Results for ' ARISTOTELIAN MATHEMATICAL SCIENCE'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the science of quantity and structure.James Franklin - 2014 - London and New York: Palgrave MacMillan.
    An Aristotelian Philosophy of Mathematics breaks the impasse between Platonist and nominalist views of mathematics. Neither a study of abstract objects nor a mere language or logic, mathematics is a science of real aspects of the world as much as biology is. For the first time, a philosophy of mathematics puts applied mathematics at the centre. Quantitative aspects of the world such as ratios of heights, and structural ones such as symmetry and continuity, are parts of the physical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  2. The beauty of the world in Aristotelian terms-The mathematical sciences and primary philosophy.M. Crubellier - 1997 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 51 (201):307-331.
  3. Mathematics as a science of non-abstract reality: Aristotelian realist philosophies of mathematics.James Franklin - 2022 - Foundations of Science 27 (2):327-344.
    There is a wide range of realist but non-Platonist philosophies of mathematics—naturalist or Aristotelian realisms. Held by Aristotle and Mill, they played little part in twentieth century philosophy of mathematics but have been revived recently. They assimilate mathematics to the rest of science. They hold that mathematics is the science of X, where X is some observable feature of the (physical or other non-abstract) world. Choices for X include quantity, structure, pattern, complexity, relations. The article lays out (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Philosophy of mathematics and mathematical practice in the seventeenth century.Paolo Mancosu (ed.) - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The seventeenth century saw dramatic advances in mathematical theory and practice. With the recovery of many of the classical Greek mathematical texts, new techniques were introduced, and within 100 years, the rules of analytic geometry, geometry of indivisibles, arithmatic of infinites, and calculus were developed. Although many technical studies have been devoted to these innovations, Mancosu provides the first comprehensive account of the relationship between mathematical advances of the seventeenth century and the philosophy of mathematics of the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  5.  52
    An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure by James Franklin. [REVIEW]Jude P. Dougherty - 2015 - Review of Metaphysics 68 (3):658-660.
  6.  1
    Science and sanity: an introduction to non-Aristotelian systems and general semantics.Alfred Korzybski - 2023 - New York, New York, USA: Institute of General Semantics. Edited by Lance Strate.
    The fundamental, irreplaceable exposition of general semantics. In this work Korzybski developed important lines of formulating neglected by subsequent authors. A must-have for the student of general semantics interested in the original formulations of Alfred Korzybski. The sixth edition of Science and Sanity: An Introduction to Non-Aristotelian Systems and General Semantics includes a new preface by Lance Strate, President of the Institute of General Semantics.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. Demarcating Aristotelian Rhetoric: Rhetoric, the Subalternate Sciences, and Boundary Crossing.Marcus P. Adams - 2015 - Apeiron 48 (1):99-122.
    The ways in which the Aristotelian sciences are related to each other has been discussed in the literature, with some focus on the subalternate sciences. While it is acknowledged that Aristotle, and Plato as well, was concerned as well with how the arts were related to one another, less attention has been paid to Aristotle's views on relationships among the arts. In this paper, I argue that Aristotle's account of the subalternate sciences helps shed light on how Aristotle saw (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  30
    How the "New Science" of Cannons Shook up the Aristotelian Cosmos.Mary J. Henninger-Voss - 2002 - Journal of the History of Ideas 63 (3):371-397.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 63.3 (2002) 371-397 [Access article in PDF] How the "New Science" of Cannons Shook up the Aristotelian Cosmos Mary J. Henninger-Voss [Figures]Approximately halfway through the "Second Day" of Galileo's Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems Galileo's mouthpiece, the mathematician Salviati, scoffs at his Aristotelian colleague Simplicio: "I see that you have hitherto been of that herd who, in order (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  32
    Applied Mathematics in the Sciences.Dale Jacquette - 2006 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):237-267.
    A complete philosophy of mathematics must address Paul Benacerraf’s dilemma. The requirements of a general semantics for the truth of mathematical theorems that coheres also with the meaning and truth conditions for non-mathematical sentences, according to Benacerraf, should ideally be coupled with an adequate epistemology for the discovery of mathematical knowledge. Standard approaches to the philosophy of mathematics are criticized against their own merits and against the background of Benacerraf’s dilemma, particularly with respect to the problem of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics: Seventeenth-Century Developments of the Quaestio de Certitudine Mathematicarum.Paolo Mancosu - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 23 (2):241-265.
