Results for 'Genetic Diseases, Inborn therapy'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  22
    The promise and peril of CRISPR.Neal Baer (ed.) - 2024 - Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
    Comprising eight revised essays and seven new pieces, this work provides a comprehensive resource for students, scientists, bioethicists, physicians, and laypeople to better understand and discuss the ethical issues underlying this technology that has the potential to forever change the world.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  94
    Francis Galton: and eugenics today.D. J. Galton & C. J. Galton - 1998 - Journal of Medical Ethics 24 (2):99-105.
    Eugenics can be defined as the use of science applied to the qualitative and quantitative improvement of the human genome. The subject was initiated by Francis Galton with considerable support from Charles Darwin in the latter half of the 19th century. Its scope has increased enormously since the recent revolution in molecular genetics. Genetic files can be easily obtained for individuals either antenatally or at birth; somatic gene therapy has been introduced for some rare inborn errors of (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  9
    Genetics and the Law.Aubrey Milunsky, George J. Annas, National Genetics Foundation & American Society of Law and Medicine - 2012 - Springer.
    Society has historically not taken a benign view of genetic disease. The laws permitting sterilization of the mentally re tarded~ and those proscribing consanguineous marriages are but two examples. Indeed as far back as the 5th-10th centuries, B.C.E., consanguineous unions were outlawed (Leviticus XVIII, 6). Case law has traditionally tended toward the conservative. It is reactive rather than directive, exerting its influence only after an individual or group has sustained injury and brought suit. In contrast, state legislatures have not (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  12
    The oxidative phosphorylation (OXPHOS) system: nuclear genes and human genetic diseases.Lambert van den Heuvel & Jan Smeitink - 2001 - Bioessays 23 (6):518-525.
    The ubiquitous nature of mitochondria, the dual genetic foundation of the respiratory chain in mitochondrial and nuclear genome, and the peculiar rules of mitochondrial genetics all contribute to the extraordinary heterogeneity of clinical disorders associated with defects of oxidative phosphorylation (mitochondrial encephalomyopathies). Here, we review recent findings about nuclear gene defects in isolated OXPHOS enzyme complex deficiency. This information should help in identifying patients with mitochondrial disease and defining a biochemical and molecular basis of the disorder found in each (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  24
    Rare Disease, Advocacy and Justice: Intersecting Disparities in Research and Clinical Care.Meghan C. Halley, Colin M. E. Halverson, Holly K. Tabor & Aaron J. Goldenberg - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics 23 (7):17-26.
    Rare genetic diseases collectively impact millions of individuals in the United States. These patients and their families share many challenges including delayed diagnosis, lack of knowledgeable providers, and limited economic incentives to develop new therapies for small patient groups. As such, rare disease patients and families often must rely on advocacy, including both self-advocacy to access clinical care and public advocacy to advance research. However, these demands raise serious concerns for equity, as both care and research for a given (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6.  13
    Good problems to have? Policy and societal implications of a disease-modifying therapy for presymptomatic late-onset Alzheimer’s disease. [REVIEW]Ornit Chiba-Falek, Boris Kantor, Anna Yang & Misha Angrist - 2020 - Life Sciences, Society and Policy 16 (1):1-11.
    In the United States alone, the prevalence of AD is expected to more than double from six million people in 2019 to nearly 14 million people in 2050. Meanwhile, the track record for developing treatments for AD has been marked by decades of failure. But recent progress in genetics, neuroscience and gene editing suggest that effective treatments could be on the horizon. The arrival of such treatments would have profound implications for the way we diagnose, triage, study, and allocate resources (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Genetic Protection Modifications: Moving Beyond the Binary Distinction Between Therapy and Enhancement for Human Genome Editing.Rasmus Bjerregaard Mikkelsen, Henriette Reventlow S. Frederiksen, Mickey Gjerris, Bjørn Holst, Poul Hyttel, Yonglun Luo, Kristine Freude & Peter Sandøe - 2019 - CRISPR Journal 2 (6):362-369.
