Results for 'Mathematics Early works to 1800.'

998 found
Order:
  1.  20
    Ilkka Niiniluoto Carnap on truth.I. Carnap'S. Early Work - 2003 - In Thomas Bonk (ed.), Language, Truth and Knowledge: Contributions to the Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 2--1.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  29
    The Brentanist Philosophy of Mathematics in Edmund Husserl’s Early Works.Carlo Ierna - 2017 - In Stefania Centrone (ed.), Essays on Husserl’s Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag. pp. 147-168.
    A common analysis of Edmund Husserl’s early works on the philosophy of logic and mathematics presents these writings as the result of a combination of two distinct strands of influence: on the one hand a mathematical influence due to his teachers is Berlin, such as Karl Weierstrass, and on the other hand a philosophical influence due to his later studies in Vienna with Franz Brentano. However, the formative influences on Husserl’s early philosophy cannot be so cleanly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  63
    Mind and Sign: Method and the Interpretation of Mathematics in Descartes’s Early Work.Amy M. Schmitter - 2000 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (3):371-411.
    Method may be second only to substance-dualism as the best-known among Descartes's enthusiasms. But knowing that Descartes wants to promote good method is one thing; knowing what exactly he wants to promote is another. Two views seem fairly widespread. The first rests on the claim that Descartes endorses a purely procedural picture of reason, so that right reasoning is a matter of proprieties of operation, rather than respect for its objects. On this view, a method for regulating our reason would (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  3
    Sasojŏl.Tŏng-mu Yi (ed.) - 1841 - Sŏul-si: Yanghyŏng̕ak.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  34
    Mind and Sign: Method and the Interpretation of Mathematics in Descartes's Early Work.Amy M. Schmitter - 2000 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30 (3):371-411.
    Method may be second only to substance-dualism as the best-known among Descartes's enthusiasms. But knowing that Descartes wants to promote good method is one thing; knowing what exactly he wants to promote is another. Two views seem fairly widespread. The first rests on the claim that Descartes endorses a purely procedural picture of reason, so that right reasoning is a matter of proprieties of operation, rather than respect for its objects. On this view, a method for regulating our reason would (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  10
    Barbara Cassin: Sophistical Reading.Paul Earlie - 2022 - Diacritics 50 (1):4-31.
    Abstract:Although best known to English-speaking readers as the general editor of the Dictionary of Untranslatables, the work of French philologist and philosopher Barbara Cassin is eclectic, encompassing literary studies, ancient philosophy, rhetoric, translation theory, psychoanalysis, politics, and more. From Presocratic philosophy to more recent reflections on Big Tech and democracy, Cassin's work is rooted in "sophistics," an approach that emphasizes the primacy of language in shaping our interactions with the world. Situating this sophistical approach vis-à-vis classical philology (Bollack) and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  4
    Derrida and the legacy of psychoanalysis.Paul Earlie - 2021 - New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press.
    This book offers a detailed account of the importance of psychoanalysis in Derrida's thought. Based on close readings of texts from the whole of his career, including less well-known and previously unpublished material, it sheds new light on the crucial role of psychoanalysis in shaping Derrida's response to a number of key questions. These questions range from the psyche's relationship to technology to the role of fiction and metaphor in scientific discourse, from the relationship between memory and the archive to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  17
    Why Mathematical Probability Failed to Emerge from Ancient Gambling.Stephen Kidd - 2020 - Apeiron 53 (1):1-25.
    The emergence of mathematical probability has something to do with dice games: all the early discussions (Cardano, Galileo, Pascal) suggest as much. Although this has long been recognized, the problem is that gambling at dice has been a popular pastime since antiquity. Why, then, did gamblers wait until the sixteenth century ce to calculate the math of dicing? Many theories have been offerred, but there may be a simple solution: early-modern gamblers played different sorts of dice games than (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  28
    Philosophical anthropology, ethics, and love: Toward a new religion and science dialogue.Christian Early - 2017 - Zygon 52 (3):847-863.
    Religion and science dialogues that orbit around rational method, knowledge, and truth are often, though not always, contentious. In this article, I suggest a different cluster of gravitational points around which religion and science dialogues might usefully travel: philosophical anthropology, ethics, and love. I propose seeing morality as a natural outgrowth of the human desire to establish and maintain social bonds so as not to experience the condition of being alone. Humans, of all animals, need to feel loved—defined as a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  7
    Complex continued fractions: early work of the brothers Adolf and Julius Hurwitz.Jörn J. Steuding & Nicola M. R. Oswald - 2014 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 68 (4):499-528.
