Results for 'Matthew McKeon'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  4
    In Defense of a Normative Concept of Argument.Matthew W. McKeon - forthcoming - Argumentation:1-18.
    Blair articulates a concept of argument that suggests, as he puts it, that argument is a normative concept (Blair, Informal Logic 24:137–151, 2004, p. 190). Put roughly, the idea is that a collection of propositions doesn’t constitute an argument unless some taken together constitute a reason for the remaining proposition and thereby support it enough to provide at least prima facie justification for it (Blair, in: Blair, Johnson, Hansen, Tindale (eds) Informal Logic at 25, Proceedings of the 25th anniversary conference, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. On the Rationale for Distinguishing Arguments from Explanations.Matthew W. McKeon - 2013 - Argumentation 27 (3):283-303.
    Even with the lack of consensus on the nature of an argument, the thesis that explanations and arguments are distinct is near orthodoxy in well-known critical thinking texts and in the more advanced argumentation literature. In this paper, I reconstruct two rationales for distinguishing arguments from explanations. According to one, arguments and explanations are essentially different things because they have different structures. According to the other, while some explanations and arguments may have the same structure, they are different things because (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3.  7
    Inference Claims as Assertions.Matthew William Mckeon - 2021 - Informal Logic 42 (4):359-390.
    When a speaker states an argument in arguing—in its core sense—for the conclusion, the speaker asserts, as opposed to merely implies or implicates, the associated inference claim to the effect that the conclusion follows from the premises. In defense of this, I argue that how an inference claim is conveyed when stating an argument is constrained by constitutive and normative conditions for core cases of the speech of arguing for a conclusion. The speech act of assertion better reflects such conditions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  15
    Action Guidance and Educating for Intellectual Virtue: A Response to Kotzee, Carter, and Siegel.Matthew McKeon & Matthew Ferkany - forthcoming - Episteme:1-21.
    In their “Educating for Intellectual Virtue: A Critique from Action Guidance” Kotzee, Carter and Siegel (2019) argue against what they call the intellectual virtues (IV) approach to the primary epistemic aim of education and in favor of what they call the critical thinking (CT) approach. The IV approach says that educating for intellectual virtue is the primary epistemic aim of education. The CT approach says that it is educating for critical thinking. They argue that the exemplarist/role-modeling pedagogy of the IV (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. The Concept of Logical Consequence: An Introduction to Philosophical Logic.Matthew W. McKeon - 2010 - Peter Lang.
    Introduction -- The concept of logical consequence -- Tarski's characterization of the common concept of logical consequence -- The logical consequence relation has a modal element -- The logical consequence relation is formal -- The logical consequence relation is A priori -- Logical and non-logical terminology -- The meanings of logical terms explained in terms of their semantic properties -- The meanings of logical terms explained in terms of their inferential properties -- Model-theoretic and deductive-theoretic conceptions of logic -- Linguistic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  6.  20
    Arguments and Reason-Giving.Matthew W. McKeon - 2022 - Argumentation 36 (2):229-247.
    Arguments figure prominently in our practices of reason-giving. For example, we use them to advance reasons for their conclusions in order to justify believing something, to explain why we believe something, and to persuade others to believe something. Intuitively, using arguments in these ways requires a certain degree of self-reflection. In this paper, I ask: what cognitive requirements are there for using an argument to advance reasons for its conclusion? Towards a partial response, the paper’s central thesis is that in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  22
    Argument, Inference, and Persuasion.Matthew William McKeon - 2020 - Argumentation 35 (2):339-356.
    This paper distinguishes between two types of persuasive force arguments can have in terms of two different connections between arguments and inferences. First, borrowing from Pinto, an arguer's invitation to inference directly persuades an addressee if the addressee performs an inference that the arguer invites. This raises the question of how invited inferences are determined by an invitation to inference. Second, borrowing from Sorenson, an arguer's invitation to inference indirectly persuades an addressee if the addressee performs an inference guided by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  31
    Logical Properties: Identity, Existence, Predication, Necessity, Truth.Matthew McKeon - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (1):39-42.
