Results for 'Arnold Boyd Levison'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1. Proof and the Case-by-Case Procedure.Arnold Boyd Levison - 1959 - Dissertation, University of Virginia
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  37
    Anthony Kenny and the cartesian circle.Fred Feldman & Arnold Boyd Levison - 1971 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 9 (4):491-496.
  3.  8
    Nature, History, and Existentialism and other Essays in the Philosophy of History.Karl Löwith & Arnold Boyd Levison - 1966 - Northwestern University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  39
    Anti-Semitic Surprises Found Throughout the Literary World.Arnold Ages & Ian Boyd - 1994 - The Chesterton Review 20 (2-3):401-405.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  8
    The Structure of Mind.Arnold Levison - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 27 (1):132-133.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  22
    Knowledge and society.Arnold Levison - 1966 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 9 (1-4):132 – 146.
    The question of the nature of our knowledge of society has recently been raised in an interesting form by Peter Winch in his monograph, The Idea of a Social Science, and debated in recent issues of Inquiry by A. R. Louch and Winch himself. In this paper I attempt to contribute to this discussion by attacking the problem of the nature of the empirical bases of social scientific knowledge, the main point in dispute between Winch and Louch. I try to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  14
    Comments on Stuart Silvers' note 'on our knowledge of the social world'.Arnold Levison - 1967 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 10 (1-4):98-100.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  69
    Metalinguistic dualism and the mark of the mental.Arnold B. Levison - 1986 - Synthese 66 (March):339-359.
    In this paper I argue against the view, defended by some philosophers, that it is part of the meaning of mental that being mental is incompatible with being physical. I call this outlook metalinguistic dualism, and I distinguish it from metaphysical theories of the mind-body relation such as Cartesian dualism. I argue that MLD is mistaken, but I don't try to defend the contrary view that mentalistic terms can be definitionally reduced to nonmental ones. After criticizing arguments by certain philosophers (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  37
    The Will: A Dual Aspect Theory. Brian O'Shaughnessy.Arnold B. Levison - 1982 - Ethics 93 (4):808-809.
  10.  49
    Events and Time’s Flow.Arnold B. Levison - 1987 - Mind 96 (383):341-353.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  31
    Might events be propositions?Arnold Levison - 1983 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (2):169-188.
  12. A Comment on Silvers' Note.Arnold Levison - 1967 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 10:98.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  32
    An Epistemic Criterion of the Mental.Arnold B. Levison - 1983 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (3):389 - 407.
    ‘When we see, hear, smell, taste, feel, meditate, or will anything, we know that we do so. … Consciousness … is inseparable from thinking, and essential to it. …’John Locke, Essay Concerning Human Understanding ‘Psycho-analysis … cannot accept the identity of the conscious and the mental. It defines what is mental as processes such as feeling, thinking and … willing. … ’Sigmund Freud, Introductory Lectures on Psycho-analysis.In this paper I shall provide a novel version of a traditional epistemic criterion for (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Chisholm and the metaphysical problem of human freedom.Arnold Levison - 1978 - Philosophia 7 (3-4):537-554.
    Chisholm's theory of freedom implies that a free action necessarily is one that has a certain causal history, Namely one leading back to a brain event (or some similar physiological occurrence) made to happen by the agent. The problem arises of the conceivability of the relation that is supposed to exist, On this theory, Between the agent and the bodily events leading up to his behavior. Furthermore, If it is a contingency whether human beings are sometimes free or always determined, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  30
    Do our actions cause our behavior?Arnold B. Levison - 1988 - Philosophia 18 (2-3):227-238.
  16.  18
    ?Epistemology today: A perspective in retrospect? by Ernest Sosa.Arnold Levison - 1981 - Philosophical Studies 40 (3):333 - 338.
  17.  30
    Frege on proof.Arnold B. Levison - 1961 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 22 (1):40-49.
  18.  39
    Mental events: An epistemic analysis.Arnold B. Levison & Gary Rosenkrantz - 1983 - Philosophia 12 (3-4):307-321.
  19.  38
    Professor Scheffler on falsifiability and meaning.Arnold B. Levison - 1965 - Philosophical Studies 16 (5):76 - 79.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  29
    The Concept of Proof.Arnold Levison - 1964 - The Monist 48 (4):547-566.