    The two brothers Julius and Adolf Hurwitz were born in the middle of the nineteenth century in a small town near Hanover (not far from Göttingen). Already during their schooldays, the two of them became acquainted with mathematical problems and both started to study mathematics, but while the younger brother Adolf turned out to be extremely successful in his research, the elder brother and his work seem to be almost forgotten. This paper examines the lives and works of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  55
    Closing the circle: An analysis of Emil post's early work.Liesbeth de Mol - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (2):267-289.
    In 1931 Kurt Gödel published his incompleteness results, and some years later Church and Turing showed that the decision problem for certain systems of symbolic logic has a negative solution. However, already in 1921 the young logician Emil Post worked on similar problems which resulted in what he called an “anticipation” of these results. For several reasons though he did not submit these results to a journal until 1941. This failure ‘to be the first’, did not discourage him: his contributions (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  8
    Early writings in the philosophy of logic and mathematics.Edmund Husserl - 1994 - Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Edited by Dallas Willard.
    This book makes available to the English reader nearly all of the shorter philosophical works, published or unpublished, that Husserl produced on the way to the phenomenological breakthrough recorded in his Logical Investigations of 1900-1901. Here one sees Husserl's method emerging step by step, and such crucial substantive conclusions as that concerning the nature of Ideal entities and the status the intentional `relation' and its `objects'. Husserl's literary encounters with many of the leading thinkers of his day illuminates both (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  13.  16
    Deconstructive Empiricism: Science and Metaphor in Derrida's Early Work.Jeremy Butman - 2019 - Derrida Today 12 (2):115-129.
    The work of Jacques Derrida is often characterized as anti-scientific, and his philosophy of language taken to mean we are sealed off from empirical reality, confined to our metaphysical prison. This position is reinforced by the fact that his forerunners, Heidegger and Nietzsche, did diminish the importance of the sciences, and argued that we are enclosed within the limits of language. Today, philosophy continues to deconstruct the nature/culture distinction, and challenge the meaning of materialism, but in recent decades has realized (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  41
    Pantheism and Ontology In Wittgenstein’s Early Work.Newton Garver - 1971 - Idealistic Studies 1 (3):269-277.
    In reading the Tractatus, one gets the impression that Wittgenstein, having resolved to his satisfaction the problems about language, logic, science, and mathematics, sets these painstakingly articulated findings in a disproportionately skimpy setting. There is a perfunctory ontology at the beginning, which is highly original as well as austere and perplexing; and at the end he hurries even more than usual through ethics, aesthetics and religion—as if the silence was already coming upon him, prematurely. The Notebooks 1914–1916 help a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  65
    Logic and philosophy of mathematics in the early Husserl.Stefania Centrone - 2010 - New York: Springer.
    This volume will be of particular interest to researchers working in the history, and in the philosophy, of logic and mathematics, and more generally, to ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  16.  15
    Nominalism and Constructivism in Seventeenth-Century Mathematical Philosophy.David Sepkoski - 2007 - Routledge.
    Introduction: mathematization and the language of nature -- Realists and nominalists : language and mathematics before the scientific revolution -- Ontology recapitulates epistemology : Gassendi, epicurean atomism, and nominalism -- British empiricism, nominalism, and constructivism -- Three mathematicians : constructivist epistemology and the new mathematical methods -- Conclusion: mathematization and the nature of language.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  32
    Teaching Ethical Reasoning.G. Fletcher Linder, Allison J. Ames, William J. Hawk, Lori K. Pyle, Keston H. Fulcher & Christian E. Early - 2019 - Teaching Ethics 19 (2):147-170.
    This article presents evidence supporting the claim that ethical reasoning is a skill that can be taught and assessed. We propose a working definition of ethical reasoning as 1) the ability to identify, analyze, and weigh moral aspects of a particular situation, and 2) to make decisions that are informed and warranted by the moral investigation. The evidence consists of a description of an ethical reasoning education program—Ethical Reasoning in Action —designed to increase ethical reasoning skills in a variety of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  9
    Collected Works: Volume 1: Early Papers; General Papers.Michael Atiyah - 1988 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Professor Atiyah is one of the greatest living mathematicians and is well known throughout the mathematical world. He is a recipient of the Fields Medal, the mathematical equivalent of the Nobel Prize, and is still at the peak of his career. His huge number of published papers, focusing on the areas of algebraic geometry and topology, have here been collected into six volumes, divided thematically for easy reference by individuals interested in a particular subject. This first volume covers his (...) and general papers dating back to his first paper written in 1952 whilst being a second-year undergraduate student. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Self-prescribed and other informal care provided by physicians: scope, correlations and implications.Michael H. Gendel, Elizabeth Brooks, Sarah R. Early, Doris C. Gundersen, Steven L. Dubovsky, Steven L. Dilts & Jay H. Shore - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (5):294-298.