    Identity, existence, predication, necessity, and truth are fundamental philosophical concerns. Colin McGinn treats them both philosophically and logically, aiming for maximum clarity and minimum pointless formalism. He contends that there are real logical properties that challenge naturalistic metaphysical outlooks. These concepts are not definable, though we can say a good deal about how they work. The aim of Logical Properties is to bring philosophy back to philosophical logic.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  45
    On the Substitutional Characterization of First-Order Logical Truth.Matthew McKeon - 2004 - History and Philosophy of Logic 25 (3):205-224.
    I consider the well-known criticism of Quine's characterization of first-order logical truth that it expands the class of logical truths beyond what is sanctioned by the model-theoretic account. Briefly, I argue that at best the criticism is shallow and can be answered with slight alterations in Quine's account. At worse the criticism is defective because, in part, it is based on a misrepresentation of Quine. This serves not only to clarify Quine's position, but also to crystallize what is and what (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  10.  2
    Inference Claims as Assertions.Matthew William Mckeon - 2021 - Informal Logic 43 (1):359-390.
    When a speaker states an argument in arguing—in its core sense—for the conclusion, the speaker asserts, as opposed to merely implies or implicates, the associated inference claim to the effect that the conclusion follows from the premises. In defense of this, I argue that how an inference claim is conveyed when stating an argument is constrained by constitutive and normative conditions for core cases of the speech of arguing for a conclusion. The speech act of assertion better reflects such conditions (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  53
    Statements of inference and begging the question.Matthew W. McKeon - 2017 - Synthese 194 (6):1919-1943.
    I advance a pragmatic account of begging the question according to which a use of an argument begs the question just in case it is used as a statement of inference and it fails to state an inference the arguer or an addressee can perform given what they explicitly believe. Accordingly, what begs questions are uses of arguments as statements of inference, and the root cause of begging the question is an argument’s failure to state an inference performable by the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Logic and existential commitment.Matthew Mckeon - 2004 - Logique Et Analyse 47:195-214.
  13.  4
    Arguments and reason-giving.Matthew W. McKeon - 2024 - New york, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Arguments, understood initially as premise-conclusion complexes of propositions, figure in our practices of giving reasons. Among other uses, we use arguments to advance reasons to explain why we believe or did something, to justify our beliefs or actions, to persuade others to do or to believe something, and (following Pinto 2001b) to advance reasons to worry or to fear that something is true. This book is about our uses of arguments to advance their premises as reasons for believing their conclusions, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  70
    A plea for logical objects.Matthew William McKeon - 2009 - Synthese 167 (1):163-182.
    An account of validity that makes what is invalid conditional on how many individuals there are is what I call a conditional account of validity. Here I defend conditional accounts against a criticism derived from Etchemendy’s well-known criticism of the model-theoretic analysis of validity. The criticism is essentially that knowledge of the size of the universe is non-logical and so by making knowledge of the extension of validity depend on knowledge of how many individuals there are, conditional accounts fail to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  63
    Bertrand Russell and logical truth.Matthew Mckeon - 1999 - Philosophia 27 (3-4):541-553.
    I expose a tension in Bertrand Russell's, _Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, between his account of logical truth and his view that logical truth is knowable without taking into account what the world is like. Russell makes the logical truth of a sentence turn on the actual truth of its second-order universal closure. But this results in making logical truth relative to the number of worldly individuals. I aim to use the tension in _Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy to classify the status (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  21
    Forall x: An Introduction to Formal Logic, Version 1.11.Matthew McKeon - 2006 - Teaching Philosophy 4 (4):387-390.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  60
    Inference, Circularity, and Begging the Question.Mckeon Matthew William - 2015 - Informal Logic 35 (3):312-341.
    I develop a syntactic concept of circularity, which I call propositional circularity. With respect to a given use of an argument advanced as a statement of inference for the benefit of a reasoner R, if the direct and indirect premises R would have to accept in order to accept the conclusion includes the conclusion, then the collection of premises is propositionally circular. The argument fails to display a type of inference that R can perform. Appealing to propositional circularity, I articulate (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Logic and Necessary Being.Matthew Mckeon - 1996 - Sorites 4:21-35.