    Hume, in the Enquiry, remarks in a footnote as follows.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Thomas's two sources of knowledge.Arnold B. Levison - 1960 - Giornale di Metafisica 15 (4):475.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  13
    Review of Brian O'Shaughnessy: The will: a dual aspect theory[REVIEW]Arnold B. Levison - 1983 - Ethics 93 (4):808-809.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  10
    R. Grossmann's "The Structure of Mind". [REVIEW]Arnold Levison - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 27 (1):132.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The limits of scientific explanation and the no-miracles argument.Greg Frost-Arnold - 2008
    There are certain explanations that scientists do not accept, even though such explanations do not conflict with observation, logic, or other scientific theories. I argue that a common version of the no-miracles argument (NMA) for scientific realism relies upon just such an explanation. First, scientists (usually) do not accept explanations whose explanans neither generates novel predictions nor unifies apparently disparate phenomena. Second, scientific realism (as it appears in the NMA) is an explanans that makes no new predictions, and fails to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  19
    Book Reviews : Knowledge and Society: An Introduction to the Philosophy of the Social Sci ences. By ARNOLD B. LEVISON. Toronto: Fitzhenry and Whiteside, 1974. Pp. 188. $5.45. [REVIEW]Frank Cunningham - 1976 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 6 (3):274-276.
  26. The evolution of altruistic punishment.Robert Boyd, Herbert Gintis, Samuel Bowles, Peter Richerson & J. - 2003 - Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 100 (6):3531-3535.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  27.  35
    Wittgenstein and logical necessity.A. B. Levison - 1964 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 7 (1-4):367-373.
    An attempt is made to show that Wittgenstein's later philosophy of logic is not the kind of conventionalism which is often ascribed to him. On the contrary, Wittgenstein gives expression to a “mixed” theory which is not only interesting but tends to resolve the perplexities usually associated with the question of the a priori character of logical truth. I try to show that Wittgenstein is better understood not as denying that there are such things as “logical rules” nor as denying (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  4
    Intension and Decision: A Philosophical Study.A. B. Levison - 1964 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 25 (2):294-295.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29. Naïve Realism and Illusion.Boyd Millar - 2015 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 2:607-625.
    It is well-known that naïve realism has difficulty accommodating perceptual error. Recent discussion of the issue has focused on whether the naïve realist can accommodate hallucination by adopting disjunctivism. However, illusions are more difficult for the naïve realist to explain precisely because the disjunctivist solution is not available. I discuss what I take to be the two most plausible accounts of illusion available to the naïve realist. The first claims that illusions are cases in which you are prevented from perceiving (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  30. Self-deception.Ian Deweese-Boyd - 2023 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Virtually every aspect of the current philosophical discussion of self-deception is a matter of controversy including its definition and paradigmatic cases. We may say generally, however, that self-deception is the acquisition and maintenance of a belief (or, at least, the avowal of that belief) in the face of strong evidence to the contrary motivated by desires or emotions favoring the acquisition and retention of that belief. Beyond this, philosophers divide over whether this action is intentional or not, whether self-deceivers recognize (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  31. Kinds, Complexity and Multiple realization.Richard Boyd - 1999 - Philosophical Studies 95 (1-2):67-98.
  32. Kinds, complexity, and multiple realization.Robert Boyd - 1999 - Philosophical Studies 95 (1-2):67-98.
  33. Shared Epistemic Responsibility.Boyd Millar - 2021 - Episteme 18 (4):493-506.
    It is widely acknowledged that individual moral obligations and responsibility entail shared (or joint) moral obligations and responsibility. However, whether individual epistemic obligations and responsibility entail shared epistemic obligations and responsibility is rarely discussed. Instead, most discussions of doxastic responsibility focus on individuals considered in isolation. In contrast to this standard approach, I maintain that focusing exclusively on individuals in isolation leads to a profoundly incomplete picture of what we're epistemically obligated to do and when we deserve epistemic blame. First, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  34.  99
    Group Beneficial Norms Can Spread Rapidly in a Structured Population.Robert Boyd & Peter J. Richerson - unknown
    Group beneficial norms are common in human societies. The persistence of such norms is consistent with evolutionary game theory, but existing models do not provide a plausible explanation for why they are common. We show that when a model of imitation used to derive replicator dynamics in isolated populations is generalized to allow for population structure, group beneficial norms can spread rapidly under plausible conditions. We also show that this mechanism allows recombination of different group beneficial norms arising in..
