Switch to: Citations

References in:

Stove's critique of "irrationalists"

Metaphilosophy 18 (2):149–160 (1987)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Paradigms.Daniel Goldman Cedarbaum - 1983 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 14 (3):173-213.
  • Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism.David Charles Stove - 1973 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    This book aims to discuss probability and David Hume's inductive scepticism. For the sceptical view which he took of inductive inference, Hume only ever gave one argument. That argument is the sole subject-matter of this book. The book is divided into three parts. Part one presents some remarks on probability. Part two identifies Hume's argument for inductive scepticism. Finally, the third part evaluates Hume's argument for inductive scepticism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Problem of Meaning in Linguistics.W. V. O. Quine - 1953 - In Willard Van Orman Quine (ed.), From a Logical Point of View. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 47-64.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   221 citations  
  • Changes in the Problem of Inductive Logic.Imre Lakatos - 1968 - In The problem of inductive logic. Amsterdam,: North Holland Pub. Co.. pp. 315--417.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?T. S. Kuhn - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 22.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Reflections on my Critics1.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 231.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes.Lakatos Imre - 1970 - In Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 91-195.
  • The philosophy of science.Stephen Toulmin - 1953 - New York,: Hutchinson's University Library.
  • From a Logical Point of View.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1953 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • Patterns of discovery.Norwood Russell Hanson - 1958 - Cambridge [Eng.]: University Press.
    In this 1958 book, Professor Hanson turns to an equally important but comparatively neglected subject, the philosophical aspects of research and discovery.
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    In the course of the discussion, Professor Quine pinpoints the difficulties involved in translation, brings to light the anomalies and conflicts implicit in our ...
  • The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.Thomas S. Kuhn - 1962 - Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Ian Hacking.
  • The problem of inductive logic.Imre Lakatos (ed.) - 1968 - Amsterdam,: North Holland Pub. Co..
  • Against Method.Mark Wilson - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (1):106.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Science; an Introduction.Stephen Edelston Toulmin - 1960 - Hassell Street Press.
    This work has been selected by scholars as being culturally important and is part of the knowledge base of civilization as we know it. This work is in the public domain in the United States of America, and possibly other nations. Within the United States, you may freely copy and distribute this work, as no entity (individual or corporate) has a copyright on the body of the work. Scholars believe, and we concur, that this work is important enough to be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Probability and Hume's inductive scepticism.David Charles Stove - 1973 - Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.
    This book aims to discuss probability and David Hume's inductive scepticism. For the sceptical view which he took of inductive inference, Hume only ever gave one argument. That argument is the sole subject-matter of this book. The book is divided into three parts. Part one presents some remarks on probability. Part two identifies Hume's argument for inductive scepticism. Finally, the third part evaluates Hume's argument for inductive scepticism. Hume's argument that induction must be either deductively valid or circular because based (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Hume, The Causal Principle, and Kemp Smith.David C. Stove - 1975 - Hume Studies 1 (1):1-24.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:HUME, THE CAUSAL PRINCIPLE, AN'D KEMP SMITH When we say of a proposition that it is possible, we sometimes mean no more than that it is logically possible, that is, consistent with itself. A proposition can be possible in stronger senses than this, but not in any weaker one. For a sense of "p is possible" that did not entail "p is self-consistent, "would have to be a sense (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hume, probability, and induction.D. Stove - 1965 - Philosophical Review 74 (2):160-177.
  • II. Feyerabend's democratic relativism.Steven Yates - 1984 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 27 (1-4):137-142.
    This note criticizes the political consequences Feyerabend draws from his ?epistemological anarchism?. Democratic relativism holds that since no traditions are ?true?, all must be given equal status in a free society. A basic protective structure is required, though, to keep the various institutions from overwhelming one another. I argue that Feyerabend provides no assurance that the protective structure would not be taken over by particular institutions; parallel problems exist for education. Hence Feyerabend's proposal is unworkable in principle. Furthermore it is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mr. Strawson on referring.Bertrand Russell - 1957 - Mind 66 (263):385-389.
    Leaving detail aside, I think we may sum up Mr. Strawson's argument and my reply to it as follows: There are two problems, that of descriptions and that of egocentricity. Mr. Strawson thinks they are one and the same problem, but it is obvious from his discussion that he has not considered as many kinds of descriptive phrases as are relevant to the argument. Having confused the two problems, he asserts dogmatically that it is only the egocentric problem that needs (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature[REVIEW]Alvin I. Goldman - 1981 - Philosophical Review 90 (3):424-429.
  • From a Logical Point of View.Richard M. Martin - 1955 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15 (4):574-575.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   566 citations  
  • Reason, truth, and history.Hilary Putnam - 1981 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Hilary Putnam deals in this book with some of the most fundamental persistent problems in philosophy: the nature of truth, knowledge and rationality. His aim is to break down the fixed categories of thought which have always appeared to define and constrain the permissible solutions to these problems.
  • The Problem of Inductive Logic.Alex C. Michalos - 1972 - Philosophy of Science 39 (1):90-91.
  • Criticism and the growth of knowledge.Imre Lakatos & Alan Musgrave (eds.) - 1970 - Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press.
    Two books have been particularly influential in contemporary philosophy of science: Karl R. Popper's Logic of Scientific Discovery, and Thomas S. Kuhn's Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Both agree upon the importance of revolutions in science, but differ about the role of criticism in science's revolutionary growth. This volume arose out of a symposium on Kuhn's work, with Popper in the chair, at an international colloquium held in London in 1965. The book begins with Kuhn's statement of his position followed by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   879 citations  
