Results for ' geometrical knowledge'

978 found
Order:
  1. Kant theory on geometrical knowledge and non-euclidean geometry.Matthias Schirn - 1991 - Kant Studien 82 (1):1-28.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  22
    On Euclidean diagrams and geometrical knowledge.Tamires Dal Magro & Manuel J. García-Pérez - 2019 - Theoria. An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science 34 (2):255.
    We argue against the claim that the employment of diagrams in Euclidean geometry gives rise to gaps in the proofs. First, we argue that it is a mistake to evaluate its merits through the lenses of Hilbert’s formal reconstruction. Second, we elucidate the abilities employed in diagram-based inferences in the Elements and show that diagrams are mathematically reputable tools. Finally, we complement our analysis with a review of recent experimental results purporting to show that, not only is the Euclidean diagram-based (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. Navigation as a source of geometric knowledge: Young children’s use of length, angle, distance, and direction in a reorientation task.Sang Ah Lee, Valeria A. Sovrano & Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2012 - Cognition 123 (1):144-161.
  4.  74
    Applications of Conceptual Spaces : the Case for Geometric Knowledge Representation.Peter Gärdenfors & Frank Zenker (eds.) - 2015 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    Why is a red face not really red? How do we decide that this book is a textbook or not? Conceptual spaces provide the medium on which these computations are performed, but an additional operation is needed: Contrast. By contrasting a reddish face with a prototypical face, one gets a prototypical ‘red’. By contrasting this book with a prototypical textbook, the lack of exercises may pop out. Dynamic contrasting is an essential operation for converting perceptions into predicates. The existence of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  5.  33
    Kant’s Epistemology and Neuroscience: The Biological Basis of the Synthethic and “A Priori” Character of Geometric Knowledge.Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden - 2008 - In Margit Ruffing, Guido A. De Almeida, Ricardo R. Terra & Valerio Rohden (eds.), Law and Peace in Kant's Philosophy/Recht und Frieden in der Philosophie Kants: Proceedings of the 10th International Kant Congress/Akten des X. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Walter de Gruyter.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  32
    The geometrical basis of arithmetical knowledge: Frege & Dehaene.Sorin Costreie - 2018 - Theoria : An International Journal for Theory, History and Fundations of Science 33 (2):361-370.
    Frege writes in Numbers and Arithmetic about kindergarten-numbers and “an a priori mode of cognition” that they may have “a geometrical source.” This resembles recent findings on arithmetical cognition. In my paper, I explore this resemblance between Gottlob Frege’s later position concerning the geometrical source of arithmetical knowledge, and some current positions in the literature dedicated to arithmetical cognition, especially that of Stanislas Dehaene. In my analysis, I shall try to mainly see to what extent logicism is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  6
    The geometrical basis of arithmetical knowledge: Frege and Dehaene.Sorin Costreie - 2018 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 33 (2):361-370.
    Frege writes in Numbers and Arithmetic about kindergarten-numbers and “an a priori mode of cognition” that they may have “a geometrical source.” This resembles recent findings on arithmetical cognition. In my paper, I explore this resemblance between Gottlob Frege’s later position concerning the geometrical source of arithmetical knowledge, and some current positions in the literature dedicated to arithmetical cognition, especially that of Stanislas Dehaene. In my analysis, I shall try to mainly see to what extent (Frege’s) logicism (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  11
    Logical and Geometrical Distance in Polyhedral Aristotelian Diagrams in Knowledge Representation.Lorenz6 Demey & Hans5 Smessaert - 2017 - Symmetry 9 (10).
    © 2017 by the authors. Aristotelian diagrams visualize the logical relations among a finite set of objects. These diagrams originated in philosophy, but recently, they have also been used extensively in artificial intelligence, in order to study various knowledge representation formalisms. In this paper, we develop the idea that Aristotelian diagrams can be fruitfully studied as geometrical entities. In particular, we focus on four polyhedral Aristotelian diagrams for the Boolean algebra B4, viz. the rhombic dodecahedron, the tetrakis hexahedron, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  19
    Thinking Geometrically in Pierre-Daniel Huet's "Demonstratio evangelica".April Shelford - 2002 - Journal of the History of Ideas 63 (4):599.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 63.4 (2002) 599-617 [Access article in PDF] Thinking Geometrically in Pierre-Daniel Huet's Demonstratio evangelica (1679) April G. Shelford Sometime after 1679, Pierre-Daniel Huet (1630-1721) indulged an author's vanity by comparing his Demonstratio evangelica with works whose authors are far better known today. He recorded his judgments on a scrap of paper. 1First, he contrasted the Demonstratio to Antoine Arnauld's Les nouveaux élémens de (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  13
    Knowing by Doing: the Role of Geometrical Practice in Aristotle’s Theory of Knowledge.Monica Ugaglia - 2015 - Elenchos 36 (1):45-88.