    Background While it is generally acknowledged that self-prescribing among physicians poses some risk, research finds such behaviour to be common and in certain cases accepted by the medical community. Largely absent from the literature is knowledge about other activities doctors perform for their own medical care or for the informal treatment of family and friends. This study examined the variety, frequency and association of behaviours doctors report providing informally. Informal care included prescriptions, as well as any other type of personal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Philosophy of mathematics in early Ernst Cassirer.Robert Maco - 2010 - Filozofia 65 (1):27-39.
    The paper deals with some major themes in early Cassirer’s philosophy of mathema- tics. It appears, that the basis of his thinking about mathematical objects and mathematical concept formation is his Neo-Kantian idealistic theory of concepts which he developed in opposition to what is called the „traditional theory of concepts“ going back to Aristotle. Cassirer often seeks to confirm his philo- sophical insights concerning mathematics by the interpretations the works of significant mathematicians. Therefore, the second part of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  12
    Early Analytic Philosophy: From Frege to Ramsey.Michael Potter - 2018 - Routledge.
    In this book, Michael Potter offers a fresh and compelling portrait of the birth and first several decades of analytic philosophy, one of the most important periods in philosophy’s long history. He focuses on the period between the publication of Gottlob Frege’s _Begriffsschrift _in 1879 and Frank Ramsey’s death in 1930. Potter--one of the most influential writers on late 19 th and early 20 th century philosophy--presents a deep but accessible account of the break with Absolute Idealism and Neo-Kantianism, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  29
    "Abraham, Planter of Mathematics"': Histories of Mathematics and Astrology in Early Modern Europe.Nicholas Popper - 2006 - Journal of the History of Ideas 67 (1):87-106.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Abraham, Planter of Mathematics":Histories of Mathematics and Astrology in Early Modern EuropeNicholas PopperFrancis Bacon's 1605 Advancement of Learning proposed to dedicatee James I a massive reorganization of the institutions, goals, and methods of generating and transmitting knowledge. The numerous defects crippling the contemporary educational regime, Bacon claimed, should be addressed by strengthening emphasis on philosophy and natural knowledge. To that end, university positions were to be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  4
    De Re Geometrica: Writing, Drawing, and Preaching Mathematics in Early Modern Mines.Thomas Morel - 2020 - Isis 111 (1):22-45.
    Georg Agricola’s De Re Metallica (1556) is an impressive work about mining arts and sciences, still used as a reference work to understand the mining world of his time and to analyze the relationships between scholars and practitioners. This essay begins by studying how Agricola presents the underground surveying, also known as geometria subterranea. How does the author’s mathematics relate to contemporary geometry or to actual surveying practices? Second, the essay contrasts his scholarly approach with sixteenth-century administrative and technical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  28
    Tensions in Garfinkel’s Ethnomethodological Studies of Work Programme Discussed Through Livingston’s Studies of Mathematics.Christian Greiffenhagen & Wes Sharrock - 2019 - Human Studies 42 (2):253-279.
    While Garfinkel’s early work, captured in Studies in Ethnomethodology, has received a lot of attention and discussion, this has not been the case for his later work since the 1970s. In this paper, we critically examine the aims of Garfinkel’s later ethnomethodological studies of work programme and evaluate key ideas such as the ‘missing what’ in the sociology of work, ‘the unique adequacy requirements of methods’, and the notion of ‘hybrid studies’. We do so through a detailed engagement with (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  11
    From Dedekind to Gödel: Essays on the Development of the Foundations of Mathematics.Jaakko Hintikka (ed.) - 1995 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Discussions of the foundations of mathematics and their history are frequently restricted to logical issues in a narrow sense, or else to traditional problems of analytic philosophy. From Dedekind to Gödel: Essays on the Development of the Foundations of Mathematics illustrates the much greater variety of the actual developments in the foundations during the period covered. The viewpoints that serve this purpose included the foundational ideas of working mathematicians, such as Kronecker, Dedekind, Borel and the early Hilbert, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26. David Adams.Early Exposure To Religion - 2009 - In Graham Oppy & Nick Trakakis (eds.), Medieval Philosophy of Religion: The History of Western Philosophy of Religion, Volume 2. Routledge. pp. 263.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Science in Merleau-Ponty's phenomenology: from the early work to the later philosophy.Komarine Romdenh-Romluc - 2018 - In Dan Zahavi (ed.), Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  28.  19
    “Nature Doth Not Work by Election”: John Wallis, Robert Grosseteste, and the Mathematical Laws of Nature.Adam D. Richter - 2018 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 7 (1):47-72.