  11.  55
    James Franklin: An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure. [REVIEW]Peter Forrest - 2015 - Studia Neoaristotelica 12 (1):105-109.
    This paper is a book review of "An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure" by James Franklin.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  29
    Applied Mathematics in the Sciences.Dale Jacquette - 2006 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):237-267.
    A complete philosophy of mathematics must address Paul Benacerraf’s dilemma. The requirements of a general semantics for the truth of mathematical theorems that coheres also with the meaning and truth conditions for non-mathematical sentences, according to Benacerraf, should ideally be coupled with an adequate epistemology for the discovery of mathematical knowledge. Standard approaches to the philosophy of mathematics are criticized against their own merits and against the background of Benacerraf’s dilemma, particularly with respect to the problem of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Aristotelian realism.James Franklin - 2009 - In A. Irvine (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematics (Handbook of the Philosophy of Science series). North-Holland Elsevier.
    Aristotelian, or non-Platonist, realism holds that mathematics is a science of the real world, just as much as biology or sociology are. Where biology studies living things and sociology studies human social relations, mathematics studies the quantitative or structural aspects of things, such as ratios, or patterns, or complexity, or numerosity, or symmetry. Let us start with an example, as Aristotelians always prefer, an example that introduces the essential themes of the Aristotelian view of mathematics. A typical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  14.  16
    Jaakko Hintikka. An Aristotelian dilemma. Ajatus, vol. 22 , pp. 87–92. - Nicholas Rescher. Aristotle's theory of modal syllogisms and its interpretation. The critical approach to science and philosophy, edited by Mario Bunge, The Free Press of Glencoe, Collier-Macmillan Limited, London1964, pp. 152–177. Reprinted in Essays in philosophical analysis, by Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh 1969, pp. 33–60. - Storrs McCall. Aristotle's modal syllogisms. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam1963, VIII + 100 pp. [REVIEW]Ivo Thomas - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (2):418-419.
  15.  32
    Review of An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure[REVIEW]William Lane Craig - 2015 - Philosophia Christi 17 (1):225-230.
    James Franklin aspires to a realist view of mathematical objects as concrete, rather than abstract, objects. It is shown that he fails to carry out his program but is forced to revert to Platonism.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  53
    Applying mathematics to empirical sciences: flashback to a puzzling disciplinary interaction.Raphaël Sandoz - 2018 - Synthese 195 (2):875-898.
    This paper aims to reassess the philosophical puzzle of the “applicability of mathematics to physical sciences” as a misunderstood disciplinary interplay. If the border isolating mathematics from the empirical world is based on appropriate criteria, how does one explain the fruitfulness of its systematic crossings in recent centuries? An analysis of the evolution of the criteria used to separate mathematics from experimental sciences will shed some light on this question. In this respect, we will highlight the historical influence of three (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  48
    Beyond Platonism and Nominalism?: James Franklin: An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure[REVIEW]Vassilis Livanios - 2016 - Axiomathes 26 (1):63-69.
    Review of James Franklin: An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure, Palgrave Macmillan, 2014, x + 308 pp.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  82
    Between Logic and Mathematics: Al-Kindī's Approach to the Aristotelian Categories.Ahmad Ighbariah - 2012 - Arabic Sciences and Philosophy 22 (1):51-68.
    What is the function of logic in al-Kindī's corpus? What kind of relation does it have with mathematics? This article tackles these questions by examining al-Kindī's theory of categories as it was presented in his epistle On the Number of Aristotle's Books, from which we can learn about his special attitude towards Aristotle theory of categories and his interpretation, as well. Al-Kindī treats the Categories as a logical book, but in a manner different from that of the classical Aristotelian (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Semi-Platonist Aristotelianism: Review of James Franklin, An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics: Mathematics as the Science of Quantity and Structure[REVIEW]Catherine Legg - 2015 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (4):837-837.
    This rich book differs from much contemporary philosophy of mathematics in the author’s witty, down to earth style, and his extensive experience as a working mathematician. It accords with the field in focusing on whether mathematical entities are real. Franklin holds that recent discussion of this has oscillated between various forms of Platonism, and various forms of nominalism. He denies nominalism by holding that universals exist and denies Platonism by holding that they are concrete, not abstract - looking to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  8
    Acts Amid Precepts: The Aristotelian Logical Structure of Thomas Aquinas's Moral Theory.Kevin L. Flannery - 2001 - Catholic University of Amer Press.