    Current debate and policy surrounding the use of genetic editing in humans often relies on a binary distinction between therapy and human enhancement. In this paper, we argue that this dichotomy fails to take into account perhaps the most significant potential uses of CRISPR-Cas9 gene editing in humans. We argue that genetic treatment of sporadic Alzheimer’s disease, breast- and ovarian-cancer causing BRCA1/2 mutations and the introduction of HIV resistance in humans should be considered within a new category (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  36
    Germ-Line Therapy to Cure Mitochondrial Disease: Protocol and Ethics of In Vitro Ovum Nuclear Transplantation.Donald S. Rubenstein, David C. Thomasma, Eric A. Schon & Michael J. Zinaman - 1995 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 4 (3):316.
    The combination of genuine ethical concerns and fear of learning to use germ-line therapy for human disease must now be confronted. Until now, no established techniques were available to perform this treatment on a human. Through an integration of several fields of science and medicine, we have developed a nine step protocol at the germ-line level for the curative treatment of a genetic disease. Our purpose in this paper is to provide the first method to apply germ-line (...) to treat those not yet born, who are destined to have a life threatening, or a severely debilitating genetic disease. We hope this proposal will initiate the process of a thorough analysis from both the scientific and ethical communities. As such, this proposal can be useful for official groups studying the advantages and disadvantages of germ-line therapy. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  9.  26
    Gene replacement therapy in the central nervous system: Viral vector-mediated therapy of global neurodegenerative disease.Edward A. Neuwelt, Michael A. Pagel, Alfred Geller & Leslie L. Muldoon - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):1-9.
    For focal neurodegenerative diseases or brain tumors, localized delivery of protein or genetic vectors may be sufficient to alleviate symptoms, halt disease progression, or even cure the disease. One may circumvent the limitation imposed by the blood-brain barrier by transplantation of genetically altered cell grafts or focal inoculation of virus or protein. However, permanent gene replacement therapy for diseases affecting the entire brain will require global delivery of genetic vectors. The neurotoxicity of currently available viral vectors and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  46
    Chosen Children? : An empirical study and a philosophical analysis of moral aspects of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis and germ-line gene therapy.Kristin Zeiler - unknown
    With pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD), genetic testing and selective transfer of embryos is possible. In the future, germ-line gene therapy (GLGT) applied to embryos before implantation, in order to introduce missing genes or replace mutant ones, may be possible. The objective of this dissertation is to analyse moral aspects of these technologies, as described by eighteen British, Italian and Swedish gynaecologists and geneticists. The objective is systematised into three parts: research interviews and qualitative analysis, philosophical analysis, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  39
    Using the therapy and enhancement distinction in law and policy.Andrew McGee - 2019 - Bioethics 34 (1):70-80.
    In a first major study, the UK’s Royal Society found that 76% of people in the UK are in favour of therapeutic germline genomic editing to correct genetic diseases in human embryos, but found there was little appetite for germline genomic editing for non‐therapeutic purposes. Assuming the UK and other governments acted on these findings, can lawmakers and policymakers coherently regulate the use of biomedical innovations by permitting their use for therapeutic purposes but prohibiting their use for enhancement purposes? (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  13
    Genetic screening: a comparative analysis of three recent reports.R. Hoedemaekers, H. Have & R. Chadwick - 1997 - Journal of Medical Ethics 23 (3):135-141.
  13. Germ-Line Gene Therapy and the Medical Imperative.Ronald Munson & Lawrence H. Davis - 1992 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 2 (2):137-158.
    Somatic cell gene therapy has yielded promising results. If germ cell gene therapy can be developed, the promise is even greater: hundreds of genetic diseases might be virtually eliminated. But some claim the procedure is morally unacceptable. We thoroughly and sympathetically examine several possible reasons for this claim but find them inadequate. There is no moral reason, then, not to develop and employ germ-line gene therapy. Taking the offensive, we argue next that medicine has a prima (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  14. Genetic Testing for Sale: Implications of Commercial Brca Testing in Canada.Bryn Williams-Jones - 2002 - Dissertation, The University of British Columbia (Canada)
    Ongoing research in the fields of genetics and biotechnology hold the promise of improved diagnosis and treatment of genetic diseases, and potentially the development of individually tailored pharmaceuticals and gene therapies. Difficulty, however, arises in determining how these services are to be evaluated and integrated equitably into public health care systems such as Canada's. The current context is one of increasing fiscal restraint on the part of governments, limited financial resources being dedicated to health care, and rising costs for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  25
    The benefits, risks and alternatives of mitochondrial replacement therapy – bringing proportionality into public policy debate.Gregory K. Pike - 2022 - Clinical Ethics 17 (4):368-376.