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  35.  16
    Der Mensch: Seine Natur Und Seine Stellung in der Welt.Arnold Gehlen - 1940 - Junker & Dünnhaupt.
    Dieses Buch ist ein Klassiker der philosophischen Anthropologie und Arnold Gehlens wichtigstes Buch. Es fasst Gehlens Modell vom Menschen als eines auf Handlung und kulturelle Kompensation angewiesenen und sich damit eigentatig von der ihn bedrohenden Umwelt entlastenden "Mangelwesens" gultig zusammen. Auch wurde in "Der Mensch" 1950 erstmals Gehlens Institutionenlehre skizziert, die er aus der Revision seiner ursprunglichen Theorie "oberster Fuhrungssysteme" entwickelte. Gehlens Hauptwerk war "ohne Zweifel der fortgeschrittenste Versuch, die Philosophische Anthropologie an die Erkenntnisse empirischer Disziplinen zu binden". Diese (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  36.  20
    Finite Beings, Finite Goods: The Semantics, Metaphysics and Ethics of Naturalist Consequentialism, Part I 1.Richard Boyd - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (3):505-553.
    0.0. Theistic Ethics as a Challenge and a Diagnostic Tool. Naturalistic conceptions in metaethics come in many varieties. Many philosophers who have sought to situate moral reasoning in a naturalistic metaphysical conception have thought it necessary to adopt non-cognitivist, prescriptivist, projectivist, relativist, or otherwise deflationary conceptions. Recently there has been a revival of interest in non-deflationary moral realist approaches to ethical naturalism. Many non-deflationary approaches have exploited the resources of non-empiricist “causal” or “naturalistic” conceptions of reference and of kind definitions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  37.  59
    Shared norms can lead to the evolution of ethnic markers.Robert Boyd & Peter J. Richerson - unknown
    Most human populations are subdivided into ethnic groups which have self-ascribed membership and are marked by seemingly arbitrary traits such as distinctive styles of dress or speech. Existing explanations of ethnicity do not adequately explain the origin and maintenance of group marking. Here we develop a mathematical model which shows that groups distinguished by both differences in social norms and in arbitrary markers can emerge and remain stable despite significant mixing between them, if (1) people preferentially interact in mutually beneficial (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  38. The Information Environment and Blameworthy Beliefs.Boyd Millar - 2019 - Social Epistemology 33 (6):525-537.
    Thanks to the advent of social media, large numbers of Americans believe outlandish falsehoods that have been widely debunked. Many of us have a tendency to fault the individuals who hold such beliefs. We naturally assume that the individuals who form and maintain such beliefs do so in virtue of having violated some epistemic obligation: perhaps they failed to scrutinize their sources, or failed to seek out the available competing evidence. I maintain that very many ordinary individuals who acquire outlandish (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39. Epistemic Obligations of the Laity.Boyd Millar - 2023 - Episteme 20 (2):232-246.
    Very often when the vast majority of experts agree on some scientific issue, laypeople nonetheless regularly consume articles, videos, lectures, etc., the principal claims of which are inconsistent with the expert consensus. Moreover, it is standardly assumed that it is entirely appropriate, and perhaps even obligatory, for laypeople to consume such anti-consensus material. I maintain that this standard assumption gets things backwards. Each of us is particularly vulnerable to false claims when we are not experts on some topic – such (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  62
    Padre Boyd alla Karis - Lo studioso di Chesterton ha incontrato gli studenti.Boyd - 2011 - The Chesterton Review in Italiano 1 (1):173-173.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  21
    Finite Beings, Finite Goods: The Semantics, Metaphysics and Ethics of Naturalist Consequentialism, Part II.Richard Boyd - 2003 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (1):24-47.
    3.0. Well-being as a Challenge to Naturalism. In Chapter Three Adams discusses and criticizes those accounts of a person’s well being which characterize it in terms of counterfactuals regarding her actual desires and preferences. These criticisms are important for the question of ethical naturalism because any plausible naturalist position will have to portray a person’s well-being as somehow or other supervening on features of her psychology and her environment. The sorts of analyses Adams criticizes are the most prominent analyses consistent (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  42. Epistemic obligations and free speech.Boyd Millar - 2024 - Analytic Philosophy 65 (2):203-222.