    Although most natural law ethical theories recognize moral absolutes, there is not much agreement even among natural law theorists about how to identify them. The author argues that in order to understand and determine the morality (or immorality) of a human action, it must be considered in relation to the organized system of human practices within which it is performed. Such an approach, he argues, is to be found in the natural law theory of Thomas Aquinas, especially once it is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  88
    Physico-mathematics and the search for causes in Descartes' optics—1619–1637.John A. Schuster - 2012 - Synthese 185 (3):467-499.
    One of the chief concerns of the young Descartes was with what he, and others, termed “physico-mathematics”. This signalled a questioning of the Scholastic Aristotelian view of the mixed mathematical sciences as subordinate to natural philosophy, non explanatory, and merely instrumental. Somehow, the mixed mathematical disciplines were now to become intimately related to natural philosophical issues of matter and cause. That is, they were to become more ’physicalised’, more closely intertwined with natural philosophising, regardless of which species (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22. Science and Sanity an Introduction to Non-Aristotelian Systems and General Semantics. 4th Ed., with New Pref. By Russell Meyers.Alfred Korzybski - 1958 - International Non-Aristotelian Library Pub. Co.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  17
    Frege and the Aristotelian Model of Science.Danielle Macbeth - 2016 - In Sorin Costreie (ed.), Early Analytic Philosophy – New Perspectives on the Tradition. Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    Although profoundly influential for essentially the whole of philosophy’s twenty-five hundred year history, the model of a science that is outlined in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics has recently been abandoned on grounds that developments in mathematics and logic over the last century or so have rendered it obsolete. Nor has anything emerged to take its place. As things stand we have not even the outlines of an adequate understanding of the rationality of mathematics as a scientific practice. It seems reasonable, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  10
    The Metaphysics of Mathematical Explanation in Science.Patrick Fisher - 2021 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 95:153-163.
    Debates between contemporary platonist and nominalist conceptions of the metaphysical status of mathematical objects have recently included discussions of explanations of physical phenomena in which mathematics plays an indispensable role, termed mathematical explanations in science (MES). I will argue that MES requires an ontology that can (1) ground claims about mathematical necessity as distinct from physical necessity and (2) explain how that mathematical necessity applies to the physical world. I contend that nominalism fails to meet (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Aristotle’s prohibition rule on kind-crossing and the definition of mathematics as a science of quantities.Paola Cantù - 2010 - Synthese 174 (2):225-235.
    The article evaluates the Domain Postulate of the Classical Model of Science and the related Aristotelian prohibition rule on kind-crossing as interpretative tools in the history of the development of mathematics into a general science of quantities. Special reference is made to Proclus’ commentary to Euclid’s first book of Elements , to the sixteenth century translations of Euclid’s work into Latin and to the works of Stevin, Wallis, Viète and Descartes. The prohibition rule on kind-crossing formulated by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  26. Philosophy, mathematics and structure.James Franklin - 1995 - Philosopher: revue pour tous 1 (2):31-38.
    An early version of the work on mathematics as the science of structure that appeared later as An Aristotelian Realist Philosophy of Mathematics (2014).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. The Aristotelian Explanation of the Halo.Monte Ransome Johnson - 2009 - Apeiron 42 (4):325-357.
    For an Aristotelian observer, the halo is a puzzling phenomenon since it is apparently sublunary, and yet perfectly circular. This paper studies Aristotle's explanation of the halo in Meteorology III 2-3 as an optical illusion, as opposed to a substantial thing (like a cloud), as was thought by his predecessors and even many successors. Aristotle's explanation follows the method of explanation of the Posterior Analytics for "subordinate" or "mixed" mathematical-physical sciences. The accompanying diagram described by Aristotle is one (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  18
    Mathematical Projection of Nature in M. Heidegger's Phenomenology. His 'Unwritten Dogma' on Thought Experiments.Panos Theodorou - 2022 - In Aristides Baltas & Thodoris Dimitrakos (eds.), Philosophy and Sciences in the 20th Century, Volume II. Crete University Press. pp. 215-242.
    In §69.b of BT Heidegger attempts an existential genetic analysis of science, i.e. a phenomenology of the conceptual process of the constitution of the logical view of science (science seen as theory) starting from the Dasein. It attempts to do so by examining the special intentional-existential modification of (human) being-in-the-world, which is called the "mathematical projection of nature"; that is, by examining that special modification of our being, which places us in the state of experience that (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  44
    Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical Optics.Antoni Malet - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (2):265-287.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical OpticsAntoni MaletIntroductionIsaac Newton’s Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy embodies a strong program of mathematization that departs both from the mechanical philosophy of Cartesian inspiration and from Boyle’s experimental philosophy. The roots of Newton’s mathematization of nature, this paper aims to demonstrate, are to be found in Isaac Barrow’s (1630–77) philosophy of the mathematical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30. On Aristotelian Ἐπιστήμη as ‘Understanding’.J. H. Lesher - 2001 - Ancient Philosophy 21 (1):45-55.
