Results for 'contrary-to-duty imperatives'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Contrary-to-Duty Imperatives and Deontic Logic.R. M. Chisholm - 1963 - Analysis 24 (2):33-36.
  2.  31
    Contrary-to-Duty Imperatives and Deontic Logic.Frederic B. Fitch - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):243-244.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  3.  87
    Contrary-to-duty imperatives and conditional obligation.James E. Tomberlin - 1981 - Noûs 15 (3):357-375.
  4. Good samaritans, contrary-to-duty imperatives, and epistemic obligations.Lennart Aqvist - 1967 - Noûs 1 (4):361-379.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  5.  35
    Reflections on contrary-to-duty imperatives.Wilfrid Sellars - 1967 - Noûs 1 (4):303-344.
  6. Contrary-to-Duty Scenarios, Deontic Dilemmas, and Transmission Principles.Benjamin Kiesewetter - 2018 - Ethics 129 (1):98-115.
    Actualists hold that contrary-to-duty scenarios give rise to deontic dilemmas and provide counterexamples to the transmission principle, according to which we ought to take the necessary means to actions we ought to perform. In an earlier article, I have argued, contrary to actualism, that the notion of ‘ought’ that figures in conclusions of practical deliberation does not allow for deontic dilemmas and validates the transmission principle. Here I defend these claims, together with my possibilist account of (...)-to-duty scenarios, against Stephen White’s recent criticism. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  7.  28
    Von Wright's Deontic Logics and "Contrary-to-Duty Imperatives".Carlos Alarcón-Cabrera - 1998 - Ratio Juris 11 (1):67-79.
  8.  15
    Roderick M. Chisholm. Contrary-to-duty imperatives and deontic logic. Analysis , vol. 24 no. 2 , pp. 33–36. - Mark Fisher. A contradiction in deontic logic?Analysis , vol. 25 no. 1 , pp. 12–13. - G. H. von Wright. A new system of deontic logic. Danish yearbook of philosophy, vol. 1 , pp. 173–182. - G. H. von Wright. A correction to a new system of deontic logic. Danish yearbook of philosophy, vol. 2 , pp. 103–107. [REVIEW]Frederic B. Fitch - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):243-244.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  91
    Contrary-to-Duty Paradox.Daniel Rönnedal - 2022 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    A contrary-to-duty obligation is an obligation telling us what ought to be the case if something that is wrong is true. For example: ‘If you have done something bad, you should make amends’. Doing something bad is wrong, but if it is true that you did do something bad, it ought to be the case that you make amends. Here are some other examples: ‘If he is guilty, he should confess’, ‘If you have hurt your friend, you should (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Contrary-to-duty obligations.Henry Prakken & Marek Sergot - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):91 - 115.
    We investigate under what conditions contrary-to-duty (CTD) structures lacking temporal and action elements can be given a coherent reading. We argue, contrary to some recent proposals, that CTD is not an instance of defeasible reasoning, and that methods of nonmonotonic logics are inadequate since they are unable to distinguish between defeasibility and violation of primary obligations. We propose a semantic framework based on the idea that primary and CTD obligations are obligations of different kinds: a CTD obligation (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  11. Contrary-to-Duty Paradox.Daniel Rönnedal - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    A contrary-to-duty obligation is an obligation that tells us what ought to be the case if something that is wrong or forbidden is true. Alternatively, we might say that a contrary-to-duty obligation is a conditional obligation where the condition is fulfilled only if a primary obligation is violated. Consider this example: “If you have hurt her feelings, you should make amends.” Since contrary-to-duty obligations play an important role in our moral and legal thinking, we (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  30
    Contrary-to-Duty Reasoning: A Categorical Approach.Clayton Peterson - 2015 - Logica Universalis 9 (1):47-92.
    This paper provides an analysis of contrary-to-duty reasoning from the proof-theoretical perspective of category theory. While Chisholm’s paradox hints at the need of dyadic deontic logic by showing that monadic deontic logics are not able to adequately model conditional obligations and contrary-to-duties, other arguments can be objected to dyadic approaches in favor of non-monotonic foundations. We show that all these objections can be answered at one fell swoop by modeling conditional obligations within a deductive system defined as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. Contrary-to-Duty Paradoxes and Counterfactual Deontic Logic.Daniel Rönnedal - 2019 - Philosophia 47 (4):1247-1282.
