26 found
Order:
  1. Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science.Michael Friedman, Mary Domski & Michael Dickson (eds.) - 2010 - Open Court.
    Addressing a wide range of topics, from Newton to Post-Kuhnian philosophy of science, these essays critically examine themes that have been central to the influential work of philosopher Michael Friedman.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  2. Newton as historically-minded philosopher.Mary Domski - 2010 - In Michael Friedman, Mary Domski & Michael Dickson (eds.), Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science. Open Court.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3.  70
    Newton and Proclus: Geometry, imagination, and knowing space.Mary Domski - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):389-413.
    I aim to clarify the argument for space that Newton presents in De Gravitatione (composed prior to 1687) by putting Newton's remarks into conversation with the account of geometrical knowledge found in Proclus's Commentary on the First Book of Euclid's Elements (ca. 450). What I highlight is that both Newton and Proclus adopt an epistemic progression (or “order of knowing”) according to which geometrical knowledge necessarily precedes our knowledge of metaphysical truths concerning the ontological state of affairs. As I argue, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  4. The constructible and the intelligible in Newton's philosophy of geometry.Mary Domski - 2003 - Philosophy of Science 70 (5):1114-1124.
    In the preface to the Principia (1687) Newton famously states that “geometry is founded on mechanical practice.” Several commentators have taken this and similar remarks as an indication that Newton was firmly situated in the constructivist tradition of geometry that was prevalent in the seventeenth century. By drawing on a selection of Newton's unpublished texts, I hope to show the faults of such an interpretation. In these texts, Newton not only rejects the constructivism that took its birth in Descartes's Géométrie (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  5.  90
    Kant and Newton on the a priori necessity of geometry.Mary Domski - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (3):438-447.
  6.  13
    Observation and mathematics.Mary Domski - 2013 - In Peter R. Anstey (ed.), The Oxford handbook of British philosophy in the seventeenth century. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 144.
    This chapter, which examines the unity shared between what appear to be conflicting modes of natural investigation, an often neglected aspect of the history of British natural philosophy, also discusses the views of Francis Bacon on observation and experiment and describes his system of the sciences. It looks at aspects of Bacon's program for natural philosophy that made critics set the divide Baconian natural philosophy and the mathematical sciences of the seventeenth century. The chapter furthermore highlights the role of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7. Newton’s Empiricism and Metaphysics.Mary Domski - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (7):525-534.
    Commentators attempting to understand the empirical method that Isaac Newton applies in his Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (1687) are forced to grapple with the thorny issue of how to reconcile Newton's rejection of hypotheses with his appeal to absolute space. On the one hand, Newton claims that his experimental philosophy does not rely on claims that are assumed without empirical evidence, and on the other hand, Newton appeals to an absolute space that, by his own characterization, does not make (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  58
    The intelligibility of motion and construction: Descartes’ early mathematics and metaphysics, 1619–1637.Mary Domski - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (2):119-130.
    I argue for an interpretation of the connection between Descartes’ early mathematics and metaphysics that centers on the standard of geometrical intelligibility that characterizes Descartes’ mathematical work during the period 1619 to 1637. This approach remains sensitive to the innovations of Descartes’ system of geometry and, I claim, sheds important light on the relationship between his landmark Geometry and his first metaphysics of nature, which is presented in Le monde. In particular, I argue that the same standard of clear and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9. Laws of nature and the divine order of things : Descartes and Newton on truth in natural philosophy.Mary Domski - 2018 - In Walter R. Ott & Lydia Patton (eds.), Laws of Nature. Oxford University Press.
  10.  49
    Descartes' mathematics.Mary Domski - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. Discourse on a new method, or a manifesto for a synthetic approach to history and philosophy of science.Mary Domski & Michael Dickson - 2010 - In Michael Friedman, Mary Domski & Michael Dickson (eds.), Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science. Open Court.
  12.  9
    Working Hypotheses, Mathematical Representation, and the Logic of Theory-Mediation.Zvi Biener & Mary Domski - 2023 - In Marius Stan & Christopher Smeenk (eds.), Theory, Evidence, Data: Themes from George E. Smith. Springer. pp. 139-162.
    We examine the contrast between the “Newtonian style” and the Cartesian, hypothetico-deductive method in order to expand on George Smith's account of working hypotheses and theory-mediation. We stress the pivotal role of theory-mediation in turning experience into well-defined phenomena and introduce the complementary notions of conditional and independent evidence. Conditional evidence is evidence in favor of an hypothesis that is based on phenomena that would not be constituted as phenomena without the hypothesis in question. Direct evidence is evidence based on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Kant on the imagination and geometrical certainty.Mary Domski - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (4):409-431.