    Aristotle’s way of conceiving the relationship between mathematics and other branches of scientific knowledge is completely different from the way a contemporary scientist conceives it. This is one of the causes of the fact that we look at the mathematical passage we find in Aristotle’s works with the wrong expectation. We expect to find more or less stringent proofs, while for the most part Aristotle employs mere analogies. Indeed, this is the primary function of mathematics when employed in a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  27
    Can We Identify the Theorem in Metaphysics 9, 1051a24-27 with Euclid’s Proposition 32? Geometric Deductions for the Discovery of Mathematical Knowledge.Francisco Miguel Ortiz Delgado - 2023 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 33 (66):41-65.
    This paper has two specific goals. The first is to demonstrate that the theorem in MetaphysicsΘ 9, 1051a24-27 is not equiva-lent to Euclid’s Proposition 32 of book I (which contradicts some Aristotelian commentators, such as W. D. Ross, J. L. Heiberg, and T. L. Heith). Agreeing with Henry Mendell’s analysis, I ar-gue that the two theorems are not equivalent, but I offer different reasons for such divergence: I propose a pedagogical-philosoph-ical reason for the Aristotelian theorem being shorter than the Euclidean (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. On the development of geometric cognition: Beyond nature vs. nurture.Markus Pantsar - 2022 - Philosophical Psychology 35 (4):595-616.
    How is knowledge of geometry developed and acquired? This central question in the philosophy of mathematics has received very different answers. Spelke and colleagues argue for a “core cognitivist”, nativist, view according to which geometric cognition is in an important way shaped by genetically determined abilities for shape recognition and orientation. Against the nativist position, Ferreirós and García-Pérez have argued for a “culturalist” account that takes geometric cognition to be fundamentally a culturally developed phenomenon. In this paper, I argue (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  15
    A Quantum Geometric Framework for Modeling Color Similarity Judgments.Gunnar P. Epping, Elizabeth L. Fisher, Ariel M. Zeleznikow-Johnston, Emmanuel M. Pothos & Naotsugu Tsuchiya - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (1):e13231.
    Since Tversky argued that similarity judgments violate the three metric axioms, asymmetrical similarity judgments have been particularly challenging for standard, geometric models of similarity, such as multidimensional scaling. According to Tversky, asymmetrical similarity judgments are driven by differences in salience or extent of knowledge. However, the notion of salience has been difficult to operationalize, especially for perceptual stimuli for which there are no apparent differences in extent of knowledge. To investigate similarity judgments between perceptual stimuli, across three experiments, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  71
    Kant on Geometrical Intuition and the Foundations of Mathematics.Frode Kjosavik - 2009 - Kant Studien 100 (1):1-27.
    It is argued that geometrical intuition, as conceived in Kant, is still crucial to the epistemological foundations of mathematics. For this purpose, I have chosen to target one of the most sympathetic interpreters of Kant's philosophy of mathematics – Michael Friedman – because he has formulated the possible historical limitations of Kant's views most sharply. I claim that there are important insights in Kant's theory that have survived the developments of modern mathematics, and thus, that they are not so (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15. A Survey of Geometric Algebra and Geometric Calculus.Alan Macdonald - 2017 - Advances in Applied Clifford Algebras 27:853-891.
    The paper is an introduction to geometric algebra and geometric calculus for those with a knowledge of undergraduate mathematics. No knowledge of physics is required. The section Further Study lists many papers available on the web.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  28
    Two Geometrical Examples From Aristotle's Metaphysics.Henry Mendell - 1984 - Classical Quarterly 34 (02):359-.
    The discussion of mathematical knowledge and its relation to the construction of an appropriate diagram in Aristotle's Metaphysics Θ 9. 1051 a21—33 is an important, if compressed, account of Aristotle's most mature thoughts on mathematical knowledge. The discussion of what sort of previous knowledge one must have for understanding a theorem recalls the discussion at An. Post. A 1. 71 a 17–21, where the epistemological point is similar and the examples the same. The first example, that the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  51
    Five Reasons to Doubt the Existence of a Geometric Module.Alexandra D. Twyman & Nora S. Newcombe - 2010 - Cognitive Science 34 (7):1315-1356.