    In this paper, I will discuss some examples of the so-called contrary-to-duty paradox, a well-known puzzle in deontic logic. A contrary-to-duty obligation is an obligation telling us what ought to be the case if something forbidden is true, for example: ‘If she is guilty, she should confess’. Contrary-to-duty obligations are important in our moral and legal thinking. Therefore, we want to be able to find an adequate symbolisation of such obligations in some logical system, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  50
    Contrary-to-duty justification.Toni Vogel Carey - 1979 - Philosophical Studies 36 (1):1 - 18.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15. Normative Requirements and Contrary-to-Duty Obligations.Juan Comesaña - 2015 - Journal of Philosophy 112 (11):600-626.
    I argue that normative requirements should be interpreted as the conditional obligations of dyadic deontic logic. Semantically, normative requirements are conditionals understood as restrictors, the prevailing view of conditionals in linguistics. This means that Modus Ponens is invalid, even when the premises are known.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  16.  47
    Remedial interchange, contrary-to-duty obligation and commutation.Xavier Parent - 2003 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 13 (3):345-375.
    This paper discusses the relation between deontic logic and the study of conversational interactions. Special attention is given to the notion of remedial interchange as analysed by sociologists and linguistic pragmaticians. This notion is close to the one of contrary-to-duty (reparational) obligation, which deontic logicians have been studying in its own right. The present article also investigates the question of whether some of the aspects of conversational interactions can fruitfully be described by using formal tools originally developed in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Temporal Alethic Dyadic Deontic Logic and the Contrary-to-Duty Obligation Paradox.Daniel Rönnedal - 2018 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 27 (1):3-25.
    A contrary-to-duty obligation (sometimes called a reparational duty) is a conditional obligation where the condition is forbidden, e.g. “if you have hurt your friend, you should apologise”, “if he is guilty, he should confess”, and “if she will not keep her promise to you, she ought to call you”. It has proven very difficult to find plausible formalisations of such obligations in most deontic systems. In this paper, we will introduce and explore a set of temporal alethic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  23
    Reactive Kripke models and contrary to duty obligations. Part A: Semantics.Dov M. Gabbay - 2013 - Journal of Applied Logic 11 (1):103-136.
  19.  28
    Logic of Violations: A Gentzen System for Reasoning with Contrary-To-Duty Obligations.Guido Governatori & Antonino Rotolo - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Logic 4:193-215.
    In this paper we present a Gentzen system for reasoning with contrary-to-duty obligations. The intuition behind the system is that a contrary-to-duty is a special kind of normative exception. The logical machinery to formalise this idea is taken from substructural logics and it is based on the definition of a new non-classical connective capturing the notion of reparational obligation. Then the system is tested against well-known contrary-to-duty paradoxes.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  20. Reasoning and Change in a Language Game for Imperative and Permission Sentences.Marvin Belzer - 1984 - Dissertation, Duke University
    The most important problem is philosophical deontic logic is to determine the logical form of expressions of conditional obligation. The dissertation shows first that this problem is closely related to David Lewis's well-known "problem about permission"--a problem concerning the characterization of changes in normative systems. The dissertation contains a solution to the problem about permission, as well as an argument that expressions of conditional obligation cannot be represented satisfactorily by means of some combination of monadic deontic operators and a counterfactual (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  14
    A Conflict Between Some Semantic Conditions of Carmo and Jones for Contrary-to-Duty Obligations.Bjørn Kjos-Hanssen - 2017 - Studia Logica 105 (1):173-178.
    We show that Carmo and Jones’ condition 5 conflicts with the other conditions on their models for contrary-to-duty obligations. We then propose a resolution to the conflict.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  27
    The Duty of Memory Revisited: Ricoeur’s Contribution to a Crisis in French Historiography.Paul Marinescu - 2021 - Human Studies 44 (3):453-471.
    The relationship between memory and history, which has preoccupied historiography and the philosophy of history since the middle of the nineteenth century, took a particular course in France at the end of the millennium. The forms this relationship took in this particular context have been the subject of heated debate around whether the reconstruction of the past should bear the sign of a moral imperative or, on the contrary, it should be kept away from any moral conditioning. To address (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  40
    The Kantian Moral Worth of Actions Contrary to Duty.Samuel J. Kerstein - 1999 - Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 53 (4):530 - 552.
    This paper concerns Kant's view of the relations between an actions's moral permissibility and its moral worth. In the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, Kant holds that only morally permissible actions can have moral worth. By restricting moral worth to morally permissible actions, Kant generates an asymmetrical account of how two kinds of failure affect an actions's moral worth. While failure to judge correctly whether one's action is morally permissible precludes it from having moral worth failure to attain the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24. Positive Duties, Kant’s Universalizability Tests, and Contradictions.Samuel Kahn - 2020 - Southwest Philosophy Review 36 (1):113-120.