    Mitochondrial replacement therapy (MRT) utilises nuclear transfer technology to replace defective mitochondria with healthy ones and thereby minimise the risk of a mitochondrial disease passing from a mother to her child. It promises much but comes with ethical controversy, significant risk of harm and many unknowns. Forming a position on MRT requires accurate information about the current state of knowledge, and an appreciation of the ethical issues at stake. Ethical deliberations will vary depending on the framework used. There are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  52
    Huntington's disease and the ethics of genetic prediction.G. Terrenoire - 1992 - Journal of Medical Ethics 18 (2):79-85.
    What ethical justification can be found for informing a person that he or she will later develop a lethal disease for which no therapy is available? This question has been discussed during the past twenty years by specialists concerned with the prevention of Huntington's Disease, an incurable late-onset hereditary disorder. Many of them have played an active role in developing experimental testing programmes for at-risk persons. This paper is based on a corpus of 119 articles; it reviews the development (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17. Genes and Future People: Philosophical Issues in Human Genetics.Walter Glannon - 2001 - Westview Press.
    Advances in genetic technology in general and medical genetics in particular will enable us to intervene in the process of human biological development which extends from zygotes and embryos to people. This will allow us to control to a great extent the identities and the length and quality of the lives of people who already exist, as well as those we bring into existence in the near and distant future. Genes and Future People explores two general philosophical questions, one (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  18.  8
    Human Genetics: The Basics.Ricki Lewis - 2016 - Routledge.
    Human genetics has blossomed from an obscure biological science and explanation for rare disorders to a field that is profoundly altering health care for everyone. This thoroughly updated new edition of _Human Genetics: The Basics_ provides a concise background of gene structure and function through the lens of real examples, from families living with inherited diseases to population-wide efforts in which millions of average people are learning about their genetic selves. The book raises compelling issues concerning: • The role (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  21
    When Does an Illness Begin: Genetic Discrimination and Disease Manifestation.Anya E. R. Prince & Benjamin E. Berkman - 2012 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 40 (3):655-664.
    Congress passed the Genetic Information Nondiscrimination Act of 2008 in order to remove a perceived barrier to clinical genetic testing. By banning health insurance companies and employers from discriminating against an individual based on his or her genetic information, legislators hoped that patients would be encouraged to seek genetic testing that could improve health outcomes and provide opportunities for preventive measures. Their explicit legislative goal was to fully protect the public from discrimination and allay their concerns (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20. Human Gene therapy: Why draw a line?W. French Anderson - 1989 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 14 (6):681-693.
    Despite widespread agreement that it would be ethical to use somatic cell gene therapy to correct serious diseases, there is still uneasiness on the part of the public about this procedure. The basis for this concern lies less with the procedure's clinical risks than with fear that genetic engineering could lead to changes in human nature. Legitimate concerns about the potential for misuse of gene transfer technology justify drawing a moral line that includes corrective germline therapy but (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  21.  45
    Gene therapy and editing in the treatment of hereditary blood disorders: Medical and ethical aspects.Paula Cano Alburquerque, Lucía Gómez-Tatay & Justo Aznar - 2022 - Clinical Ethics 17 (3):315-325.
    Gene therapy and gene editing are revolutionising the treatment of genetic diseases, most notably haematological disorders. This paper evaluates the use of both techniques in hereditary blood disorders. Many studies have been conducted in this field, especially with gene therapy, with very promising results in diseases such as haemophilia, certain haemoglobinopathies and Fanconi anaemia. The application of these techniques in clinical practice and the foreseeable development of these approaches in the coming years suggest that it might be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  24
    Genetics' dreams in the post genomics era.Maurizio Salvi - 2002 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 5 (1):73-77.