    It is frequently claimed that the human mind is organized in a modular fashion, a hypothesis linked historically, though not inevitably, to the claim that many aspects of the human mind are innately specified. A specific instance of this line of thought is the proposal of an innately specified geometric module for human reorientation. From a massive modularity position, the reorientation module would be one of a large number that organized the mind. From the core knowledge position, the reorientation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  18.  14
    Learning by abduction: A geometrical interpretation.Inna Semetsky - 2005 - Semiotica 2005 (157):199-212.
    This paper posits Peirce’s logical category of abduction as a necessary component in the learning process. Because of the cardinality of categories, Thirdness always contains in itself the Firstness of abduction. In psychological terms, abduction can be interpreted as intuition or insight. The paper suggests that abduction can be modeled as a vector on a complex plane. Such geometrical interpretation of the triadic sign helps to clarify the paradox of new knowledge that haunted us since Plato first articulated (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  6
    The Geometrical Foundation of Federigo Enriques’ Gnoseology and Epistemology.Paolo Bussotti & Raffaele Pisano - unknown
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Elementary Students’ Construction of Geometric Transformation Reasoning in a Dynamic Animation Environment.N. Panorkou & A. Maloney - 2015 - Constructivist Foundations 10 (3):338-347.
    Context: Technology has not only changed the way we teach mathematical concepts but also the nature of knowledge, and thus what is possible to learn. While geometric transformations are recognized to be foundational to the formation of students’ geometric conceptions, little research has focused on how these notions can be introduced in elementary schooling. Problem: This project addressed the need for development of students’ reasoning about and with geometric transformations in elementary school. We investigated the nature of students’ understandings (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  31
    Hermann Cohen and Alois Riehl on Geometrical Empiricism.Francesca Biagioli - 2014 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (1):83-105.
    When non-Euclidean geometry was developed in the nineteenth century, both scientists and philosophers addressed the question as to whether the Kantian theory of space ought to be refurbished or even rejected. The possibility of considering a variety of hypotheses regarding physical space appeared to contradict Kant’s supposition of Euclid’s geometry as a priori knowledge and suggested the view that the geometry of space is a matter for empirical investigation. In this article, I discuss two different attempts to defend the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  19
    Free Variation and the Intuition of Geometric Essences: Some Reflections on Phenomenology and Modern Geometry.Richard Tieszen - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):153-173.
    Edmund Husserl has argued that we can intuit essences and, moreover, that it is possible to formulate a method for intuiting essences. Husserl calls this method ‘ideation’. In this paper I bring a fresh perspective to bear on these claims by illustrating them in connection with some examples from modern pure geometry. I follow Husserl in describing geometric essences as invariants through different types of free variations and I then link this to the mapping out of geometric invariants in modern (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  23. Kant on the Acquisition of Geometrical Concepts.John J. Callanan - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):580-604.
    It is often maintained that one insight of Kant's Critical philosophy is its recognition of the need to distinguish accounts of knowledge acquisition from knowledge justification. In particular, it is claimed that Kant held that the detailing of a concept's acquisition conditions is insufficient to determine its legitimacy. I argue that this is not the case at least with regard to geometrical concepts. Considered in the light of his pre-Critical writings on the mathematical method, construction in the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  51
    What is it the Unbodied Spirit cannot do? Berkeley and Barrow on the Nature of Geometrical Construction.Stefan Storrie - 2012 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (2):249-268.
    In ?155 of his New Theory of Vision Berkeley explains that a hypothetical ?unbodied spirit? ?cannot comprehend the manner wherein geometers describe a right line or circle?.1The reason for this, Berkeley continues, is that ?the rule and compass with their use being things of which it is impossible he should have any notion.? This reference to geometrical tools has led virtually all commentators to conclude that at least one reason why the unbodied spirit cannot have knowledge of plane (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  32
    Our Knowledge of What Is Real.Paul Weiss - 1964 - Review of Metaphysics 18 (1):3 - 22.
    WHAT IS PERHAPS the most influential of all theories of knowledge maintains that the content of knowledge and the known are identical in nature. The view goes back to Pythagoras, with his doctrine that reality is at once constituted of and known by means of geometrized numbers. Over the course of time, these numbers have been replaced by other equally startling candidates. The Platonic Idea, the Leibnizian Simple, the Berkeleyan Notion, the Humean Impression, the Peircean Third, and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  9
    Spatial diagrams and geometrical reasoning in the theater.Irit Degani-Raz - 2021 - Semiotica 2021 (239):177-200.