    Myles Burnyeat maintains that Aristotelian epistêmê, in so far as it deals with explanations, is properly identified as understanding rather than as knowledge. Although Burnyeat is right in thinking that the cognitive achievement Aristotle typically has in mind is not justified true belief, Aristotelian epistêmê cannot be equated with understanding. On some occasions in Aristotle's writings (e.g. Apo 71a4), the term designates a particular science such as mathematics; on others (e.g. Apo 72b18-20), it designates the grasp of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  11
    On Aristotelian epistêmê as `Understanding'.J. H. Lesher - 2001 - Ancient Philosophy 21 (1):45-55.
    Myles Burnyeat maintains that Aristotelian epistêmê, in so far as it deals with explanations, is properly identified as understanding rather than as knowledge. Although Burnyeat is right in thinking that the cognitive achievement Aristotle typically has in mind is not justified true belief, Aristotelian epistêmê cannot be equated with understanding. On some occasions in Aristotle’s writings (e.g. Apo 71a4), the term designates a particular science such as mathematics; on others (e.g. Apo 72b18-20), it designates the grasp of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. What Science Knows: And How It Knows It.James Franklin - 2009 - Encounter Books.
    In What Science Knows, the Australian philosopher and mathematician James Franklin explains in captivating and straightforward prose how science works its magic. It offers a semipopular introduction to an objective Bayesian/logical probabilist account of scientific reasoning, arguing that inductive reasoning is logically justified (though actually existing science sometimes falls short). Its account of mathematics is Aristotelian realist.
  33.  7
    Juxtaposing 2 contradictory views of Freud: The apotheosis of Logic ; the undermining of the epistemological validity of logic: Freud rejects Aristotelian logic as the criteria to assess the 'truths' of psychoanalysis and thus becomes a precursor to quantum mechanics and mathematics like wise abandonment of Aristotelian logic as an epistemic condition of 'truth' in certain situations.Colin Leslie Dean - 2005 - West Geelong, Vic.: Gamahucher Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Hobbes on Natural Philosophy as "True Physics" and Mixed Mathematics.Marcus P. Adams - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 56 (C):43-51.
    I offer an alternative account of the relationship of Hobbesian geometry to natural philosophy by arguing that mixed mathematics provided Hobbes with a model for thinking about it. In mixed mathematics, one may borrow causal principles from one science and use them in another science without there being a deductive relationship between those two sciences. Natural philosophy for Hobbes is mixed because an explanation may combine observations from experience (the ‘that’) with causal principles from geometry (the ‘why’). My (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  15
    Forms of Mathematization (14th -17th Centuries).Sophie Roux - 2010 - Early Science and Medicine 15 (4-5):319-337.
    According to a grand narrative that long ago ceased to be told, there was a seventeenth century Scientific Revolution, during which a few heroes conquered nature thanks to mathematics. This grand narrative began with the exhibition of quantitative laws that these heroes, Galileo and Newton for example, had disclosed: the law of falling bodies, according to which the speed of a falling body is proportional to the square of the time that has elapsed since the beginning of its fall; the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36.  11
    Morphisms Between Aristotelian Diagrams.Alexander De Klerck, Leander Vignero & Lorenz Demey - forthcoming - Logica Universalis:1-35.
    In logical geometry, Aristotelian diagrams are studied in a precise and systematic way. Although there has recently been a good amount of progress in logical geometry, it is still unknown which underlying mathematical framework is best suited for formalizing the study of these diagrams. Hence, in this paper, the main aim is to formulate such a framework, using the powerful language of category theory. We build multiple categories, which all have Aristotelian diagrams as their objects, while having (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  21
    Matter and Mathematics: An Essentialist Account of the Laws of Nature by Andrew YOUNAN (review).Dominic V. Cassella - 2023 - Review of Metaphysics 77 (1):166-168.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Matter and Mathematics: An Essentialist Account of the Laws of Nature by Andrew YOUNANDominic V. CassellaYOUNAN, Andrew. Matter and Mathematics: An Essentialist Account of the Laws of Nature. Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2023. xii + 228 pp. Cloth, $75.00Andrew Younan’s work situates itself between two opposing philosophical accounts of the laws of nature. In one corner, there are the Humeans (or Nominalists); in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  11
    Acts Amid Precepts: The Aristotelian Logical Structure of Thomas Aquinas’s Moral Theory. [REVIEW]Beverly J. Whelton - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (4):872-873.
