15
    Morally Good Sense.Strachan Donnelley - 1993 - Hastings Center Report 23 (2):43-44.
    Book reviewed in this article: Can't We Make Moral Judgements? By Mary Midgley.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  12
    Moral Goodness Alone Is ‘Good Without Qualifications’.Josef Seifert - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 44:223-230.
    Kant says that moral values are ‘good without qualification.’ This assertion and similar remarks of Plato can be understood in terms of a return to moral data themselves in the following ways: 1. Moral values are objectively good and not relative to our judgments; 2. Moral goodness is intrinsic goodness grounded in the nature of acts and independent of our subjective satisfaction; 3. Moral goodness expresses in an essentially new and higher sense of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. The logic of moral goodness.Kam-Por Yu & 余錦波 - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. God’s moral goodness and supererogation.Elizabeth Drummond Young - 2013 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 73 (2):83-95.
    What do we understand by God’s goodness? William Alston claims that by answering this question convincingly, divine command theory can be strengthened against some major objections. He rejects the idea that God’s goodness lies in the area of moral obligations. Instead, he proposes that God’s goodness is best described by the phenomenon of supererogation. Joseph Lombardi, in response, agrees with Alston that God does not have moral obligations but says that having rejected moral obligation as the content (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  98
    Hunting as a Moral Good.Lawrence Cahoone - 2009 - Environmental Values 18 (1):67 - 89.
    I argue that hunting is not a sport, but a neo-traditional cultural trophic practice consistent with ecological ethics, including a meliorist concern for animal rights or welfare. Death by hunter is on average less painful than death in wild nature. Hunting achieves goods, including trophic responsibility, ecological expertise and a unique experience of animal inter-dependence. Hunting must then be not only permissible but morally good wherever: a) preservation of ecosystems or species requires hunting as a wildlife management tool; and/or (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17.  49
    Beauty as Propaganda.Robert Gooding-Williams - 2021 - Philosophical Topics 49 (1):13-33.
    This paper considers W.E.B. Du Bois’s short story, “Jesus Christ in Texas,” in the perspective of his analysis of the concept of beauty in Darkwater (1920); his exposition of the idea that “all art is propaganda” in “Criteria of Negro Art” (1926); and his moral psychology of white supremacy. On my account, Du Bois holds that beautiful art can help to undermine white supremacy by using representations of moral goodness to expand the white supremacist’s ethical horizons. To defend (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18. The Moral Good as a Relation between Persons.I. W. Phillips, A. Macbeath & H. F. Hallett - 1939 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 18:106-178.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  40
    Immediate Certainty and the Morally Good: Luther, Kierkegaard and Cognitive Psychology.Jörg Disse - 2020 - In Marius Timmann Mjaaland (ed.), The Reformation of Philosophy. Mohr Siebeck. pp. 109-118.
    I consider the relationship between the notion of certainty and the notion of a form of life. There are circumstances under which a feeling of certainty may become the ground for adopting a certain form of life. The forms of life I have in mind are those with a formal orientation towards the realization of the (morally) good for its own sake. The article proceeds in three steps: First I consider Luther’s certainty of salvation as a kind of inaugural (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  27
    Kantian Conceptions of Moral Goodness.John Campbell - 1983 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (4):527 - 550.
    There are two general views associated with Kant about the nature of morally good persons and their actions. One view is that one's actions have moral worth only if one is motivated by a sense of duty and not by inclination. The other view is that morally good persons are motivated by reason and not by desire. These two views are not always distinguished. But taken at face value, they do seem distinct. They seem distinct at least (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  27
    Against God’s Moral Goodness.Joseph L. Lombardi - 2005 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 79 (2):313-326.
    While denying that God has moral obligations, William Alston defends divine moral goodness based on God’s performance of supererogatory acts. The present article argues that an agent without obligations cannot perform supererogatory acts. Hence, divine moral goodness cannot be established on that basis. Defenses of divine moral obligation by Eleonore Stump and Nicholas Wolterstorff are also questioned. Against Stump, it is argued (among other things) that the temptations of Jesus do not establish the existence of a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  46
    The assessment of individual moral goodness.Raymond B. Chiu & Rick D. Hackett - 2016 - Business Ethics: A European Review 26 (1):31-46.