    Though he is known primarily for his mathematics, John Wallis was also a prominent natural philosopher and experimentalist. Like many experimental philosophers, including his colleagues in the Royal So­ciety, Wallis sought to identify the mathematical laws that govern natural phenomena. However, I argue that Wallis’s particular understanding of the laws of nature was informed by his reading of a thirteenth–century optical treatise by Robert Grosseteste, De lineis, angulis et figuris, which expresses the principle that “Nature doth not work by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  94
    Nicolas Rashevsky's Mathematical Biophysics.Tara H. Abraham - 2004 - Journal of the History of Biology 37 (2):333 - 385.
    This paper explores the work of Nicolas Rashevsky, a Russian émigré theoretical physicist who developed a program in "mathematical biophysics" at the University of Chicago during the 1930s. Stressing the complexity of many biological phenomena, Rashevsky argued that the methods of theoretical physics -- namely mathematics -- were needed to "simplify" complex biological processes such as cell division and nerve conduction. A maverick of sorts, Rashevsky was a conspicuous figure in the biological community during the 1930s and early (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  13
    From Frege to Wittgenstein: Perspectives on Early Analytic Philosophy.Edited by Erich H. Reck (ed.) - 2002 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Analytic philosophy - arguably the most important philosophical movement in the 20th century - has gained a new historical self-consciousness, particularly about it's own origins. The period between 1880 and 1930 saw the most important work of its founding figures (Frege, Russell, Moore, Wittgenstein) take root and flourish. The fifteen previously-unpublished essays in this collection explore different facets of this period, with an emphasis on the vital intellectual relationship between Frege and the early Wittgenstein.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  13
    Philosophical aspects of symbolic reasoning in early modern mathematics.Albrecht Heeffer & Maarten Van Dyck - 2010 - London: College Publications.
    The novel use of symbolism in early modern mathematics poses both philosophical and historical questions. How can we trace its development and transmission through manuscript sources? Is it intrinsically related to the emergence of symbolic algebra? How does symbolism relate to the use of diagrams? What are the consequences of symbolic reasoning on our understanding of nature? Can a symbolic language enable new forms of reasoning? Does a universal symbolic language exist which enable us to express all knowledge? (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  50
    Steve Russ. The mathematical works of Bernard Bolzano. Oxford: Oxford university press, 2004. Pp. XXX + 698. Isbn 0-19-853930-. [REVIEW]Ali Behboud - 2006 - Philosophia Mathematica 14 (3):352-362.
    In his book on The Mathematics of Great Amateurs Coolidge starts the chapter on Bolzano saying that he included Bolzano because it seemed interesting to him ‘that a man who was a remarkable pulpit orator, only removed from his chair for his political opinions, should have thought so far into the deepest problems of a science which he never taught in a professional capacity’ [Coolidge, 1990, p. 195]. In fact, considering Bolzano's poor health and his enormous productivity in his (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  60
    The intelligibility of motion and construction: Descartes’ early mathematics and metaphysics, 1619–1637.Mary Domski - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (2):119-130.
    I argue for an interpretation of the connection between Descartes’ early mathematics and metaphysics that centers on the standard of geometrical intelligibility that characterizes Descartes’ mathematical work during the period 1619 to 1637. This approach remains sensitive to the innovations of Descartes’ system of geometry and, I claim, sheds important light on the relationship between his landmark Geometry and his first metaphysics of nature, which is presented in Le monde. In particular, I argue that the same standard of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34.  20
    Egg-Forms and Measure-Bodies: Different Mathematical Practices in the Early History of the Modern Theory of Convexity.Tinne Hoff Kjeldsen - 2009 - Science in Context 22 (1):85-113.