    This article offers an analysis of the cognitive role of diagrammatic movements in the theater. Based on the recognition of a theatrical work’s inherent ability to provide new insights concerning reality, the article concentrates on the way by which actors’ movements on stage create spatial diagrams that can provide new insights into the spectators’ world. The suggested model of theater’s epistemology results from a combination of Charles S. Peirce’s doctrine of diagrammatic reasoning and David Lewis’s theoretical account of the truth (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Core Knowledge of Geometry in an Amazonian Indigene Group.Stanislas Dehaene, Véronique Izard, Pierre Pica & Elizabeth Spelke - 2006 - Science 311 (5759)::381-4.
    Does geometry constitues a core set of intuitions present in all humans, regarless of their language or schooling ? We used two non verbal tests to probe the conceptual primitives of geometry in the Munduruku, an isolated Amazonian indigene group. Our results provide evidence for geometrical intuitions in the absence of schooling, experience with graphic symbols or maps, or a rich language of geometrical terms.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  28.  62
    Core knowledge of geometry can develop independently of visual experience.Benedetta Heimler, Tomer Behor, Stanislas Dehaene, Véronique Izard & Amir Amedi - 2021 - Cognition 212 (C):104716.
    Geometrical intuitions spontaneously drive visuo-spatial reasoning in human adults, children and animals. Is their emergence intrinsically linked to visual experience, or does it reflect a core property of cognition shared across sensory modalities? To address this question, we tested the sensitivity of blind-from-birth adults to geometrical-invariants using a haptic deviant-figure detection task. Blind participants spontaneously used many geometric concepts such as parallelism, right angles and geometrical shapes to detect intruders in haptic displays, but experienced difficulties with symmetry (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  89
    The Geometry of Knowledge.Johan van Benthem & Darko Sarenac - unknown
    The most widely used attractive logical account of knowledge uses standard epistemic models, i.e., graphs whose edges are indistinguishability relations for agents. In this paper, we discuss more general topological models for a multi-agent epistemic language, whose main uses so far have been in reasoning about space. We show that this more geometrical perspective affords greater powers of distinction in the study of common knowledge, defining new collective agents, and merging information for groups of agents.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  30.  16
    Cassirer and Klein on the Geometrical Foundations of Relativistic Physics.Francesca Biagioli - 2023 - In Chiara Russo Krauss & Luigi Laino (eds.), Philosophers and Einstein's Relativity: The Early Philosophical Reception of the Relativistic Revolution. Springer Verlag. pp. 89-105.
    Several studies have emphasized the limits of invariance-based approaches such as Klein’s and Cassirer’s when it comes to account for the shift from the spacetimes of classical mechanics and of special relativity to those of general relativity. Not only is it much more complicated to find such invariants in the case of general relativity, but even if local invariants in Weyl’s fashion are admitted, Cassirer’s attempt at a further generalization of his approach to the spacetime structure of general relativity seems (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  17
    The Knowledge of Other Egos.Theodor Lipps - 2018 - The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy:261-282. Translated by Marco Cavallaro.
    The text translated, “Das Wissen von fremden Ichen,” bears particular importance for the early phenomenological movement for two reasons. The first is Lipps’ refutation of the theory that knowledge of other selves arises by way of an inference from analogy. Lipps first developed his account of empathy to explain that we tend to succumb to geometric optical illusions because we project living activity into inanimate objects. In sum, Lipps’ groundbreaking article on The Knowledge of Other Egos deserves as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  12
    Reflections on the Notion of Culture in the History of Mathematics: The Example of “Geometrical Equations”.François Lê - 2016 - Science in Context 29 (3):273-304.
    ArgumentThis paper challenges the use of the notion of “culture” to describe a particular organization of mathematical knowledge, shared by a few mathematicians over a short period of time in the second half of the nineteenth century. This knowledge relates to “geometrical equations,” objects that proved crucial for the mechanisms of encounters between equation theory, substitution theory, and geometry at that time, although they were not well-defined mathematical objects. The description of the mathematical collective activities linked to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  49
    Spinoza's Epistemology through a Geometrical Lens.Michael LeBuffe - 2022 - Philosophical Quarterly 73 (3):859-861.
    This book concerns Spinoza's theory of knowledge and closely related issues: Spinoza's conceptions of geometrical figure or shape, number, and observational sci.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  20
    Spinoza’s Epistemology Through a Geometrical Lens.Matthew Homan - 2021 - Springer Verlag.