    Yuval Steinitz has argued that, since it is logically possible that there are logically necessary beings, it follows that there is at least one logically necessary being. Steinitz switches the Leibnitzean ontological argument's concern from perfect beings to logically necessary beings. My paper has two primary aims. First, I argue that Steinitz's quick treatment is insufficient to establish the validity of his argument. Secondly, I argue that the correct approach to logical necessity must account for those possible situations in which (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Logical consequence, deductive-theoretic conceptions.Matthew McKeon - 2004 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  20. Logical consequence, philosophical considerations.Matthew McKeon - 2004 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  21. Logic, Semantics, and Possible Worlds.Matthew William Mckeon - 1994 - Dissertation, The University of Connecticut
    The general issue addressed in this dissertation is: what do the models of formal model-theoretic semantics represent? In chapter 2, I argue that those of first-order classical logic represent meaning assignments in possible worlds. This motivates an inquiry into what the interpretations of first-order quantified model logic represent, and in Chapter 3 I argue that they represent meaning assignments in possible universes of possible worlds. A possible universe is unpacked as one way model reality might be. The problem arises here (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  15
    Logical Truth in Modal Logic.Matthew McKeon - 1996 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 77 (4):351-361.
    In this paper, I consider the criticism due to Hartry Field, John Pollack, William Hanson and James Hawthorne that the Kripkean requirement that a logical truth in modal logic be true at all possible worlds in _all quantified model structures is unmotivated and misses some logical truths. These authors do not see the basis for making the logical truth of a modal sentence turn on more than the model structure given by one reading of the modal operator(s) which occur in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  8
    14. On the Substitutional Approach to Logical Consequence.Matthew Mckeon - 2005 - In Kent A. Peacock & Andrew D. Irvine (eds.), Mistakes of reason: essays in honour of John Woods. Buffalo: University of Toronto Press. pp. 243-263.
  24.  10
    What does formal logic have to do with arguments?Matthew W. McKeon - 2022 - Metaphilosophy 53 (5):696-708.
    This paper sharpens the distinction between inferential and logcon arguments. Inferential arguments represent possible inferences, logcon ones need not. This distinction clarifies the roles that arguments play in accounting for the normativity of validity for inferential reasoning and in establishing the theoretical connection between validity and logical consequence. There are two related takeaways. First, the normativity of validity for inferential reasoning is grounded on the notion of an inferential argument. This will account for the use of validity to judge inference (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  15
    Forall X. [REVIEW]Matthew McKeon - 2006 - Teaching Philosophy 29 (4):387-390.
  26.  37
    Forall X. [REVIEW]Matthew McKeon - 2006 - Teaching Philosophy 29 (4):387-390.
  27.  18
    McGinn Colin. Logical properties: identity, existence, predication, necessity, truth. Clarendon Press, Oxford 2000, vi+ 114 pp. [REVIEW]Matthew McKeon - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (1):39-42.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  28
    Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth". [REVIEW]Matthew McKeon - 2012 - Essays in Philosophy 13 (2):623-631.
  29. Review of “Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus”. [REVIEW]Matthew McKeon - 2004 - Essays in Philosophy 5 (2):24.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  6
    Review of Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, by Ludwig Wittgenstein, trans. C. K. Ogden. [REVIEW]Matthew McKeon - 2004 - Essays in Philosophy 5 (2):535-537.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  4
    Review of The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth, by Leon Horsten. [REVIEW]Matthew McKeon - 2012 - Essays in Philosophy 13 (2):623-631.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  13
    Book Review:The Early Philosophers of Greece. Matthew Thompson McClure, Richard Lattimore. [REVIEW]Richard McKeon - 1937 - International Journal of Ethics 47 (3):399-.