    In this paper I am going to raise a problem for recent attempts to derive positive duties from Kant’s universalizability tests. In particular, I argue that these recent attempts are subject to reductio and that the most obvious way of patching them renders them impracticable. I begin by explaining the motivation for these attempts. Then I describe how they work and begin my attack. I conclude by considering some patches.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  32
    Counterfactual-Style Revisions in the Semantics of Deontic Modals.Ana Arregui - 2011 - Journal of Semantics 28 (2):171-210.
    The article argues for a parallelism between the interpretation of deontic modals and the interpretation of counterfactuals. The main claim is that dependencies between facts play a role in the resolution of both types of modality: in both cases, facts ‘stand and fall’ together. The article provides two types of evidence supporting this claim: (i) evidence that comes from the interaction between primary and secondary duties (as presented in contrary-to-duty imperatives) and (ii) evidence that comes from the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. The Ethics of Doping: Between Paternalism and Duty.Evangelos D. Protopapadakis - 2020 - Pannoniana: Journal of Humanities 4 (1):35-49.
    The most plausible line of anti-doping argumentation starts with the fact that performance enhancing substances are harmful and put at considerable risk the health and the life of those who indulge in the overwhelming promises these substances hold. From a liberal point of view, however, this is not a strong reason neither to morally reject doping altogether, nor to put a blanket ban on it; on the contrary, allowing adult, competent and informed athletes to have access to performance enhancement (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Expanding the Limits of Universalization: Kant’s Duties and Kantian Moral Deliberation.Joshua M. Glasgow - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (1):23 - 47.
    Despite all the attention given to Kant’s universalizability tests, one crucial aspect of Kant’s thought is often overlooked. Attention to this issue, I will argue, helps us resolve two serious problems for Kant’s ethics. Put briefly, the first problem is this: Kant, despite his stated intent to the contrary, doesn’t seem to use universalization in arguing for duties to oneself, and, anyway, it is not at all clear why duties to oneself should be grounded on a procedure that envisions (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  28. The point of studying ethics according to Kant.Lucas Thorpe - 2006 - Journal of Value Inquiry 40 (4):461-474.
    Many readers of Kant’s ethical writings take him to be primarily concerned with offering guidelines for action. At the least, they write about Kant as if this were the purpose of his ethical writings. For example, Christine Korsgaard, in her influential article Kant’s Analysis of Obligation: The Argument of Groundwork I, writes that, ‘‘the argument of Groundwork I is an attempt to give what I call a ‘motivational analysis’ of the concept of a right action, in order to discover what (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  27
    The Robbery Paradox.Mark Vorobej - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (3):433-440.
    James E. Tomberlin [6] has recently argued that the logical systems of conditional obligation proposed by Azizah al-Hibri [1] and Peter Mott [5] are incapable of resolving at least one variant of the notorious contrary to duty imperative paradox, formulated originally by Chisholm [2]. Tomberlin concedes that these systems offer the very best of the' “conditional obligation approach” to deontic logic and concludes his critical discussion with the pessimistic remark that “the best of this approach is simply not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  45
    Directives and Norms. [REVIEW]H. K. R. - 1969 - Review of Metaphysics 23 (1):138-138.
    The expressed aim of Alf Ross' study is to lay the philosophical foundations for deontic logic by explicating the concepts of directive and norm. But there is a wider significance to his task, for he makes clear throughout that the concepts of directive and norm are central to a wide variety of disciplines, including moral, legal, and social philosophy, linguistics and the other social sciences. Moreover, the test of adequacy of his explications include an appeal to the usefulness the concepts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  34
    Gene editing of human embryos is not contrary to human rights law: A reply to Drabiak.Andrea Boggio & Rumiana Yotova - 2021 - Bioethics 35 (9):956-963.
    In an article in this journal, Katherine Drabiak argues that green lighting genome editing of human embryos is contrary to “fundamental human rights law.” According to the author, genome editing of human embryos violates what we should recognize as a fundamental human right to inherit a genome without deliberate manipulation. In this reply article, we assess Drabiak's legal analysis and show methodological and substantive flaws. Methodologically, her analysis omits the key international legal instruments that form the so‐called International Bill (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Impossible Imperatives.Impossible Imperatives - unknown
    The usual conception of transcendence is as the success of a process or practice of mediation, meditation, transmutation, salvation, supplication, application or implication. Blanchot's unusual transcendence escapes the inevitable ruin of such achievements by arriving in the form of the failure of immanence. Although it is impossible to describe that failure explicitly, it can be approached apophatically. Following an impossible imperative to see the whole, immanence generates inadvertent transcendence “thus exposing the essential ambiguity of transcendence and the impossibility that this (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  16
    Kant’s Derivation of Imperatives of Duty.Laurenz Ramsauer - 2024 - Kantian Review 29 (1):39-59.