    In a field dominated by research on moral prescription and moral prediction, there is poor understanding of the place of moral perceptions in organizations alongside philosophical ethics and causal models of ethical outcomes. As leadership failures continue to plague organizational health and firms recognize the wide-ranging impact of subjective bias, scholars and practitioners need a renewed frame of reference from which to reconceptualize their current understanding of ethics as perceived in individuals. Based on an assessment and selection (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  23.  22
    Moral Judgment and its Impact on Business-to-Business Sales Performance and Customer Relationships.David J. Good & Charles H. Schwepker - 2011 - Journal of Business Ethics 98 (4):609 - 625.
    For many years, researchers and practitioners have sought out meaningful indicators of sales performance. Yet, as the concept of performance has broadened, the understanding of what makes up a successful seller, has become far more complicated. The complexity of buyer-seller relationships has changed therefore as the definition of sales performance has expanded, cultivating a growing interest in ethical/unethical actions since they could potentially have impacts on sales performance. Given this environment, the purpose of this study is to explore the impact (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  24.  11
    Morality, goodness and love: A rhetoric for resource management.Craig Millar & Hong-Key Yoon - 2000 - Philosophy and Geography 3 (2):155-172.
    Resource development takes place through the transformation of social institutions. The moral dimension is of crucial importance in the evolution of associated management regimes. More than just a code of ethics, moralities are predicated on what is understood to be ‘the good’. Recognition of the good requires a rhetoric beyond those of power and interest. This paper proposes a rhetoric of love. Within this conception of morality, the management of human relationships becomes understood as an unfolding cycle (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  13
    Moral Judgment and its Impact on Business-to-Business Sales Performance and Customer Relationships.Charles H. Schwepker & David J. Good - 2011 - Journal of Business Ethics 98 (4):609-625.
    For many years, researchers and practitioners have sought out meaningful indicators of sales performance. Yet, as the concept of performance has broadened, the understanding of what makes up a successful seller, has become far more complicated. The complexity of buyer–seller relationships has changed therefore as the definition of sales performance has expanded, cultivating a growing interest in ethical/unethical actions since they could potentially have impacts on sales performance. Given this environment, the purpose of this study is to explore the impact (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26.  13
    Sensitivity to moral goodness under different aesthetic contexts.Chenjing Wu, Hongyan Zhu, Yameng Zhang, Wei Zhang & Xianyou He - 2024 - Ethics and Behavior 34 (4):279-293.
    Does context influence our appreciation of beauty? To answer this question, two experiments were conducted to determine the effect of contextual aesthetics on the recognition of moral behavior. Experiment 1 demonstrated that individuals in a high-aesthetic context had a quicker recognition time for moral behavior than those in a low-aesthetic context. In a low-aesthetic context, individuals recognize immoral behavior more quickly than in a high aesthetic context. Individuals showed greater recognition rates for moral behavior in a high (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  77
    Does integrity require moral goodness?Jody L. Graham - 2001 - Ratio 14 (3):234–251.
    Most accounts of integrity agree that the person of integrity must have a relatively stable sense of who he is, what is important to him, and the ability to stand by what is most important to him in the face of pressure to do otherwise. But does integrity place any constraints on the kind of principles that the person of integrity stands for? In response to several recent accounts of integrity, I argue that it is not enough that a person (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  28.  63
    Are morally good actions ever free?Cory J. Clark, Adam Shniderman, Jamie B. Luguri, Roy F. Baumeister & Peter H. Ditto - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 63 (C):161-182.
  29.  11
    The Roots of Morality and the Nature of Moral Goodness.P. M. S. Hacker - 2020 - In The moral powers: a study of human nature. Hoboken, NJ, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 33–64.
    Von Wright argued that moral goodness is a derivative form of goodness. He proceeded to give an account of the moral goodness of an act, in terms of the good of man. Philosophical anthropology must render the phenomenon of morality intelligible. This chapter suggests that the roots of moral value lie in human sympathy, in maternal love, in intuitive recognition of the humanity of others, and in the nature of loving friendship. The sentiment of sympathy is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  36
    On the Absence of Moral Goodness in Hobbes’s Ethics.Johan Olsthoorn - 2020 - The Journal of Ethics 24 (2):241-266.