    Through textual analysis and an exposition of Aristotelian mathematics and logic, Acts Amid Precepts makes two points essential to a proper consideration of Thomistic moral theory. First, one must understand Aristotle’s ethical theory as having the general structure of an Aristotelian science with a hierarchy of axioms, principles, definitions, and precepts. Second, Flannery proposes that through analytic and synthetic reasoning, practical acts must be evaluated within a hierarchy of cultural and professional precepts, not just the application of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  50
    What could mathematics be for it to function in distinctively mathematical scientific explanations?Marc Lange - 2021 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 87 (C):44-53.
    Several philosophers have suggested that some scientific explanations work not by virtue of describing aspects of the world’s causal history and relations, but rather by citing mathematical facts. This paper investigates what mathematical facts could be in order for them to figure in such “distinctively mathematical” scientific explanations. For “distinctively mathematical explanations” to be explanations by constraint, mathematical language cannot operate in science as representationalism or platonism describes. It can operate as Aristotelian realism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  85
    Galileo's first new science: The science of matter.Zvi Biener - 2004 - Perspectives on Science 12 (3):262-287.
    : Although Galileo's struggle to mathematize the study of nature is well known and oft discussed, less discussed is the form this struggle takes in relation to Galileo's first new science, the science of the second day of the Discorsi. This essay argues that Galileo's first science ought to be understood as the science of matter—not, as it is usually understood, the science of the strength of materials. This understanding sheds light on the convoluted structure (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41.  9
    Tartaglia's Science of Weights and Mechanics in the Sixteenth Century: Selections from Quesiti et inventioni diverse: Books VII-VIII.Raffaele Pisano - 2016 - Dordrecht: Imprint: Springer. Edited by Danilo Capecchi.
    This book presents a historical and scientific analysis as historical epistemology of the science of weights and mechanics in the sixteenth century, particularly as developed by Tartaglia in his Quesiti et inventioni diverse, Book VII and Book VIII (1546; 1554). In the early 16th century mechanics was concerned mainly with what is now called statics and was referred to as the Scientia de ponderibus, generally pursued by two very different approaches. The first was usually referred to as Aristotelian, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  13
    Mathematics and the Physical World in Aristotle.Pierre Pellegrin - 2018 - In Hassan Tahiri (ed.), The Philosophers and Mathematics: Festschrift for Roshdi Rashed. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 189-199.
    I would like to start with a historical question or, more precisely, a question pertaining to the history of science itself. It is a widely accepted idea that Aristotelism has been an obstacle to the emergence of modern physical science, and this was for at least two reasons. The first one is the cognitive role Aristotle is supposed to have attributed to perception. Instead of considering perception as an origin of error, Aristotle thinks that our senses provide us (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  40
    Causação descendente, emergência de propriedades e modos causais aristotélicos (Downward Causation, Property Emergence, and Aristotelian Causal Modes).Charbel Niño Ei-Hani & Antonio Augusto Passos Videira - 2001 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 16 (2):301-329.
    O problema da causação descendente é um ponto central na formulação do fisicalismo não-redutivo e na compreensão da emergência de propriedades. Duas interpretações possíveis da causação descendente, nas quais a contribuição do pensamento aristotélico é importante, são examinadas. Os requisitos do programa de matematização da natureza na mecanica clássica, que levaram ao abandono de três dos modos causais aristotélicos, nao parecem igualmente importantes nas ciencias especiais. Isto sugere que a contribuição de Aristóteles pode ser, de certa maneira, retomada. Uma definição (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  77
    Socratic Questions and Aristotelian Answers: A Virtue-Based Approach to Business Ethics.Edwin M. Hartman - 2008 - Journal of Business Ethics 78 (3):313-328.
    To teach that being ethical requires knowing foundational ethical principles – or, as Socrates claimed, airtight definitions of ethical terms – is to invite cynicism among students, for students discover that no such principles can be found. Aristotle differs from Socrates in claiming that ethics is about virtues primarily, and that one can be virtuous without having the sort of knowledge that characterizes mathematics or natural science. Aristotle is able to demonstrate that ethics and self-interest may overlap, that ethics (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  45.  51
    Tartaglia’s Science of Weights and Mechanics in the Sixteenth Century Selections from Quesiti et inventioni diverse: Books VII–VIII.Pisano Raffaele & Capecchi Danilo - 2015 - Springer.