    On the currently dominant reading of the Groundwork, Kant’s derivation of ‘imperatives of duty’ exemplifies a decision procedure for the derivation of concrete duties in moral deliberation. However, Kant’s response to an often-misidentified criticism of the Groundwork by G. A. Tittel suggests that Kant was remarkably unconcerned with arguing for the practicality of the categorical imperative as a decision procedure. Instead, I argue that the main aim of Kant’s derivation of imperatives of duty was to show (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  9
    Being and duty: the contribution of 20th-century Polish thinkers to the theory of imperatives and norms.Jacek Juliusz Jadacki - 2013 - Kraków: Copernicus Center Press.
    The book is comprised of three components. The first component analyses the creative contribution to the theory of imperatives and norms provided by 20th-century Polish researchers. The second component summarizes their reflections and considerations. The third component is an anthology of the classic writings of Polish authors of the time; it constitutes an illustration of the first part and indicates that their research covered practically the whole scope of this theory. Author Jacek Jadacki (born 1946) is professor at Warsaw (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  29
    Without consent: Moral imperatives, special abilities, and the duty to treat.Nadia N. Sawicki - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (8):33 – 35.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  19
    Duties to Oneself.Oliver Sensen - 2017 - In Matthew C. Altman (ed.), The Palgrave Kant Handbook. Palgrave Macmillan Uk. pp. 285–306.
    Sensen analyzes Kant’s justification of duties to oneself. Why does Kant say that duties to oneself have priority over other duties? Sensen concludes that there is a common idea behind the different formulas of the categorical imperative: the idea that our human capacities have a high importance. Kant’s ethics needs anthropology to derive concrete duties from this general idea.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Can Positive Duties be Derived from Kant’s Categorical Imperative?Michael Yudanin - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (3):595-614.
    Kant’s moral philosophy usually considers two types of duties: negative duties that prohibit certain actions and positive duties commanding action. With that, Kant insists on deriving all morality from reason alone. Such is the Categorical Imperative that Kant lays at the basis of ethics. Yet while negative duties can be derived from the Categorical Imperative and thus from reason, the paper argues that this is not the case with positive duties. After answering a number of attempts to derive positive duties (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Duties Regarding Nature: A Kantian Approach to Environmental Ethics.Toby Svoboda - 2012 - Kant Yearbook 4 (1):143-163.
    Many philosophers have objected to Kant’s account of duties regarding non-human nature, arguing that it does not ground adequate moral concern for non-human natural entities. However, the traditional interpretation of Kant on this issue is mistaken, because it takes him to be arguing merely that humans should abstain from animal cruelty and wanton destruction of flora solely because such actions could make one more likely to violate one’s duties to human beings. Instead, I argue, Kant’s account of duties regarding nature (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  77
    Response to Tumulty on Pain and Imperatives.Colin Klein - 2010 - Journal of Philosophy 107 (10):554-557.
    Maura Tumulty has raised two objections to my imperative account of pain.1 First, she argues that there is a disanalogy between pains and other imperative sensations like itch, hunger, and thirst. Suppose (with Hall) one thinks that an itch says “Scratch here!”2 Scratch the itch, and it dutifully disappears. Not so with pain. The pain of a broken ankle has the content ‘Do not put weight on that ankle!’ Yet the coddled ankle still throbs: obeying the imperative does not extinguish (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40.  22
    The Duty to Miscegenate.Nathaniel Adam Tobias Coleman - 2013 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    In 'The duty to miscegenate', I harness John Stuart Mill's 19th century theory of social freedom to explain and to dismantle contemporary racialised and gendered injustice. In the first chapter—Social stigmatisation: 'a social tyranny'—I argue that persons racialised-and-gendered-as-black-women were, in the past, unjustly stigmatised by legal penalties against 'miscegenation' and are still, today, unjustly stigmatised by white male avoidance of cross-racial marriage and companionship. In the second chapter—Encounters that count: 'a foundation for solid friendship'—I argue that we can dismantle (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  10
    Doing Christian Ethics on the Ground Polycentrically: Cross-Cultural Moral Deliberation on Ethical and Social Issues.Ronald W. Duty - 2014 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 34 (1):41-63.
    This article argues that congregations should be seen as grassroots public moral agents, on the ground working to bring what they discern as God's preferred future into being. Deliberations among congregations of all social backgrounds are a way of doing ethics "polycentrically," without a dominant center. Because cultural and social boundaries are permeable and people in various social groups can imaginatively enter the worlds of people unlike themselves, they can engage those perspectives morally on an equal footing. The essay addresses (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  40
    Duty to disclose what? Querying the putative obligation to return research results to participants.F. A. Miller, R. Christensen, M. Giacomini & J. S. Robert - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (3):210-213.