    ArgumentTwo simultaneous episodes in late nineteenth-century mathematical research, one by Karl Hermann Brunn and another by Hermann Minkowski, have been described as the origin of the theory of convex bodies. This article aims to understand and explain how and why the concept of such bodies emerged in these two trajectories of mathematical research; and why Minkowski's – and not Brunn's – strand of thought led to the development of a theory of convexity. Concrete pieces of Brunn's and Minkowski's mathematical work (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35. Cassirer's Psychology of Relations: From the Psychology of Mathematics and Natural Science to the Psychology of Culture.Samantha Matherne - 2018 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (3).
    In spite of Ernst Cassirer’s criticisms of psychologism throughout Substance and Function, in the final chapter he issues a demand for a “psychology of relations” that can do justice to the subjective dimensions of mathematics and natural science. Although these remarks remain somewhat promissory, the fact that this is how Cassirer chooses to conclude Substance and Function recommends it as a topic worthy of serious consideration. In this paper, I argue that in order to work out the details of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. Applying inconsistent mathematics.Mark Colyvan - unknown
    At various times, mathematicians have been forced to work with inconsistent mathematical theories. Sometimes the inconsistency of the theory in question was apparent (e.g. the early calculus), while at other times it was not (e.g. pre-paradox na¨ıve set theory). The way mathematicians confronted such difficulties is the subject of a great deal of interesting work in the history of mathematics but, apart from the crisis in set theory, there has been very little philosophical work on the topic of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  37.  14
    Texts, Practice and Practitioners: Computational Cultures at Work in Early Modern South India.D. Senthil Babu - 2022 - Berichte Zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte 45 (4):561-580.
    This essay will discuss the hegemonic role that texts have come to play in the historiography of subcontinental mathematical traditions. It will argue that texts need to be studied as records of practices of people's working lives, grounded in social hierarchies. We will take particular mathematical texts to show how different occupational registers have come to shape practices that defy the binaries of concrete and abstract, high and low mathematics or the pure and applied conundrum. Measuring, counting and accounting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  99
    Mathematics, experience and laboratories: Herbart’s and Brentano’s role in the rise of scientific psychology.Wolfgang Huemer & Christoph Landerer - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (3):72-94.
    In this article we present and compare two early attempts to establish psychology as an independent scientific discipline that had considerable influence in central Europe: the theories of Johann Friedrich Herbart (1776—1841) and Franz Brentano (1838—1917). While both of them emphasize that psychology ought to be conceived as an empirical science, their conceptions show revealing differences. Herbart starts with metaphysical principles and aims at mathematizing psychology, whereas Brentano rejects all metaphysics and bases his method on a conception of inner (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  13
    The Early Wittgenstein on Metaphysics, Natural Science, Language and Value.Chon Tejedor - 2014 - New York: Routledge.
    This book advances a reading of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus that moves beyond the main interpretative options of the New Wittgenstein debate. It covers Wittgenstein’s approach to language and logic, as well as other areas unduly neglected in the literature, such as his treatment of metaphysics, the natural sciences and value. Tejedor re-contextualises Wittgenstein’s thinking in these areas, plotting its evolution in his diaries, correspondence and pre- Tractatus texts, and developing a fuller picture of its intellectual background. This broadening of the angle (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  15
    Big in Reverse Mathematics: The Uncountability of the Reals.Sam Sanders - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-34.
    The uncountability of$\mathbb {R}$is one of its most basic properties, known far outside of mathematics. Cantor’s 1874 proof of the uncountability of$\mathbb {R}$even appears in the very first paper on set theory, i.e., a historical milestone. In this paper, we study the uncountability of${\mathbb R}$in Kohlenbach’shigher-orderReverse Mathematics (RM for short), in the guise of the following principle:$$\begin{align*}\mathit{for \ a \ countable \ set } \ A\subset \mathbb{R}, \mathit{\ there \ exists } \ y\in \mathbb{R}\setminus A. \end{align*}$$An important conceptual (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    Assessing Mathematical School Readiness.Sandrine Mejias, Claire Muller & Christine Schiltz - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10:439470.
    Early mathematical abilities matter for later formal arithmetical performances, school and professional success. Accordingly, it seems central to accurately assess numerical school readiness at school entrance. This is a prerequisite for identifying school-starters who are at risk to encounter difficulties in mathematics and stimulate their acquisition of mathematical fundamentals as soon as possible. In the present study, we present a new test which allows professionals working with children (e.g., teachers, school psychologists, speech therapists, school doctors) to assess children’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Mathematics and bleak house.John P. Burgess - 2004 - Philosophia Mathematica 12 (1):18-36.