    In this paper I explore the heuristic limits ofhuman genetics, in particular the claim that itis possible to manipulate human germcells in a pre-ordinate way (Gordon, 1999). I arguethat this claim is unrealistic based ongenetic reductionism and a wrong concept ofgenetic diseases.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  30
    Human Rights and Genetic Discrimination: Protecting Genomics' Promise for Public Health.Anita Silvers & Michael Ashley Stein - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (3):377-389.
    The potential power of predictive genetic testing as a risk regulator is impressive. By identifying asymptomatic individuals who are at risk of becoming ill, predictive genetic testing may enable those individuals to take prophylactic measures. As new therapies become available, the usefulness of genetic testing undoubtedly will increase. Further, when a person's family medical history indicates a propensity towards a particular genetic disease, a negative test result may open up otherwise denied opportunities by showing that this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  24.  20
    Human Rights and Genetic Discrimination: Protecting Genomics' Promise for Public Health.Anita Silvers & Michael Ashley Stein - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (3):377-389.
    The potential power of predictive genetic testing as a risk regulator is impressive. By identifying asymptomatic individuals who are at risk of becoming ill, predictive genetic testing may enable those individuals to take prophylactic measures. As new therapies become available, the usefulness of genetic testing undoubtedly will increase. Further, when a person's family medical history indicates a propensity towards a particular genetic disease, a negative test result may open up otherwise denied opportunities by showing that this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  25. Gene therapy: Ethical issues.Isaac Rabino - 2003 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24 (1):31-58.
    To discern the ethical issues involved incurrent gene therapy research, to explore theproblems inherent in possible future genetherapies, and to encourage debate within thescientific community about ethical questionsrelevant to both, we surveyed American Societyof Human Genetics scientists who engage inhuman genetics research. This study of theopinions of U.S. scientific experts about theethical issues discussed in the literature ongene therapy contributes systematic data on theattitudes of those working in the field as wellas elaborative comments. Our survey finds thatrespondents are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. 8.1. Gene Therapy of Mitochondrial Diseases.Yasuo Kagawa - forthcoming - Bioethics in Asia: The Proceedings of the Unesco Asian Bioethics Conference (Abc'97) and the Who-Assisted Satellite Symposium on Medical Genetics Services, 3-8 Nov, 1997 in Kobe/Fukui, Japan, 3rd Murs Japan International Symposium, 2nd Congress of the Asi.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  11
    Human Gene Therapy.Mary Carrington Coutts - 1994 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 4 (1):63-83.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Human Gene TherapyMary Carrington Coutts (bio)On September 14, 1990, researchers at the U.S. National Institutes of Health (NIH) performed the first approved gene therapy procedure on a four-year-old girl named Ashanti DeSilva. Born with a rare genetic disease, severe combined immune deficiency (SCID), Ashanti lacked a healthy immune system and was extremely vulnerable to infection. Children with SCID usually develop overwhelming infections and rarely survive to adulthood; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  63
    Response to “Germ Line Therapy to Cure Mitochondrial Disease: Protocol and Ethics of In Vitro Ovum Nuclear Transplantation” by Donald S. Rubenstein, David C. Thomasma, Eric A. Schon, and Michael J. Zinaman. [REVIEW]Helen Watt - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (1):88-96.
    Germ-line therapy has long been regarded with great caution both by scientists and by ethicists. Even those who do not reject germ-line therapy in principle have tended to reject it in practice as carrying unacceptable risks in our current state of knowledge. For this reason, a recent paper by Rubenstein, Thomasma, Shon, and Zinaman is unusual in putting forward a serious proposal for the use of germ-line therapy in the foreseeable future.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  78
    Human gene therapy and the slippery slope argument.Veikko Launis - 2002 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 5 (2):169-179.