    This article reassesses Hobbes’s place in the history of ethics based on the first systematic analysis of his various classifications of formal goodness. The good was traditionally divided into three: profitably good, pleasurably good, and morally good. Across his works, Hobbes replaced the last with pulchrum—a decidedly non-moral form of goodness on his account. I argue that Hobbes’s dismissal of moral goodness was informed by his hedonist conception of the good and accompanied by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  47
    Moral Good and Ontological Good.Robert W. Schmidt - 1978 - New Scholasticism 52 (3):421-427.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Moral goodness as happiness according to Aristotle-formal definition and metaphysical prerequisites.H. Seidl - 1975 - Philosophisches Jahrbuch 82 (1):31-53.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  14
    Moral goodness and the human good.Erling Skorpen - 1968 - Journal of Value Inquiry 2 (2-3):137-156.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  37
    Autonomy: A Moral Good, Not a Moral Obsession.Daniel Callahan - 1984 - Hastings Center Report 14 (5):40-42.
  35.  20
    Moral Judgment and its Impact on Business-to-Business Sales Performance and Customer Relationships.Charles H. Schwepker & David J. Good - 2011 - Journal of Business Ethics 98 (4):609-625.
    For many years, researchers and practitioners have sought out meaningful indicators of sales performance. Yet, as the concept of performance has broadened, the understanding of what makes up a successful seller, has become far more complicated. The complexity of buyer–seller relationships has changed therefore as the definition of sales performance has expanded, cultivating a growing interest in ethical/unethical actions since they could potentially have impacts on sales performance. Given this environment, the purpose of this study is to explore the impact (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  86
    Against God’s Moral Goodness.Joseph L. Lombardi - 2005 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 79 (2):313-326.
    While denying that God has moral obligations, William Alston defends divine moral goodness based on God’s performance of supererogatory acts. The present article argues that an agent without obligations cannot perform supererogatory acts. Hence, divine moral goodness cannot be established on that basis. Defenses of divine moral obligation by Eleonore Stump and Nicholas Wolterstorff are also questioned. Against Stump, it is argued (among other things) that the temptations of Jesus do not establish the existence of a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37. From Duty and for the Sake of the Noble: Kant and Aristotle on Morally Good Action.Christine M. Korsgaard - 1996 - In Stephen Engstrom & Jennifer Whiting (eds.), Aristotle, Kant, and the Stoics: Rethinking Happiness and Duty. Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle believes that an agent lacks virtue unless she enjoys the performance of virtuous actions, while Kant claims that the person who does her duty despite contrary inclinations exhibits a moral worth that the person who acts from inclination lacks. Despite these differences, this chapter argues that Aristotle and Kant share a distinctive view of the object of human choice and locus of moral value: that what we choose, and what has moral value, are not mere acts, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  38. Proximity’s dilemma and the difficulties of moral response to the distant sufferer.The Geography Of Goodness - 2003 - The Monist 86 (3):355-366.
    The work of the French Lithuanian Jewish philosopher, Emmanuel Levinas, describes a perceptive rethinking of the possibility of concrete acts of goodness in the world, a rethinking never more necessary than now, in the wake of the cruel realities of the twentieth century—ten million dead in the First World War, forty million dead in the Second World War, Hiroshima, Nagasaki, the Soviet gulags, the grand slaughter of Mao’s “Great Leap Forward,” the pointless and gory Vietnam War, the Cambodian self-genocide and (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  34
    Are There Non-Moral Goods?Henry B. Veatch - 1978 - New Scholasticism 52 (4):471-499.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  19
    Music and Moral Goodness.Donald Walhout - 1995 - The Journal of Aesthetic Education 29 (1):5.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Gratitude to God for Our Own Moral Goodness.Robert J. Hartman - 2022 - Faith and Philosophy 39 (2):189-204.