  33.  39
    The Early Philosophers of Greece. Matthew Thompson McClure, Richard Lattimore.Richard McKeon - 1937 - International Journal of Ethics 47 (3):399-402.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. The Early Philosophers of Greece. By Richard McKeon[REVIEW]Matthew Thompson Mcclure - 1936 - International Journal of Ethics 47:399.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  25
    Freedom and history and other essays: an introduction to the thought of Richard McKeon.Richard McKeon - 1990 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by Zahava Karl McKeon.
    This volume of essays is an important introduction to the thought of one of the twentieth century's most significant yet underappreciated philosophers, Richard McKeon. The originator of philosophical pluralism, McKeon made extraordinary contributions to philosophy, to international relations, and to theory-formation in the communication arts, aesthetics, the organization of knowledge, and the practical sciences. This collection, which includes a philosophical autobiography as well as the out-of-print title essay "Freedom and History" and a previously unpublished essay on "Philosophic Semantics (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  36.  12
    The philosophy of Spinoza: the unity of his thought.Richard McKeon - 1928 - Woodbridge, Conn.: Ox Bow Press.
  37.  21
    On knowing--the natural sciences.Richard McKeon - 1994 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Edited by David B. Owen & Zahava Karl McKeon.
    Well before the current age of discourse, deconstruction, and multiculturalism, Richard McKeon propounded a philosophy of pluralism showing how "facts" and "values" are dependent on diverse ways of reading texts. This book is a transcription of an entire course, including both lectures and student discussions, taught by McKeon. As such, it provides an exciting introduction to McKeon's conception of pluralism, a central aspect of neo-Pragmatism, while demonstrating how pluralism works in a classroom setting. In his lectures, (...) outlines the entire history of Western thinking on the sciences. Treating the central concepts of motion, space, time, and cause, he traces modern intellectual debates back to the ancient Greeks, notably Plato, Aristotle, Democritus, and the Sophists. As he brings the story of Western science up to the twentieth century, he uses his fabled semantic schema (reproduced here for the first time) to uncover new ideas and observations about cosmology, mechanics, dynamics, and other aspects of physical science. Illustrating the broad historical sweep of the lectures are a series of discussions which give detail to the course's intellectual framework. These discussions of Plato, Aristotle, Galileo, Newton, and Maxwell are perhaps the first published rendition of a philosopher in literal dialogue with his students. Led by McKeon's pointed questioning, the discussions reveal the difficulties and possibilities of learning to engage in serious intellectual communication. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Leadership After Virtue: MacIntyre’s Critique of Management Reconsidered.Matthew Sinnicks - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 147 (4):735-746.
    MacIntyre argues that management embodies emotivism, and thus is inherently amoral and manipulative. His claim that management is necessarily Weberian is, at best, outdated, and the notion that management aims to be neutral and value free is incorrect. However, new forms of management, and in particular the increased emphasis on leadership which emerged after MacIntyre’s critique was published, tend to support his central charge. Indeed, charismatic and transformational forms of leadership seem to embody emotivism to a greater degree than do (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  39. Nietzsche on the beginnings of western philosophy.Gareth B. Matthews - 2004 - In Jorge J. E. Gracia & Jiyuan Yu (eds.), Uses and abuses of the classics: Western interpretations of Greek philosophy. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.
  40. Mad Max and Philosophy.Matthew Meyer, David Koepsell & William Irwin (eds.) - 2024 - New York: Wiley.
    Beneath the stylized violence and thrilling car crashes, the Mad Max films consider universal questions about the nature of human life, order and anarchy, justice and moral responsibility, society and technology, and ultimately, human redemption. In Mad Max and Philosophy, a diverse team of political scientists, historians, and philosophers investigates the underlying themes of the blockbuster movie franchise, following Max as he attempts to rebuild himself and the world. -/- This book guides you through the barren wastelands of a post-apocalyptic (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. A moment like this : American idol and narratives of meritocracy.Matthew Wheelock Stahl - 2004 - In Christopher Washburne & Maiken Derno (eds.), Bad music: the music we love to hate. New York: Routledge.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  5
    The scientific background to modern philosophy: selected readings.Michael R. Matthews (ed.) - 2022 - Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
    The first edition of The Scientific Background to Modern Philosophy took the dialogue of science and philosophy from Aristotle through to Newton. This second edition adds eight chapters, taking the dialogue through the Enlightenment and up to Darwin. This anthology is an attempt to help bridge the gap between the history of science and the history of philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. What is Masculinity?Matthew Andler - 2023 - Synthese 202 (3):1-16.