    The article investigates the validity of two different versions of the slippery slope argument construed in relation to human gene therapy: the empirical and the conceptual argument. The empirical version holds that our accepting somatic cell therapy will eventually cause our accepting eugenic medical goals. The conceptual version holds that we are logically committed to accepting such goals once we have accepted somatic cell therapy. It is argued that neither the empirical nor the conceptual version of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  7
    Gene Therapy.Ruth Chadwick - 1998 - In Helga Kuhse & Peter Singer (eds.), A Companion to Bioethics. Malden, Mass., USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 205–215.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Promise and Disappointment Ethical Issues Resource Allocation References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  2
    The Moral Image of Therapy.Nicholas Agar - 2004 - In Liberal Eugenics. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 64–87.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Biotechnological Solution to Disease Who Benefits from Gene Therapy? Are we Essentially Human Beings or Essentially Persons, and does it Matter? Genetic Influences, Environmental Influences and the Formation of Human Identities Interactionism's Implications for Identity The Scope of Therapy and the Notion of Disease Buchanan, Brock, Daniels and Wikler on Protecting Normal Functioning Therapy, Obligation and Procreative Liberty's Diminishment.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  93
    Germ-line Genetic Engineering: A Critical Look at Magisterial Catholic Teaching.D. A. Jones - 2012 - Christian Bioethics 18 (2):126-144.
    This article is written from within the Catholic, and more particularly the Augustinian/Thomist tradition of moral theology. It analyses the response of the Catholic Magisterium to the prospect of germline-genetic engineering (GGE). This is a very new issue and the Church has little definitive teaching on it. The statements of Popes and Vatican congregations or commissions have not settled the key questions. An analysis of theological themes drawn from secular writers points beyond pragmatic safety considerations toward intrinsic ethical limits (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  39
    Response to “Germ Line Therapy to Cure Mitochondrial Disease: Protocol and Ethics of In Vitro Ovum Nuclear Transplantation” by Donald S. Rubenstein, David C. Thomasma, Eric A. Schon, and Michael J. Zinaman (CQ Vol 4, No 3). [REVIEW]Imre Szebik - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (3):369-374.
    Technical, ethical, and social questions of germ-line gene interventions have been widely discussed in the literature. The majority of these discussions focus on planned interventions executed on the nuclear DNA (nDNA). However, human cells also contain another set of genes that is the mitochondrial DNA (mtDNA). As the characteristics of the mtDNA grossly differ from those of nDNA, so do the social, ethical, psychological, and safety considerations of possible interventions on this part of the genetic substance.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  24
    Age at onset and causes of disease.Barton Childs & Charles R. Scriver - 1985 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 29 (3 Pt 1):437-460.
  35.  8
    Mitochondrial Replacement Therapy: In Whose Interests?Forough Noohi, Vardit Ravitsky, Bartha Maria Knoppers & Yann Joly - 2022 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 50 (3):597-602.
    Mitochondrial replacement therapy (MRT), also called nuclear genome transfer and mitochondrial donation, is a new technique that can be used to prevent the transmission of mitochondrial DNA diseases. Apart from the United Kingdom, the first country to approve MRT in 2015, Australia became the second country with a clear regulatory path for the clinical applications of this technique in 2021. The rapidly evolving clinical landscape of MRT makes the elaboration and evaluation of the responsible use of this technology a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  15
    PI3K inhibition in inflammation: Toward tailored therapies for specific diseases.Alessandra Ghigo, Federico Damilano, Laura Braccini & Emilio Hirsch - 2010 - Bioessays 32 (3):185-196.
    In the past decade, the availability of genetically modified animals has enabled the discovery of interesting roles for phosphatidylinositol 3‐kinase‐γ (PI3Kγ) and ‐δ (PI3Kδ) in different cell types orchestrating innate and adaptive immune responses. Therefore, these PI3K isoforms appear to be attractive drug targets for the treatment of diseases caused by unrestrained immune reactions. Currently, pharmacological targeting of PI3Kγ and/or PI3Kδ represents one of the most promising challenges for companies interested in the development of novel safe treatments for inflammatory diseases. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  35
    Response to “Germ Line Therapy to Cure Mitochondrial Disease: Protocol and Ethics of In Vitro Ovum Nuclear Transplantation” by Donald S. Rubenstein, David C. Thomasma, Eric A. Schon, and Michael J. Zinaman (CQ Vol 4, No 3) Altering the Mitochondrial Genome: Is it Just a Technical Issue? [REVIEW]Imre Szebik - 1999 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 (3):369-374.