    Largely thanks to Mill’s influence, the suggestion that the state ought to restrict the distribution of misinformation will strike most philosophers as implausible. Two of Mill’s influential assumptions are particularly relevant here: first, that free speech debates should focus on moral considerations such as the harm that certain forms of expression might cause; second, that false information causes minimal harm due to the fact that human beings are psychologically well equipped to distinguish truth and falsehood. However, in addition to our (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  80
    The seventh letter of Plato.M. Levison, A. Q. Morton & A. D. Winspear - 1968 - Mind 77 (307):309-325.
  44. The phenomenological directness of perceptual experience.Boyd Millar - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 170 (2):235-253.
    When you have a perceptual experience of a given physical object that object seems to be immediately present to you in a way it never does when you consciously think about or imagine it. Many philosophers have claimed that naïve realism (the view that to perceive is to stand in a primitive relation of acquaintance to the world) can provide a satisfying account of this phenomenological directness of perceptual experience while the content view (the view that to perceive is to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  45. The Open Future, Free Will and Divine Assurance: Responding to Three Common Objections to the Open View.Gregory Boyd - 2015 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 7 (3):207--222.
    In this essay I respond to three of the most forceful objections to the open view of the future. It is argued that a) open view advocates must deny bivalence; b) the open view offers no theodicy advantages over classical theism; and c) the open view can’t assure believers that God can work all things to the better. I argue that the first objection is premised on an inadequate assessment of future tensed propositions, the second is rooted in an inadequate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. The Phenomenological Problem of Perception.Boyd Millar - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (3):625-654.
    A perceptual experience of a given object seems to make the object itself present to the perceiver’s mind. Many philosophers have claimed that naïve realism (the view that to perceive is to stand in a primitive relation of acquaintance to the world) provides a better account of this phenomenological directness of perceptual experience than does the content view (the view that to perceive is to represent the world to be a certain way). But the naïve realist account of this phenomenology (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  40
    The Problem of Self-Destroying Sin in John Milton’s Samson Agonistes.Ian T. E. Boyd & Ian Deweese-Boyd - 1996 - Faith and Philosophy 13 (4):487-507.
    In this paper, I argue that John Milton, in his tragedy Smason Agonistes, raises and offers a solution to a version of the problem of evil raised by Marilyn McCord Adams. Sections I and II are devoted to the presentation of Adams’s version of the problem and its place in the current discussion of the problem of evil. In section III, I present Milton’s version of the problem as it is raised in Samson Agonistes. The solution Milton offers to this (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Perceiving properties versus perceiving objects.Boyd Millar - 2022 - Analytic Philosophy 63 (2):99-117.
    The fact that you see some particular object seems to be due to the causal relation between your visual experience and that object, rather than to your experiences’ phenomenal character. On the one hand, whenever some phenomenal element of your experience stands in the right sort of causal relation to some object, your experience presents that object (your experience’s phenomenology doesn’t need to match that object). On the other hand, you can’t have a perceptual experience that presents some object unless (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  40
    The requirements of the Data Protection Act 1998 for the processing of medical data.P. Boyd - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (1):34-35.
    The Data Protection Act 1998 presents a number of significant challenges to data controllers in the health sector. To assist data controllers in understanding their obligations under the act, the Information Commissioner has published guidance, The Use and Disclosure of Health Data, which is reproduced here. The guidance deals, among other things, with the steps that must be taken to obtain patient data fairly, the implied requirements of the act to use anonymised or psuedonymised data where possible, an exemption applicable (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50. Learning to see.Boyd Millar - 2019 - Mind and Language 35 (5):601-620.
    The reports of individuals who have had their vision restored after a long period of blindness suggest that, immediately after regaining their vision, such individuals are not able to recognize shapes by vision alone. It is often assumed that the empirical literature on sight restoration tells us something important about the relationship between visual and tactile representations of shape. However, I maintain that, immediately after having their sight restored, at least some newly sighted individuals undergo visual experiences that instantiate basic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000