    My goal in this paper is to develop our understanding of the role the imagination plays in Kant’s Critical account of geometry, and I do so by attending to how the imagination factors into the method of reasoning Kant assigns the geometer in the First Critique. Such an approach is not unto itself novel. Recent commentators, such as Friedman (1992) and Young (1992), have taken a careful look at the constructions of the productive imagination in pure intuition and highlighted the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. Construction without spatial constraints: A reply to Emily Carson.Mary Domski - 2006 - Locke Studies 6:85-99.
  15. Geometry and Experimental Method in Locke, Newton and Kant.Mary Domski - 2003 - Dissertation, Indiana University
    Historians of modern philosophy have been paying increasing attention to contemporaneous scientific developments. Isaac Newton's Principia is of course crucial to any discussion of the influence of scientific advances on the philosophical currents of the modern period, and two philosophers who have been linked especially closely to Newton are John Locke and Immanuel Kant. My dissertation aims to shed new light on the ties each shared with Newtonian science by treating Newton, Locke, and Kant simultaneously. I adopt Newton's philosophy of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  38
    Imagination, metaphysics, mathematics: Descartes’s arguments for the Vortex Hypothesis.Mary Domski - 2019 - Synthese 196 (9):3505-3526.
    In this paper, I examine the manner in which Descartes defends his Vortex Hypothesis in Part III of the Principles of Philosophy, and expand on Ernan McMullin’s characterization of the methodology that Descartes uses to support his planetary system. McMullin illuminates the connection between the deductive method of Part III and the method Descartes uses in earlier portions of the Principles, and he brings needed light to the role that imaginative constructions play in Descartes’s explanations of the phenomena. I develop (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  39
    Introduction: “Newton and newtonianism”.Mary Domski - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):363-369.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  42
    Putting the Pieces Back Together Again: Reading Newton's Principia through Newton's Method.Mary Domski - 2013 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 3 (2):318-333.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  38
    Space, Geometry and Kant’s Transcendental Deduction of the Categories by Thomas C. Vinci.Mary Domski - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (1):174-175.
    Those familiar with the Critique of Pure Reason will not at all be surprised that Thomas C. Vinci has found it fitting to dedicate an entire book to the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories, a chapter of the CPR that is as important to Kant’s argument for Transcendental Idealism as it is difficult to decipher. The purpose of that section is to establish the objective validity of the categories—to show, that is, that the pure concepts of the understanding apply to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  85
    The God of matter, the God of geometry: The connection between Descartes' math and metaphysics.Mary Domski - unknown
    Building on the work of Henk Bos and John Schuster, I will examine how the story of Descartes-the-philosopher and Descartes-the-mathematician proceeds in the years immediately following 1628. Specifically, I will focus on the 1633 Le Monde and the 1637 Geometry and hope to show that Descartes is still trying in this period to integrate his distinctively Cartesian version of math with his distinctively Cartesian version of philosophy. Being even more specific, I will look at the creation story presented in Le (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. The transcendental and the geometrical: Kant's argument for the infinity of space.Mary Domski - 2008 - In Valerio Rohden, Ricardo R. Terra, Guido A. de Almeida & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Law and Peace in Kant's Philosophy. Walter de Gruyter.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  36
    Kant and the Early Moderns, edited by Daniel Garber and Béatrice Longuenesse. [REVIEW]Mary Domski - 2010 - Mind 119 (474):478-481.
  23.  11
    Lorenzo Magnani: Philosophy and Geometry: Theoretical and Historical Issues. [REVIEW]Mary Domski - 2004 - Philosophy of Science 71 (3):412-415.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  27
    Newton as Philosopher. [REVIEW]Mary Domski - 2009 - Early Science and Medicine 14 (4):590-592.
  25.  26
    Peter Machamer and J. E. McGuire. Descartes’s Changing Mind. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2009. Pp. xi+258. $39.50. [REVIEW]Mary Domski - 2011 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1):162-165.
  26.  26
    Putting the Pieces Back Together Again: Reading Newton’s Principia through Newton’s MethodSteffen Ducheyne. “The main Business of natural Philosophy”: Isaac Newton’s Natural-Philosophical Methodology. Dordrecht: Springer, 2012. Pp. xxv+352. $189.00 .William L. Harper. Isaac Newton’s Scientific Method: Turning Data into Evidence about Gravity and Cosmology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. Pp. xviii+424. $75.00. [REVIEW]Mary Domski - 2013 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 3 (2):318-333.