    This paper initiates analytic inquiry into the metaphysics of masculinity. I argue that individual masculinities (such as ‘clone masculinity’ and ‘incel masculinity’) are distinct homeostatic property cluster kinds related to gender structures via processes of adherence, failed-adherence, selective adherence, and/or reinterpretation with respect to male-coded social norms.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. The Just World Fallacy as a Challenge to the Business-As-Community Thesis.Matthew Sinnicks - 2020 - Business and Society 59 (6):1269-1292.
    The notion that business organizations are akin to Aristotelian political communities has been a central feature of research into virtue ethics in business. In this article, I begin by outlining this “community thesis” and go on to argue that psychological research into the “just world fallacy” presents it with a significant challenge. The just world fallacy undermines our ability to implement an Aristotelian conception of justice, to each as he or she is due, and imperils the relational equality required for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45. Symmetry arguments against regular probability: A reply to recent objections.Matthew W. Parker - 2019 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 9 (1):1-21.
    A probability distribution is regular if it does not assign probability zero to any possible event. While some hold that probabilities should always be regular, three counter-arguments have been posed based on examples where, if regularity holds, then perfectly similar events must have different probabilities. Howson and Benci et al. have raised technical objections to these symmetry arguments, but we see here that their objections fail. Howson says that Williamson’s “isomorphic” events are not in fact isomorphic, but Howson is speaking (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46. Two purposes of knowledge-attribution and the contextualism debate.Matthew McGrath - 2015 - In David K. Henderson & John Greco (eds.), Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press UK.
    In this chapter, we follow Edward Craig?s advice: ask what the concept of knowledge does for us and use our findings as clues about its application conditions. What a concept does for us is a matter of what we can do with it, and what we do with concepts is deploy them in thought and language. So, we will examine the purposes we have in attributing knowledge. This chapter examines two such purposes, agent evaluation and informant-suggestion, and brings the results (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  47.  22
    Hippocampal function and interference.Matthew L. Shapiro & David S. Olton - 1994 - In D. Schacter & E. Tulving (eds.), Memory Systems. MIT Press. pp. 1994--87.
  48.  36
    The Recognition Signal Hypothesis for the Adaptive Evolution of Religion.Luke J. Matthews - 2012 - Human Nature 23 (2):218-249.
    Recent research on the evolution of religion has focused on whether religion is an unselected by-product of evolutionary processes or if it is instead an adaptation by natural selection. Adaptive hypotheses for religion include direct fitness benefits from improved health and indirect fitness benefits mediated by costly signals and/or cultural group selection. Herein, I propose that religious denominations achieve indirect fitness gains for members through the use of ecologically arbitrary beliefs, rituals, and moral rules that function as recognition markers of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  44
    Socratic perplexity and the nature of philosophy.Gareth B. Matthews - 1999 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Gareth Matthews suggests that we can better understand the nature of philosophical inquiry if we recognize the central role played by perplexity. The seminal representation of philosophical perplexity is in Plato's dialogues; Matthews examines the intriguing shifts in Plato's attitude to perplexity and suggests that these may represent a course of philosophical development that philosophers follow even today.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  50. Feasibility and Normative Penetration.Matthew Lindauer & Nicholas Southwood - forthcoming - Journal of Moral Philosophy.
    An important theme in recent experimental philosophy is that certain judgements (e.g. our judgements involving intentional action and causation) exhibit a kind of normative penetration whereby, in spite of a not-obviously-normative subject matter, they turn out to be sensitive to, and co-vary with, our normative attitudes in interesting and surprising ways. We present the results of several new experimental studies that suggest that our judgements about feasibility also appear to exhibit this kind of normative penetration in at least some cases; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000