    The form of nominalism known as 'mathematical fictionalism' is examined and found wanting, mainly on grounds that go back to an early antinominalist work of Rudolf Carnap that has unfortunately not been paid sufficient attention by more recent writers.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  43. Hilbert, logicism, and mathematical existence.José Ferreirós - 2009 - Synthese 170 (1):33 - 70.
    David Hilbert’s early foundational views, especially those corresponding to the 1890s, are analysed here. I consider strong evidence for the fact that Hilbert was a logicist at that time, following upon Dedekind’s footsteps in his understanding of pure mathematics. This insight makes it possible to throw new light on the evolution of Hilbert’s foundational ideas, including his early contributions to the foundations of geometry and the real number system. The context of Dedekind-style logicism makes it possible to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  44.  5
    The early proofs of the theorem of Campbell, Baker, Hausdorff, and Dynkin.Andrea Bonfiglioli & Rüdiger Achilles - 2012 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 66 (3):295-358.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a comprehensive exposition of the early contributions to the so-called Campbell, Baker, Hausdorff, Dynkin Theorem during the years 1890–1950. Related works by Schur, Poincaré, Pascal, Campbell, Baker, Hausdorff, and Dynkin will be investigated and compared. For a full recovery of the original sources, many mathematical details will also be furnished. In particular, we rediscover and comment on a series of five notable papers by Pascal (Lomb Ist Rend, 1901–1902), which nowadays (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism.Jared Warren - 2020 - New York, USA: Oxford University Press.
    What is the source of logical and mathematical truth? This book revitalizes conventionalism as an answer to this question. Conventionalism takes logical and mathematical truth to have their source in linguistic conventions. This was an extremely popular view in the early 20th century, but it was never worked out in detail and is now almost universally rejected in mainstream philosophical circles. Shadows of Syntax is the first book-length treatment and defense of a combined conventionalist theory of logic and (...). It argues that our conventions, in the form of syntactic rules of language use, are perfectly suited to explain the truth, necessity, and a priority of logical and mathematical claims, as well as our logical and mathematical knowledge. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  46.  33
    The early works, 1882-1898.John Dewey - 1967 - Carbondale,: Southern Illinois University Press.
    Volume 4 of’ “The Early Works” series covers the period of Dewey’s last year and one-half at the University of Michigan and his first half-year at the University of Chicago. In addition to sixteen articles the present volume contains Dewey’s reviews of six books and three articles, verbatim reports of three oral statements made by Dewey, and a full-length book, The Study of Ethics. Like its predecessors in this series, this volume presents a “clear text,” free of interpretive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  52
    Philosophy’s Loss of Logic to Mathematics: An Inadequately Understood Take-Over.Woosuk Park - 2018 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    This book offers a historical explanation of important philosophical problems in logic and mathematics, which have been neglected by the official history of modern logic. It offers extensive information on Gottlob Frege’s logic, discussing which aspects of his logic can be considered truly innovative in its revolution against the Aristotelian logic. It presents the work of Hilbert and his associates and followers with the aim of understanding the revolutionary change in the axiomatic method. Moreover, it offers useful tools to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48. Hermann Weyl's Mathematics, Science and Phenomenology.Richard A. Feist - 1999 - Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada)
    The work addresses the problem of the relationship between science and philosophy in the work of Hermann Weyl. The author begins by discussing Weylls Gottingen tradition. Contrary to standard accounts of this tradition, Edmund Husserl and Georg Cantor are included. The influence of this tradition on Weyl is then illustrated by an examination of Weyl's early philosophy of mathematics. Here Weyl attempts to use Husserl's early phenomenology to amalgamate the thought of Felix Klein, David Hilbert and Cantor. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  48
    Mathematical Hygiene.Andrew Arana & Heather Burnett - 2023 - Synthese 202 (4):1-28.
    This paper aims to bring together the study of normative judgments in mathematics as studied by the philosophy of mathematics and verbal hygiene as studied by sociolinguistics. Verbal hygiene (Cameron 1995) refers to the set of normative ideas that language users have about which linguistic practices should be preferred, and the ways in which they go about encouraging or forcing others to adopt their preference. We introduce the notion of mathematical hygiene, which we define in a parallel way (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Mathematical and Philosophical Works to Which is Prefix'd the Author's Life, and an Account of His Works.John Wilkins - 1708 - Nicholson.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 998