    Technical, ethical, and social questions of germ-line gene interventions have been widely discussed in the literature. The majority of these discussions focus on planned interventions executed on the nuclear DNA (nDNA). However, human cells also contain another set of genes that is the mitochondrial DNA (mtDNA). As the characteristics of the mtDNA grossly differ from those of nDNA, so do the social, ethical, psychological, and safety considerations of possible interventions on this part of the genetic substance.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  22
    A Crispr Revolution: The Brave New World of Cut-and-Paste Genetics.Sahotra Sarkar - 2021 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    The emergence of CRISPR/Cas9 technology has revolutionized gene editing and made both gene therapy and eugenic control of future human evolution plausible. This accessible book puts these developments in their historical and scientific contexts and analyzes the policy and ethical challenges they raise. It presents the case for altering the human germ-line to eliminate a large number of genetic diseases controlled by a single or few genes, while pointing out that gene therapy is likely to ineffective for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  13
    Local and global gene therapy in the central nervous system.Leslie L. Muldoon & Edward A. Neuwelt - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):76-78.
    For focal neurodegenerative diseases or brain tumors, localized delivery of protein or genetic vectors may be sufficient to alleviate symptoms, halt disease progression, or even cure the disease. One may circumvent the limitation imposed by the blood-brain barrier by transplantation of genetically altered cell grafts or focal inoculation of virus or protein. However, permanent gene replacement therapy for diseases affecting the entire brain will require global delivery of genetic vectors. The neurotoxicity of currently available viral vectors and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  27
    Genetic Tools, Kuhnean Theoretical Shift and the Geneticization Process.Juan Manuel Torres - 2005 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 9 (1):3-12.
    The growing use of genetic tests in medical practice has a strong influence on some widespread notions of health and unhealth. Two consequences of this phenomenon are: (i) important changes in the meaning of these current notions and, therefore, (ii) the arrival of a new taxonomy or rearrangement for the so-called “health-concepts”. This paper attempts to demonstrate that both facts fuel a theoretical change that might be considered a model of scientific Kuhnean change in a fundamental aspect. On the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  40
    The Bioethics of Gene Therapy.Robert Scott Smith, Bryan A. Piras & Carr J. Smith - 2010 - The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 10 (1):45-50.
    Gene therapy is the modification of the human genetic code to prevent disease or cure illness. This technology is in its infancy and remains confined to experimental clinical trials. Once the present barriers are overcome, gene therapy will confront humanity with a host of ethical challenges. Therapies targeted to the genes of germ-line cells will introduce permanent changes to the human gene pool. Furthermore, nonmedical gene modifications have the potential to introduce a new form of eugenics into (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  49
    The Mitochondrial Replacement ‘Therapy’ Myth.Tina Rulli - 2016 - Bioethics 31 (4):368-374.
    This article argues that two forms of mitochondrial replacement therapy, maternal spindle transfer and pro-nuclear transfer, are not therapies at all because they do not treat children who are coming into existence. Rather, these technologies merely create healthy children where none was inevitable. Even if creating healthy lives has some value, it is not to be confused with the medical value of a cure or therapy. The article addresses a recent Bioethics article, ‘Mitochondrial Replacement: Ethics and Identity,’ by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  43.  82
    Is Mitochondrial Donation Germ‐Line Gene Therapy? Classifications and Ethical Implications.Anthony Wrigley & Ainsley J. Newson - 2016 - Bioethics 31 (1):55-67.
    The classification of techniques used in mitochondrial donation, including their role as purported germ-line gene therapies, is far from clear. These techniques exhibit characteristics typical of a variety of classifications that have been used in both scientific and bioethics scholarship. This raises two connected questions, which we address in this paper: how should we classify mitochondrial donation techniques?; and what ethical implications surround such a classification? First, we outline how methods of genetic intervention, such as germ-line gene therapy, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44. Can reproductive genetic manipulation save lives?G. Owen Schaefer - 2020 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy (3):381-386.