  • A Treatise of Human Nature.David Hume & A. D. Lindsay - 1958 - Philosophical Quarterly 8 (33):379-380.
  • Wittgenstein's philosophical investigations.Paul Feyerabend - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (3):449-483.
  • Science in a free society.Paul Feyerabend - 1978 - London: NLB.
    No study in the philosophy of science created such controversy in the seventies as Paul Feyerabend's Against Method. In this work, Feyerabend reviews that controversy, and extends his critique beyond the problem of scientific rules and methods, to the social function and direction of science today. In the first part of the book, he launches a sustained and irreverent attack on the prestige of science in the West. The lofty authority of the "expert" claimed by scientists is, he argues, incompatible (...)
  • Against method.Paul Feyerabend - 1975 - London: New Left Books.
  • Against method: outline of an anarchistic theory of knowledge.Paul Feyerabend - 1974 - Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press.
    Paul Feyerabend's globally acclaimed work, which sparked and continues to stimulate fierce debate, examines the deficiencies of many widespread ideas about scientific progress and the nature of knowledge. Feyerabend argues that scientific advances can only be understood in a historical context. He looks at the way the philosophy of science has consistently overemphasized practice over method, and considers the possibility that anarchism could replace rationalism in the theory of knowledge. -- Amazon.com.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   220 citations  
  • How Popper's Philosophy Began.D. C. Stove - 1982 - Philosophy 57 (221):381 - 387.
  • True to the facts.Donald Davidson - 1969 - Journal of Philosophy 66 (21):748-764.
  • More than a marriage of convenience: On the inextricability of history and philosophy of science.Richard M. Burian - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (1):1-42.
    History of science, it has been argued, has benefited philosophers of science primarily by forcing them into greater contact with "real science." In this paper I argue that additional major benefits arise from the importance of specifically historical considerations within philosophy of science. Loci for specifically historical investigations include: (1) making and evaluating rational reconstructions of particular theories and explanations, (2) estimating the degree of support earned by particular theories and theoretical claims, and (3) evaluating proposed philosophical norms for the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Reason, Truth and History.Hilary Putnam - 1981 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Hilary Putnam deals in this book with some of the most fundamental persistent problems in philosophy: the nature of truth, knowledge and rationality. His aim is to break down the fixed categories of thought which have always appeared to define and constrain the permissible solutions to these problems.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   584 citations  
  • A treatise of human nature.David Hume & D. G. C. Macnabb (eds.) - 1969 - Harmondsworth,: Penguin Books.
    One of Hume's most well-known works and a masterpiece of philosophy, A Treatise of Human Nature is indubitably worth taking the time to read.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   896 citations  
  • Genesis and development of a scientific fact.Ludwik Fleck - 1979 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by T. J. Trenn & R. K. Merton.
    The sociological dimension of science is studied using the discovery of the Wasserman reaction and its accidental application as a test for syphilis as a basis, ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   323 citations  
  • Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.Richard Rorty - 1979 - Princeton University Press.
    This edition includes new essays by philosopher Michael Williams and literary scholar David Bromwich, as well as Rorty's previously unpublished essay "The ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1194 citations  
  • Popper and after: four modern irrationalists.David Charles Stove - 1982 - New York: Pergamon Press.
    Stove argues that Popper and his successors in the philosophy of science, Kuhn, Lakatos and Feyerabend, were irrationalists because they were deductivists. That is, they believed all logic is deductive, and thus denied that experimental evidence could make scientific theories logically more probable. The book was reprinted as Anything Goes (1998) and Scientific Irrationalism: Origins of a Postmodern Cult (1998).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Is Logic Empirical?Hilary Putnam - 1968 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5.
  • Explanation, Reduction and Empiricism.Paul K. Feyerabend - 1962 - In H. Feigl and G. Maxwell (ed.), Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía. pp. 103-106.
  • Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism.D. C. Stove - 1977 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (1):203-211.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Probability and Hume's Inductive Scepticism.D. C. Stove - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 35 (3):646-647.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning.Carl G. Hempel - 1950 - 11 Rev. Intern. De Philos 41 (11):41-63.
    The fundamental tenet of modern empiricism is the view that all non-analytic knowledge is based on experience. Let us call this thesis the principle of empiricism. [1] Contemporary logical empiricism has added [2] to it the maxim that a sentence makes a cognitively meaningful assertion, and thus can be said to be either true or false, only if it is either (1) analytic or self-contradictory or (2) capable, at least in principle, of experiential test. According to this so-called empiricist criterion (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2231 citations  
  • Word and Object.Willard Van Orman Quine - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 17 (2):278-279.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2807 citations  
  • Patterns of Discovery.Norwood R. Hanson, A. D. Ritchie & Henryk Mehlberg - 1960 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (40):346-349.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   627 citations  
  • Philosophical Investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 4 (15):258-260.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   333 citations  
  • Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.Richard Rorty - 1979 - Philosophy 56 (217):427-429.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   360 citations  
  • Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.Richard Rorty - 1979 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 170 (4):463-464.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   361 citations  
  • Science in a Free Society.Paul Feyerabend - 1978 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 169 (4):448-451.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations