Results for 'Cartesian scholasticism'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  8
    Body and Soul in Philoponus, HJ BLUMENTHAL Philoponus like other Platonists had to reconcile his dualism with the need to give an account of human activity. The article explores how he formulated and attempted to resolve some of the consequential problems. It is based on the assumption that Philoponus' Neoplatonism was crucial. [REVIEW]Cartesian Selves & E. D. McCANN - 1986 - New Scholasticism 60 (3).
  2.  22
    French Cartesian Scholasticism: Remarks on Descartes and the First Cartesians.Tad M. Schmaltz - 2018 - Perspectives on Science 26 (5):579-598.
    In a 1669 letter to his mentor Thomasius, Leibniz writes that "hardly any of the Cartesians have added anything to the discoveries of their master" insofar as they "have published only paraphrases of their leader."1 The book that is the focus of my remarks here—Roger Ariew's Descartes and the First Cartesians —shows that Leibniz was most certainly incorrect. In particular, Ariew draws attention to the fact that there was a concerted effort to present a new sort of Cartesianism that conforms (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  83
    Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy.Jorge Secada - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This is the first book-length study of Descartes's metaphysics to place it in its immediate historical context, the Late Scholastic philosophy of thinkers such as Suárez against which Descartes reacted. Jorge Secada views Cartesian philosophy as an 'essentialist' reply to the 'existentialism' of the School, and his discussion includes careful analyses and original interpretations of such central Cartesian themes as the role of scepticism, intentionality and the doctrine of the material falsity of ideas, universals and the relation between (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  4.  24
    Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy (review).Patrick R. Frierson - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2):292-294.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.2 (2001) 292-294 [Access article in PDF] Secada, Jorge. Cartesian Metaphysics: The Scholastic Origins of Modern Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2000. Pp. xii + 333. Cloth, $59.95. Descartes scholars can welcome this book. Secada supports trends in scholarship that criticize seeing Descartes as merely an anti-skeptical foundationalist, and he challenges many prominent interpretations of Descartes's metaphysics. In addition, Secada helpfully (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Thomistic “Monism” vs. Cartesian “Dualism”.Gyula Klima - 2007 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 10:92-112.
    This paper contrasts the Thomistic and Cartesian interpretations of what the substantial unity of the body and mind can consist in. A detailed discussion of the Thomistic account of the substantial unity of body and soul identifies especially those principles of the presupposed hylomorphist metaphysical background of this account that Descartes abandoned. After arguing for the consistency of the Thomistic view, briefly outlines how certain developments in late-medieval scholasticism prepared the way for the abandonment of precisely these principles. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  27
    The Cartesian Circle.Elizabeth G. Salmon - 1938 - New Scholasticism 12 (4):378-391.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  22
    A Contextualist History of Cartesian Philosophy: Roger Ariew’s Descartes and the First Cartesians.Domenico Collacciani - 2018 - Perspectives on Science 26 (5):521-532.
    The title Descartes and the First Cartesians only partly reflects the scope of the research presented in Roger Ariew's latest book. To be sure, this study does offer a new and extensive account of the work of the first Cartesians and thus a new perspective on the historical phenomenon that was seventeenth century Cartesianism. Yet it does so on the basis of a vast survey of the Scholastic context from which the new philosophy emerged. The investigation of Cartesianism is thus (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Domesticating Descartes, Renovating Scholasticism: Johann Clauberg And The German Reception Of Cartesianism.Nabeel Hamid - 2020 - History of Universities 30 (2):57-84.
    This article studies the academic context in which Cartesianism was absorbed in Germany in the mid-seventeenth century. It focuses on the role of Johann Clauberg (1622-1665), first rector of the new University of Duisburg, in adjusting scholastic tradition to accommodate Descartes’ philosophy, thereby making the latter suitable for teaching in universities. It highlights contextual motivations behind Clauberg’s synthesis of Cartesianism with the existing framework such as a pedagogical interest in Descartes as offering a simpler method, and a systematic concern to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  81
    Is the Cartesian Ontological Argument Defensible?J. William Forgie - 1976 - New Scholasticism 50 (1):108-121.
  10.  9
    The Progressive Norm of Cartesian Morality.Connor J. Chambers - 1968 - New Scholasticism 42 (3):374-400.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  18
    Descartes and the First Cartesians by Roger Ariew. [REVIEW]John Grey - 2016 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (1):167-168.
    The title of Roger Ariew’s new book parallels that of his earlier collection of essays, Descartes and the Last Scholastics, published in 1999 and widely regarded as a signal contribution to the study of Descartes’s relationship to his intellectual predecessors. Some of the themes of that work are reflected in the new book as well. In both, Ariew seeks to overthrow the myth of Descartes as staunch opponent of Scholasticism by revealing his affinities to strands of Scholastic thought. Indeed, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  21
    Aristotelian and Cartesian Motion.James A. McWiIliams - 1943 - New Scholasticism 17 (4):307-321.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  30
    Anthony Legrand : Franciscan and Cartesian.John K. Ryan - 1935 - New Scholasticism 9 (3):226-250.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  18
    Mathematical Roots of Cartesian Metaphysics.Elizabeth G. Salmon - 1965 - New Scholasticism 39 (2):158-169.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  11
    Psychology and philosophy : inquiries into the soul from late scholasticism to contemporary thought.Sara Heinämaa & Martina Reuter (eds.) - 2009 - Springer.
    Psychology and Philosophy provides a history of the relations between philosophy and the science of psychology from late scholasticism to contemporary discussions. The book covers the development from 16th-century interpretations of Aristotle’s De Anima, through Kantianism and the 19th-century revival of Aristotelianism, up to 20th-century phenomenological and analytic studies of consciousness and the mind. In this volume historically divergent conceptions of psychology as a science receive special emphasis. The volume illuminates the particular nature of studies of the psyche in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  7
    John Austin SJ (1717–84), The First Irish Catholic Cartesian?Jacob Schmutz - 2020 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 88:239-271.
    Early-Modern Irish Catholics exiled on the European continent are known to have often held prominent academic positions in various important colleges and universities. This paper investigates the hitherto unknown Scholastic legacy of the Dublin-born Jesuit John Austin (1717–84), a famous Irish educator who started his career teaching philosophy at the Jesuit college of Rheims in 1746–47, before returning to the country of his birth as part of the Irish Mission. These manuscript lecture notes provides us first-hand knowledge about the content (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  44
    An Inconsistency in Husserl’s Cartesian Meditations.James L. Marsh - 1979 - New Scholasticism 53 (4):460-474.
  18. Anthony Kenny.Marxism Scholasticism - 1994 - In Anthony Kenny (ed.), The Oxford history of Western philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 363.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  11
    Anindita Niyogi Balslev.Cartesian Meditations - 1992 - In D. P. Chattopadhyaya, Lester Embree & Jitendranath Mohanty (eds.), Phenomenology and Indian philosophy. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research in association with Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. pp. 133.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Analysis of I-Consciousness in the Transcendental Phenomenology and Indian Philosophy.Cartesian Meditations - 1992 - In D. P. Chattopadhyaya, Lester Embree & Jitendranath Mohanty (eds.), Phenomenology and Indian philosophy. New Delhi: Indian Council of Philosophical Research in association with Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. pp. 133.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Tr vldyasagar.Geniculate Orientation Biases as Cartesian - 1985 - In David Rose & Vernon Dobson (eds.), Models of the Visual Cortex. New York: Wiley.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Efficient Cause as Paradigm? From Suárez to Clauberg.Nabeel Hamid - 2021 - Journal of Modern Philosophy 3 (7):1-22.
    This paper critiques a narrative concerning causality in later scholasticism due to, among others, Des Chene, Carraud, Schmaltz, Schmid, and Pasnau. On this account, internal developments in the scholastic tradition culminating in Suárez lead to the efficient cause being regarded as the paradigmatic kind of cause, anticipating a view explicitly held by the Cartesians. Focusing on Suárez and his scholastic reception, I defend the following claims: a) Suárez’s definition of cause does not privilege efficient causation; b) Suárez’s readers, from (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  4
    Locke and Descartes.Lisa Downing - 2015 - In Matthew Stuart (ed.), A Companion to Locke. Hoboken, NJ, USA: Wiley. pp. 100–120.
    In this chapter, John Locke's anti‐Cartesian stances on the difference between body and space, on whether the soul always thinks, on the possibility of thinking matter, all connect back to the basic opposition to Cartesian overreaching in regard to essences. The chapter presents a summary of Locke's anti‐Cartesianism, which seems to fit with his own representation of his Cartesian inheritance, which, notoriously, is that it is minimal, consisting only in anti‐scholasticism. The only acknowledgment that Locke wishes (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Substance, Causation, and the Mind-Body Problem in Johann Clauberg.Nabeel Hamid - 2022 - Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy 11:31-66.
    This essay proposes a new interpretation of Clauberg’s account of the mind-body problem, against both occasionalist and interactionist readings. It examines his treatment of the mind-body relation through the lens of his theories of substance and cause. It argues that, whereas Clauberg embraces Descartes’s substance dualism, he retains a broadly scholastic theory of causation as the action of essential powers. On this account, mind and body are distinct, power-bearing substances, and each is a genuine secondary cause of its own modifications. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Elisabeth of Bohemia as a Naturalistic Dualist.Frederique Janssen-Lauret - 2018 - In Emily Thomas (ed.), Early Modern Women on Metaphysics. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. pp. 171-187.
    Elisabeth was the first of Descartes' interlocutors to press concerns about mind-body union and interaction, and the only one to receive a detailed reply, unsatisfactory though she found it. Descartes took her tentative proposal `to concede matter and extension to the soul' for a confused version of his own view: `that is nothing but to conceive it united to the body. Contemporary commentators take Elisabeth for a materialist or at least a critic of dualism. I read her instead as a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Of Dreams, Demons, and Whirlpools: Doubt, Skepticism, and Suspension of Judgment in Descartes's Meditations.Jan Forsman - 2021 - Dissertation, Tampere University
    I offer a novel reading in this dissertation of René Descartes’s (1596–1650) skepticism in his work Meditations on First Philosophy (1641–1642). I specifically aim to answer the following problem: How is Descartes’s skepticism to be read in accordance with the rest of his philosophy? This problem can be divided into two more general questions in Descartes scholarship: How is skepticism utilized in the Meditations, and what are its intentions and relation to the preceding philosophical tradition? -/- I approach the topic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. La Logique de Port Royal : Une logique des idées et une sémantique des termes.Nuno Fonseca - 2021 - In Christophe Roche (ed.), Terminologie & Ontologie : Théories et Applications - Actes de la conférence TOTh 2020. Presses Universitaires Savoie Mont Blanc. pp. 15-37.
    La Logique ou L'Art de Penser (LAP), also known as the Port-Royal Logic, is generally presented as a "logic of ideas" in which the idea, the central epistemological entity, is the starting point of this logic based on Cartesian ontology. Structured around the four main operations of the mind - conceiving, judging, reasoning and ordering - the first part of the LAP contains "reflections on ideas". The idea, "the form by which we represent things [objects]", thus takes the place (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  62
    Dealing with Diversity: On the Uses of Common Sense in Descartes and Montaigne.Darryl M. De Marzio - 2010 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 29 (3):301-313.
    This essay attempts to retrieve the notion of ‘common sense’ within the writings of Descartes and Montaigne. I suggest that both writers represent distinct traditions in which the notion is employed. Descartes represents a modernist tradition in which common sense is understood to be a cognitive faculty, while Montaigne represents a humanist tradition in which common sense is understood as a political virtue. I also suggest that both writers work with the notion as a way of responding to diversity in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  4
    Spinoza's Dutch Philosophical Background.Henri Krop - 2021 - In Yitzhak Y. Melamed (ed.), A Companion to Spinoza. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley. pp. 68–80.
    This chapter outlines the intellectual world of the Netherlands during Spinoza's lifetimes. It starts with Scholasticism, which dominated Leiden, the country's leading university, during the first half of the seventeenth century. The teaching of philosophy in the early years of Leiden University, established in 1575, was inspired by humanist ideals of education. It had an introductory and philological nature, and lacked metaphysical training. The chapter deals with Cartesianism, which inspired Spinoza, especially in its non‐academic forms. Cartesianism is both part (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  38
    Descartes among the Scholastics.Roger Ariew - 2011 - Boston: Brill. Edited by Roger Ariew.
    Descartes and the last Scholastics: objections and replies -- Descartes and the Scotists -- Ideas, before and after Descartes -- The Cartesian destiny of form and matter -- Descartes, Basso, and Toletus: three kinds of Corpuscularians -- Scholastics and the new astronomy on the substance of the heavens -- Descartes and the Jesuits of La Fleche: the Eucharist -- Condemnations of Cartesianism: the extension and unity of the universe -- Cartesians, Gassendists, and censorship -- The cogito in the seventeenth (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  31.  64
    Descartes and the last Scholastics.Roger Ariew - 1999 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
    The volume touches upon many topics and themes shared by Cartesian and late scholastic philosophy: matter and form; infinity, place, time, void, and motion; the ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  32. The Medieval Origins of Conceivability Arguments.Stephen Boulter - 2011 - Metaphilosophy 42 (5):617-641.
    The central recommendation of this article is that philosophers trained in the analytic tradition ought to add the sensibilities and skills of the historian to their methodological toolkit. The value of an historical approach to strictly philosophical matters is illustrated by a case study focussing on the medieval origin of conceivability arguments and contemporary views of modality. It is shown that common metaphilosophical views about the nature of the philosophical enterprise as well as certain inference patterns found in thinkers from (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  41
    Heidegger, Metaphysics and the Univocity of Being.Philip Tonner - 2010 - Continuum.
    Introduction -- The univocity of being -- The modern predicament -- The problem of univocity in ancient and medieval philosophy -- From Heidegger to Aristotle -- Medieval philosophy -- Scholasticism -- Heidegger, Scotus, and univocity -- The question of being -- Analogy, the medieval experience of life -- Univocity and phenomenology -- Destruction and tradition -- Metaphysics -- Phenomenological philosophy and aletheia -- Descartes, scholasticism, and time -- The presupposition of the tradition -- Scholasticism, analogy, and the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  25
    A interação entre a forma E a matéria em Tomás de aquino E as interações do sistema cartesiano.Márcio Augusto Damin Custódio - 2015 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 56 (131):173-189.
    Este artigo explora a relação que Descartes estabelece com as noções de forma e de matéria do aristotelismo escolástico ao tratar da interação entre as substâncias nas correspondências com Elisabeth, Gassendi e Arnauld. Partindo do exemplo do peso utilizado por Descartes em diversas cartas, traça-se uma relação de identidade entre a noção de forma em Tomás de Aquino e de pensamento em Descartes, assim como se traça a crítica à noção de forma, entendida como qualidade oculta, para os corpos inanimados. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  23
    A “Calvinist” theory of matter? Burgersdijk and Descartes on res extensa.Giovanni Gellera - 2018 - Intellectual History Review 28 (2):255-270.
    In the Dutch debates on Cartesianism of the 1640s, a minority believed that some Cartesian views were in fact Calvinist ones. The paper argues that, among others, a likely precursor of this position is the Aristotelian Franco Burgersdijk (1590-1635), who held a reductionist view of accidents and of the essential extension of matter on Calvinist grounds. It seems unlikely that Descartes was unaware of these views. The claim is that Descartes had two aims in his Replies to Arnauld: to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  33
    La distinction entre concept formel et concept objectif : Suárez, Pasqualigo, Mastri.Marco Forlivesi - 2002 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 1 (1):3.
    Cette étude montre comment s’élabore une doctrine de l’objet, et de l’objectité, de la scolastique du XIIIe siècle jusqu’au XVIIe, par une succession de créations conceptuelles et de ruptures interprétatives. Elle débouche sur l’opposition entre concept formel et concept objectif au XVIIe siècle. De cette histoire retrouvée découle une nouvelle évaluation de l’argument cartésien sur l’existence de Dieu.This study shows how a theory of object, and of « objectity » is elaborated, from XIIIth century’s scholasticism to the XVIIth century, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  37.  11
    Radical Cartesianism: The French Reception of Descartes (review).Richard A. Watson - 2003 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 41 (3):415-416.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 41.3 (2003) 415-416 [Access article in PDF] Tad M. Schmaltz. Radical Cartesianism: The French Reception of Descartes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002. Pp. xiv + 288. Cloth, $65.00.More than fifty years ago Richard H. Popkin urged historians of philosophy to work on secondary figures in philosophy, in part for their own sake, but also because the true shape of philosophy and the development (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  29
    The Causation Debate in Modern Philosophy: 1637-1739 (review).Jan A. Cover - 2000 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (4):600-601.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Causation Debate in Modern Philosophy: 1637–1739J. A. CoverKenneth Clatterbaugh. The Causation Debate in Modern Philosophy: 1637–1739. New York and London: Routledge, 1999. Pp. xi + 239. Cloth, $75.00. Paper, $21.00.Over the scholastics and earliest moderns, Hume had an advantage of hindsight in declaring that "There is no question, which on account of its importance, as well as difficulty, has caus'd more disputes both among ancients and modern (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  3
    The Downfall of Cartesianism, 1673-1712: A Study of Epistemological Issues in Late 17th Century Cartesianism.Richard Allan Watson - 1966 - Springer.
    Phenomenalism, idealism, spiritualism, and other contemporary philo sophical movements originating in the reflective experience of the cogito witness to the immense influence of Descartes. However, Carte sianism as a complete metaphysical system in the image of that of the master collapsed early in the 18th century. A small school of brilliant Cartesians, almost all expert in the new mechanistic science, flashed like meteors upon the intellectual world of late 17th century France to win well-deserved recognition for Cartesianism. They were accompanied (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  6
    Dealing with Diversity: On the Uses of Common Sense in Descartes and Montaigne.Darryl Marzio - 2010 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 29 (3):301-313.
    This essay attempts to retrieve the notion of ‘common sense’ within the writings of Descartes and Montaigne. I suggest that both writers represent distinct traditions in which the notion is employed. Descartes represents a modernist tradition in which common sense is understood to be a cognitive faculty, while Montaigne represents a humanist tradition in which common sense is understood as a political virtue. I also suggest that both writers work with the notion as a way of responding to diversity in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. Flesh Vs. Mind: A Study of the Debate Between Descartes and Gassendi.Antonia Lolordo - 2001 - Dissertation, Rutgers the State University of New Jersey - New Brunswick
    The 17th century's new science and new philosophy was roughly equally divided between Cartesians and Gassendists. Scholars agree that understanding Gassendi's metaphysics, epistemology and scientific method is crucial for understanding the development of modern philosophy, as Gassendis version of Epicureanism provides a third strand of influence on modern philosophy paralleling Cartesianism and scholasticism. Despite this, Gassendi is rather little understood today. I look at Gassendi in the context of his Objections and Counter-Objections to the Meditations, along with Descartes' Replies. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  16
    4. Dutch Cartesianism in the 1650s and 1660s: Philosophy, theology, and ethics.Andrea Strazzoni - 2018 - In Dutch Cartesianism and the Birth of Philosophy of Science: From Regius to ‘s Gravesande. Berlin-Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 69-104.
    The fourth chapter analyses the establishment of Cartesianism at the University of Leiden in 1650s and 1660s. This was carried out by De Raey, who provided a defence and teaching of Descartes’s physics in his Clavis philosophiae naturalis (1654), although not based on Descartes’s metaphysics: physical principles, indeed, are presented by De Raey as self-evident truths, and consistent with Aristotle’s theory of scientia or universal and necessary knowledge. This was not the only peculiar characteristic of Leiden Cartesianism, as De Raey (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  88
    Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle.Frank J. Leavitt - 1991 - Hume Studies 17 (2):203-208.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Against Spinoza and Aristotle1 Frank J. Leavitt It is always good to try to make peace, to try to resolve differences between whatsomebelieveare conflictingpoints ofview. Nevertheless, sometimes the points ofview which are believed to be opposed to each other really do oppose one another and so the most ingenious attempts at reconciliation turn out to have been ill-conceived. Wim Klever has brought considerable scholarship to bear in his (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  5
    Studies in medieval philosophy.Etienne Gilson - 2019 - Eugene, Oregon: Cascade Books. Edited by James G. Colbert.
    The meaning of Christian rationalism -- The handmaiden of theology -- The doctrine of double truth -- Appendix : Texts of John the Jandun on the relations between reason and faith -- The historical significance of Thomism -- Reasoning by analogy in Campanella -- Theology and Cartesian innatism -- Descartes, Harvey, and scholasticism -- Appendix: William Harvey's critique of the Cartesian theory of the movement of the heart -- Cartesian and scholastic meteors.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  33
    English Philosophers and Scottish Academic Philosophy.Gellera Giovanni - 2017 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 15 (2):213-231.
    This paper investigates the little-known reception of Thomas Hobbes, Henry More, Francis Bacon, Robert Boyle, Isaac Newton, and John Locke in the Scottish universities in the period 1660–1700. The fortune of the English philosophers in the Scottish universities rested on whether their philosophies were consonant with the Scots’ own philosophical agenda. Within the established Cartesian curriculum, the Scottish regents eagerly taught what they thought best in English philosophy and criticised what they thought wrong. The paper also suggests new sources (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Wolff on Substance, Power, and Force.Nabeel Hamid - forthcoming - Journal of the History of Philosophy.
    This paper argues that Wolff’s rejection of Leibnizian monads is rooted in a disagreement concerning the general notion of substance. Briefly, whereas Leibniz defines substance in terms of activity, Wolff retains a broadly scholastic and Cartesian conception of substance as that which per se subsists and sustains accidents. One consequence of this difference is that it leads Wolff to interpret Leibniz’s concept of a constantly striving force as denoting a feature of substance separate from its static powers, and not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. La filosofia aristotelico-cartesiana di Johannes de Raey.Andrea Strazzoni - 2011 - Giornale Critico Della Filosofia Italiana 7 (1):107-132.
    The search for an agreement between Aristotle’s and Descartes’ philosophy was aimed at making Cartesian physics acceptable in the Dutch universities by showing its consistency with Aristotelian thought. Their agreement is defended by Johannes De Raey in the Clavis philosophiae naturalis (1654), where he interprets the Corpus Aristotelicum from a Cartesian standpoint. Those Aristotelian positions which are inconsistent with Descartes’ are treated as erroneous. The Scholastic positions, moreover, are considered as distant from the true Aristotelian philosophy rediscovered by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  13
    The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy (review).Donald Rutherford - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (1):165-168.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy by Daniel Garber, Michael AyersDonald RutherfordDaniel Garber, Michael Ayers, editors. The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xii + 1616. Cloth, $175.Over a decade in preparation, this latest addition to the Cambridge History of Philosophy is an enormous achievement—both in its size and the contribution it makes to redefining [End Page 165] the landscape of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  15
    Virtual reflection: Antoine Arnauld on Descartes' concept of conscientia.Daniel Schmal - 2020 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 28 (4):714-734.
    Although Descartes has often been portrayed as the father of the modern concept of mind, his approach to consciousness is notoriously problematic. What makes it particularly hard to assess his role in the development of the theories of consciousness is the difficulty of clarifying the kind of consciousness he might have in mind when using the associated Latin terms (conscius, cogitatio, conscium esse, etc.). In this article, I analyse Antoine Arnauld’s early interpretation of the passages in Descartes that refer to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  16
    Seventeenth Century Rationalism. [REVIEW]G. L. - 1971 - Review of Metaphysics 25 (1):145-145.
    This volume is fifth in a series, Monuments of Western Thought. Most of the book consists of excerpts from the works of Bacon and Descartes The selections from Bacon are the preface and plan of The Great Instauration, parts of the New Organon, a bit of Advancement of Learning, and all of The New Atlantis. The selections from Descartes are a short passage from the Discourse on Method and all of the Meditations. The text is introduced by a historical sketch (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000