    Many research ethics guidelines now oblige researchers to offer research participants the results of research in which they participated. This practice is intended to uphold respect for persons and ensure that participants are not treated as mere means to an end. Yet some scholars have begun to question a generalised duty to disclose research results, highlighting the potential harms arising from disclosure and questioning the ethical justification for a duty to disclose, especially with respect to individual results. In (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  43.  19
    A Duty to treat? A Right to refrain? Bangladeshi physicians in moral dilemma during COVID-19.Mohammad Kamrul Ahsan, Md Munir Hossain Talukder & Norman K. Swazo - 2020 - Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 15 (1):1-23.
    BackgroundNormally, physicians understand they have a duty to treat patients, and they perform accordingly consistent with codes of medical practice, standards of care, and inner moral motivation. In the case of COVID-19 pandemic in a developing country such as Bangladesh, however, the fact is that some physicians decline either to report for duty or to treat patients presenting with COVID-19 symptoms. At issue ethically is whether such medical practitioners are to be automatically disciplined for dereliction of duty (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  8
    Duty to Human Needs from African Rights.Christopher Allsobrook - 2021 - In Motsamai Molefe & Christopher Allsobrook (eds.), Towards an African Political Philosophy of Needs. Springer Verlag. pp. 187-204.
    This final chapter argues that the determination of public duties to our needs in African politics ought to be based on established social and political rights derived from recognised African customary norms. The argument is motivated by a basic limitation with two opposed approaches to African political theory of needs—realist and communitarian—which struggle with the naturalistic fallacy in determining objective public needs, since they dismiss the security of rights-based law as the basis for the legitimate determination of public duties towards (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  82
    How to Release Oneself from an Obligation: Good News for Duties to Oneself.Tim Oakley - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (1):70-80.
    In some cases, you may release someone from some obligation they have to you. For instance, you may release them from a promise they made to you, or an obligation to repay money they have borrowed from you. But most take it as clear that, if you have an obligation to someone else, you cannot in any way release yourself from that obligation. I shall argue the contrary. The issue is important because one standard problem for the idea of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  15
    Physicians’ duty to refrain from religious discourse: a response to critics.Ryan K. Hubbard & Jake Greenblum - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (11):721-722.
    We recently argued that—contrary to what we call the dominant view— physicians ought to avoid engaging patients on religious grounds.1 The six responses to our article present an array of concerns and have provided us with the opportunity to consider further aspects of our view. While we cannot reply to all the relevant issues, our aim here is to reply to the most significant concerns. Against our Public Reason Argument, Nick Colgrove maintains that physicians are not relevantly akin to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  75
    On Marcus Singer’s “On Duties to Oneself”.Michael Cholbi - 2015 - Ethics 125 (3):851-853,.
    In “On duties to oneself,” Marcus G. Singer argued that, contrary to long established philosophical tradition, there are no duties to oneself. Singer observes that to have a duty is to be accountable to someone for that duty’s fulfillment, and while she to whom a duty is owed may release the person who has the duty from being bound to fulfill it, the latter cannot release herself from the duty. For releasing oneself from a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48. Neoliberalism and the duty to die: biopolitical and psychopolitical perspectives.Jose Luis Guerrero Quiñones - 2023 - Isegoría 68 (e29):1-9.
    This paper aims to explore and offer different hypotheses that could account for an adequate understanding of the duty to die and its relation to biopolitics from two neglected approaches. First, death will be analysed from a biopolitical perspective to understand the crucial role it has in biopower. Second, the focus lies on the two-folded implication that death has in biopower, for it could be either a defiance of it or the final sublimation of its control. Similarly, the next (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The editor has review copies of the following books. Potential reviewers should contact the editor to obtain a review copy (rhaynes@ phil. ufl. edu). Books not previously listed are in bold faced type. [REVIEW]Contrary Life - 2000 - Agriculture and Human Values 17:113-114.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  78
    Investing in socially responsible companies is a must for public pension funds – because there is no better alternative.S. Prakash Sethi - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 56 (2):99 - 129.
    >With assets of over US$1.0 trillion and growing, public pension funds in the United States have become a major force in the private sector through their holding of equity positions in large publicly traded corporations. More recently, these funds have been expanding their investment strategy by considering a corporations long-term risks on issues such as environmental protection, sustainability, and good corporate citizenship, and how these factors impact a companys long-term performance. Conventional wisdom argues that the fiduciary responsibility of the pension (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000