    This book interrogates the ontology of mathematical entities in Spinoza as a basis for addressing a wide range of interpretive issues in Spinoza’s epistemology—from his antiskepticism and philosophy of science to the nature and scope of reason and intuitive knowledge and the intellectual love of God. Going against recent trends in Spinoza scholarship, and drawing on various sources, including Spinoza’s engagements with optical theory and physics, Matthew Homan argues for a realist interpretation of geometrical figures in Spinoza; illustrates (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  10
    Kant's Explanation of the Necessity of Geometrical Truths.John Watling - 1971 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 5:131-144.
    Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling it ‘transcendental’. It is less extreme than Berkeley's in two ways. First, Kant does not assert that everything which exists is essentially mental, as Berkeley does. Second, those things which he does hold to be essentially mental, he holds to be so in a weaker fashion. Nevertheless he was an idealist; he held that neither intuition (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  5
    Physical Science, its Structure and Development: From Geometric Astronomy to the Mechanical Theory of Heat.Edwin C. Kemble - 1966 - MIT Press.
    This introduction to physical science combines a rigorous discussion of scientific principles with sufficient historical background and philosophic interpretation to add a new dimension of interest to the accounts given in more conventional textbooks. It brings out the twofold character of physical science as an expanding body of verifiable knowledge and as an organized human activity whose goals and values are major factors in the revolutionary changes sweeping over the world today.Professor Kemble insists that to understand science one must (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  17
    Kant's Explanation of the Necessity of Geometrical Truths.John Watling - 1971 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 5:131-144.
    Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling it ‘transcendental’. It is less extreme than Berkeley's in two ways. First, Kant does not assert that everything which exists is essentially mental, as Berkeley does. Second, those things which he does hold to be essentially mental, he holds to be so in a weaker fashion. Nevertheless he was an idealist; he held that neither intuition (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  25
    Differential Geometry, the Informational Surface and Oceanic Art: The Role of Pattern in Knowledge Economies.Susanne Küchler - 2017 - Theory, Culture and Society 34 (7-8):75-97.
    Graphic pattern (e.g. geometric design) and number-based code (e.g. digital sequencing) can store and transmit complex information more efficiently than referential modes of representation. The analysis of the two genres and their relation to one another has not advanced significantly beyond a general classification based on motion-centred geometries of symmetry. This article examines an intriguing example of patchwork coverlets from the maritime societies of Oceania, where information referencing a complex genealogical system is lodged in geometric designs. By drawing attention to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Kant on the imagination and geometrical certainty.Mary Domski - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (4):409-431.
    My goal in this paper is to develop our understanding of the role the imagination plays in Kant’s Critical account of geometry, and I do so by attending to how the imagination factors into the method of reasoning Kant assigns the geometer in the First Critique. Such an approach is not unto itself novel. Recent commentators, such as Friedman (1992) and Young (1992), have taken a careful look at the constructions of the productive imagination in pure intuition and highlighted the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Giordano Bruno and Bonaventura Cavalieri's theories of indivisibles: a case of shared knowledge.Paolo Rossini - 2018 - Intellectual History Review 28 (4):461-476.
    At the turn of the seventeenth century, Bruno and Cavalieri independently developed two theories, central to which was the concept of the geometrical indivisible. The introduction of indivisibles had significant implications for geometry – especially in the case of Cavalieri, for whom indivisibles provided a forerunner of the calculus. But how did this event occur? What can we learn from the fact that two theories of indivisibles arose at about the same time? These are the questions addressed in this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  18
    Spinoza, Adam Bede, Knowledge, and Sympathy: A Reply to Atkins.Ted Zenzinger - 2012 - Philosophy and Literature 36 (2):424-440.
    This paper joins the conversation on the relationship between Spinoza and George Eliot. After critically examining Atkins’s claim that the novels of George Eliot, as exemplified by Adam Bede, are a presentation of Spinoza’s philosophy stripped of the geometrical method, the paper explores Eliot’s philosophical engagement with Spinoza’s views on sympathy and the imagination. Thus, Eliot is read as a philosopher engaging with the arguments of Spinoza, rather than as someone representing his views in novel form.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  37
    Growth and development of root systems: Geometrical and structural aspects.Loïc Pages & Jocelyne Kervella - 1990 - Acta Biotheoretica 38 (3-4):289-302.