    Someone owes gratitude to God for something only if God benefits her and is morally responsible for doing so. These requirements concerning benefit and moral responsibility generate reasons to doubt that human beings owe gratitude to God for their own moral goodness. First, moral character must be generated by its possessor’s own free choices, and so God cannot benefit moral character in human beings. Second, owed gratitude requires being morally responsible for providing a benefit, which rules (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. Concerning moral good and evil.Francis Hutcheson - 1997 - In Alexander Broadie (ed.), The Scottish Enlightenment: an anthology. Edinburgh: Canongate Books. pp. 119--142.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  54
    The Moral Metacognition Scale: Development and Validation.Joan M. McMahon & Darren J. Good - 2016 - Ethics and Behavior 26 (5):357-394.
    Scholars have advocated for the inclusion of metacognition in our understanding of the ethical decision making process and in support of moral learning. An instrument to measure metacognition as a domain-specific capacity related to ethical decision making is not found in the current literature. This research describes the development and validation of the 20-item Moral Metacognition Scale. Psychometric properties of the scale were assessed by exploration and confirmation of the factor structure, and the demonstration of convergent, discriminant, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. On justifying an account of moral goodness to each individual: contractualism, utilitarianism, and prioritarianism.Richard Pettigrew - manuscript
    Many welfarists wish to assign to each possible state of the world a numerical value that measures something like its moral goodness. How are we to determine this quantity? This paper proposes a contractualist approach: a legitimate measure of moral goodness is one that could be justified to each member of the population in question. How do we justify a measure of moral goodness to each individual? Each individual recognises the measure of moral goodness must be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Virtue is a Great Moral Good.Bradford Cokelet - manuscript
    According to Aristotelian virtue ethicists, virtue is a great moral good that contributes to, but cannot be reduced to, an agent's welfare. In addition, they hold that the value of virtue is different from, and in some sense greater than, the agent-neutral intrinsic goodness that consequentialists attribute to states of affair. According to Thomas Hurka (1998, 2003, 2011), these fundamental Aristotelian views are indefensible. In this paper, I rebuff Hurka's skepticism and identify an Aristotelian view that stands fast (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  43
    What is a Person?: Rethinking Humanity, Social Life, and the Moral Good From the Person Up.Christian Smith - 2010 - University of Chicago Press.
    What is a person? This fundamental question is a perennial concern of philosophers and theologians. But, Christian Smith here argues, it also lies at the center of the social scientist’s quest to interpret and explain social life. In this ambitious book, Smith presents a new model for social theory that does justice to the best of our humanistic visions of people, life, and society. Finding much current thinking on personhood to be confusing or misleading, Smith finds inspiration in critical realism (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  47. Nietzsche on Slave Morality and Master Morality: Good Psychology, Bad Sociology.John-Michael Kuczynski - 2021 - Madison, WI, USA: Philosophypedia.
    Nietzsche distinguishes between “slave morality” (the morality of the weak) and “master morality” (the morality of the strong), and he believes the structure of modern society to be rooted in slave morality. According to Nietzsche, slave morality is the morality of modern “bourgeois” (commerce-based) society, whereas “master morality” was the morality of ancient caste-based societies. In this paper, I argue for the legitimacy of the distinction between these two kinds of morality but argue against Nietzsche's contention that contemporary (capitalist or (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  38
    Pro-Theism and the Added Value of Morally Good Agents.Myron A. Penner & Kirk Lougheed - 2015 - Philosophia Christi 17 (1):53-69.
    Pro-theism is the view that God’s existence would be good in that God’s existence increases the value of a world. Anti-theism is the view that God’s existence would decrease the value of a world. We develop and defend the morally good agent argument for pro-theism. The basic idea is that morally good agents tend to add value to states of affairs, and God, moral agent par excellence is no exception. Thus, we argue that the existence of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  49. Have Elephant Seals Refuted Aristotle? Nature, Function, and Moral Goodness.Micah Lott - 2012 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (3):353-375.
    An influential strand of neo-Aristotelianism, represented by writers such as Philippa Foot, holds that moral virtue is a form of natural goodness in human beings, analogous to deep roots in oak trees or keen vision in hawks. Critics, however, have argued that such a view cannot get off the ground, because the neo-Aristotelian account of natural normativity is untenable in light of a Darwinian account of living things. This criticism has been developed most fully by William Fitzpatrick in his (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  50.  91
    The Moral Aspect of Nonmoral Goods and Evils.I. What Admirable Immorality & Nonadmirable Morality Are - 1999 - Utilitas 11 (1).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000