    This book presents a historical and scientific analysis as historical epistemology of the science of weights and mechanics in the sixteenth century, particularly as developed by Tartaglia in his Quesiti et inventioni diverse, Book VII and Book VIII (1546; 1554). -/- In the early 16th century mechanics was concerned mainly with what is now called statics and was referred to as the Scientia de ponderibus, generally pursued by two very different approaches. The first was usually referred to as (...), where the equilibrium of bodies was set as a balance of opposite tendencies to motion. The second, usually referred to as Archimedean, identified statics with centrobarica, the theory of centres of gravity based on symmetry considerations. In between the two traditions the Italian scholar Niccolò Fontana, better known as Tartaglia (1500?–1557), wrote the treatise Quesiti et inventioni diverse (1546). -/- This volume consists of three main parts. In the first, a historical excursus regarding Tartaglia’s lifetime, his scientific production and the Scientia de ponderibus in the Arabic-Islamic culture, and from the Middle Ages to the Renaissance, is presented. Secondly, all the propositions of Books VII and VIII, by relating them with the Problemata mechanica by the Aristotelian school and Iordani opvsculvm de ponderositate by Jordanus de Nemore are examined within the history and historical epistemology of science. The last part is relative to the original texts and critical transcriptions into Italian and Latin and an English translation. -/- This work gathers and re-evaluates the current thinking on this subject. It brings together contributions from two distinguished experts in the history and historical epistemology of science, within the fields of physics, mathematics and engineering. It also gives much-needed insight into the subject from historical and scientific points of view. The volume composition makes for absorbing reading for historians, epistemologists, philosophers and scientists. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  3
    Science and Philosophy : And Other Essays.Bernard Bosanquet - 1927 - Freeport, N.Y.,: Routledge.
    First published in 1927, _Science and Philosophy: And Other Essays_ is a collection of individual papers written by Bernard Bosanquet during his highly industrious philosophical life. The collection was put together by Bosanquet’s wife after the death of the writer and remains mostly unaltered with just a few papers added and the order of entries improved. The papers here displayed consist of various contributions Bosanquet made to _Mind_, the _Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society_, the _International Journal of Ethics_ and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  5
    Mathematical Logic in the History of Logic: Łukasiewicz’s Contribution and Its Reception.Zuzana Rybaříková - 2024 - History and Philosophy of Logic 45 (2):98-108.
    AbstractŁukasiewicz introduced a new methodological approach to the history of logic. It consists of the use of modern formal logic in the research of the history of logic. Although he was not the first to use formal logic in his historical research, Łukasiewicz was the first who used it consistently and formulated it as a requirement for a historian of logic. The aim of this paper is to present Łukasiewicz's contribution and the history of its formulation. In addition, the paper (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  24
    Elliptical orbits and the Aristotelian Scientific Revolution.James Franklin - 2016 - Studia Neoaristotelica 13 (2):69-79.
    The Scientific Revolution was far from the anti-Aristotelian movement traditionally pictured. Its applied mathematics pursued by new means the Aristotelian ideal of science as knowledge by insight into necessary causes. Newton’s derivation of Kepler’s elliptical planetary orbits from the inverse square law of gravity is a central example.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  38
    Elliptical Orbits and the Aristotelian Scientific Revolution Comment on Groarke.James Franklin - 2016 - Studia Neoaristotelica 13 (2):169-179.
    The Scientific Revolution was far from the anti-Aristotelian movement traditionally pictured. Its applied mathematics pursued by new means the Aristotelian ideal of science as knowledge by insight into necessary causes. Newton’s derivation of Kepler’s elliptical planetary orbits from the inverse square law of gravity is a central example.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Remaking the science of mind: Psychology as a natural science.Gary Hatfield - 1995 - In Christopher Fox, Roy Porter & Robert Wokler (eds.), Inventing Human Science: Eighteenth Century Domains. University of California Press. pp. 184–231.
    Psychology considered as a natural science began as Aristotelian "physics" or "natural philosophy" of the soul, conceived as an animating power that included vital, sensory, and rational functions. C. Wolff restricted the term " psychology " to sensory, cognitive, and volitional functions and placed the science under metaphysics, coordinate with cosmology. Near the middle of the eighteenth century, Krueger, Godart, and Bonnet proposed approaching the mind with the techniques of the new natural science. At nearly the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000