    The agronomist who wants to study the nutrient and water uptake of roots needs a quantitative three-dimensional dynamic model of the structure of root systems.The model presented takes into account current knowledge about the morphogenesis of root systems. It describes the root system as a set of root axes, characterised by their orders. The morphogenetic properties of root axes differ according to their order. The axes of order 1 are directly inserted on the stem, the axes of order 2 (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  71
    Method and the structure of knowledge in Spinoza.Diane Steinberg - 1998 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79 (2):152–169.
    It is argued, first, that although Spinoza's early Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect does show evidence of a foundationalist approach to the justification of knowledge, there are good reasons to think he came to find such an approach unsatisfactory; and second, that the Ethics notion of certainty as adequate knowledge of one's knowledge is a justificational concept which is holistic in that any instance of such certainty depends on knowledge of the entire basic metaphysical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  13
    The Theory of Knowledge of Giambattista Vico. [REVIEW]B. H. - 1970 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (2):341-342.
    The modern reinterpretations of Vico are a good example of the rethinking by historians of one age of the rethinking by historians of previous ages of the original thought of a philosopher. The present volume stresses the unique unity of theory and practice in Vico's thought and dispels some unfounded criticisms, such as his alleged reliance on the geometric method, inconsistencies in his use of the terms "philosophy" and "philology," and the mechanical acceptance of the patterns of development of Greece (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  2
    “Tear away the external chains”: the common struggle of the French Revolution and Fichte’s Doctrine of Scientific Knowledge.Thomas Van der Hallen - 2021 - Astérion 24.
    Dans sa violente charge contre la Révolution française, Edmund Burke avait élevé le débat politique à un niveau philosophique. Son argument le plus profond consistait à reprocher aux révolutionnaires de pécher par apriorisme, en cherchant à déduire, comme des géomètres, une nouvelle constitution à partir des principes abstraits énoncés dans la Déclaration des droits de l’homme. Reprise par les disciples allemands de Burke, cette critique de la méthode adoptée par la Constituante tirait des postulats empiristes des Lumières anglo-écossaises toutes les (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Review of Matthew Homan. Spinoza’s Epistemology through a Geometrical Lens. London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2021. Pp. xv+256. [REVIEW]Yitzhak Y. Melamed - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (2):329-31.
    Like most, if not all, of his contemporaries, Spinoza never developed a full-fledged philosophy of mathematics. Still, his numerous remarks about mathematics attest not only to his deep interest in the subject (a point which is also confirmed by the significant presence of mathematical books in his library), but also to his quite elaborate and perhaps unique understanding of the nature of mathematics. At the very center of his thought about mathematics stands a paradox (or, at least, an apparent paradox): (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  10
    Hermann Cohen’s logic of the pure knowledge as a philosophy of science.Zinaida A. Sokuler - 2022 - RUDN Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):658-671.
    The connection of Hermann Сohen’s “The Logic of Pure Knowledge” with the revolutionary transformations in physics and mathematics at the end of the 19th century is shown. Сohen criticised Kant’s answer to the question “How is mathematics possible”? If Kant refers to a priori forms of pure intuition, Сohen sees in it a restriction of freedom of mathematical thinking by limits of intuition. It has been shown that Cohen's position is in accordance with the main development of mathematics in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  24
    How does low level vision interact with knowledge?John R. Pani - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (3):387-388.
    Basic processes of perception should be cognitively impenetrable so that they are not prey to momentary changes of belief. That said, how does low level vision interact with knowledge to allow recognition? Much more needs to be known about the products of low level vision than that they represent the geometric layout of the world.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  22
    Intuition and Reasoning in Geometry.Otto Hölder - 2013 - Philosophia Scientiae 17:15-52.
    The way in which geometrical knowledge has been obtained has always attracted the attention of philosophers. The fact that there is a science that concerns things outside our thinking and that proceeds inferentially appeared striking, and gave rise to specific theories of experience and space. Nonetheless, the geometrical method has not yet been sufficiently investigated. Philosophers who investigate the theory of knowledge discuss the question of whether geometry is an empirical science, but...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  17
    Intuition and Reasoning in Geometry. Inaugural Academic Lecture held on July 22, 1899. With supplements and notes.Otto Hölder - 2013 - Philosophia Scientiae 17 (17-1):15-52.
    The way in which geometrical knowledge has been obtained has always attracted the attention of philosophers. The fact that there is a science that concerns things outside our thinking and that proceeds inferentially appeared striking, and gave rise to specific theories of experience and space. Nonetheless, the geometrical method has not yet been sufficiently investigated. Philosophers who investigate the theory of knowledge discuss the question of whether geometry is an empirical science, but.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 978