    It has recently been argued that reproductive genetic manipulation technologies like mitochondrial replacement and germline CRISPR modifications cannot be said to save anyone’s life because, counterfactually, no one would suffer more or die sooner absent the intervention. The present article argues that, on the contrary, reproductive genetic manipulations may be life-saving (and, from this, have therapeutic value) under an appropriate population health perspective. As such, popular reports of reproductive genetic manipulations potentially saving lives or preventing disease are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  13
    Polymorphism-screening: genetic testing for predisposition—guidance for technology assessment. [REVIEW]Claudia Wild - 2008 - Poiesis and Praxis 5 (1):1-14.
    Health policy is increasingly confronted with the demand for financing genetic testing on inherited susceptibility to disease. Tests on polymorphism/snp associated with multicausal and chronic conditions are already offered in private commercial institutions or in academic hospitals. The increasing pressure on public health services to offer SNP testing leads to first methodological approaches for a generally valid regulatory framework applicable for inclusion or refusal of genetic tests into the public health services. Systematic search in Medline, Embase and the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  45
    Nurturing the genius of genes: The new frontier of education, therapy, and understanding of the brain. [REVIEW]Dennis D. Embry - 2002 - Brain and Mind 3 (1):101-132.
    Genes dance. They dance with culture. Theydance with environment. Genes act on the world through the brain, mind and behavior. Historically, psychologists, therapists,educators and most lay people have understoodgenes in the context of Gregor Mendel'sexperiments, which were only partiallyexplained to us. While many studies show thatbrain structures and behaviors have quiterobust influences from inheritance, mostbehavior is not influenced in the classic waywe were taught in our introduction to genetics– which has been revolutionized by molecularstudies and understandings that most of theimportant (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  12
    Gene therapy and retinitis pigmentosa: advances and future challenges.Nadine S. Dejneka & Jean Bennett - 2001 - Bioessays 23 (7):662-668.
    It may be possible, one day, to use gene therapy to treat diseases whose genetic defects have been discerned. Because many genes responsible for inherited eye disorders within the retina have been identified, diseases of the eye are prime candidates for this form of therapy. The eye also has the advantage of being highly accessible with altered immunological properties, important considerations for easy delivery of virus and avoidance of systemic immune responses. Currently, adenovirus, adeno‐associated virus and lentivirus (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  15
    Made in Whose Image?: Genetic Engineering and Christian Ethics.Thomas Anthony Shannon - 1997 - Humanities Press.
    The ability of medical science to clone and perhaps even predetermine characteristics of certain species conflicts dramatically with many claims of the religious establishment. Opening with a description of various developments in plant, animal, and human genetics, Made in Whose Image? highlights the progress genetic research has achieved, its future promise, and its social impact. The developments are analyzed from the perspective of Christian ethics, as expounded by Roman Catholic and Protestant theorists, to give an overview of crucial ethical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  54
    Harm, ethics committees and the gene therapy death.Julian Savulescu - 2001 - Journal of Medical Ethics 27 (3):148-150.
    The recent tragic and widely publicised death of Jesse Gelsinger in a gene therapy trial has many important lessons for those engaged in the ethical review of research. One of the most important lessons is that ethics committees can give too much weight to ensuring informed consent and not enough attention to minimising the harm associated with participation in research. The first responsibility of ethics committees should be to ensure that the expected harm associated with participation is reasonable. Jesse (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  50.  39
    Bringing prosocial values to translational, disease-specific stem cell research.Reuben G. Sass - 2014 - BMC Medical Ethics 15 (1):16.
    Disease-specific stem cell therapies, created from induced pluripotent stem cell lines containing the genetic defects responsible for a particular disease, have the potential to revolutionize the treatment of refractory chronic diseases. Given their capacity to differentiate into any human cell type, these cell lines might be reprogrammed to correct a disease-causing genetic defect in any tissue or organ, in addition to offering a more clinically realistic model for testing new drugs and studying disease mechanisms. Clinical translation of these (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000