Switch to: References

Citations of:

Progress and its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth

University of California Press (1977)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Truth, rationality and the sociology of science.Richard C. Jennings - 1984 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (3):201-211.
    Philosophers of science are becoming more sensitive to the claims about truth and rationality being made by sociologists of science. There is a tendency among some of these philosophers to dismiss such claims as irrelevant to philosophy of science and as self-refuting. Larry Laudan, in his 'arationality assumption', has captured the essence of positions which argue that sociology of science can only be concerned with scientific claims which are not rational (or, in some versions, 'not true'). I show that the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Limits to problem solving in science.Struan Jacobs - 2001 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (3):231 – 242.
    Popper, Polanyi and Duncker represent the widely held position that theoretical and experimental scientific research are motivated by problems to which discoveries are solutions. According to the argument here, their views are unsupported and - in light of counter-instances, anomalous chance discoveries, and the force of curiosity - over-generalized.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How to change Behavior?Iver H. Iversen - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):457.
  • Theory Choice, Good Sense and Social Consensus.Milena Ivanova & Cedric Paternotte - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (5):1109-1132.
    There has been a significant interest in the recent literature in developing a solution to the problem of theory choice which is both normative and descriptive, but agent-based rather than rule-based, originating from Pierre Duhem’s notion of ‘good sense’. In this paper we present the properties Duhem attributes to good sense in different contexts, before examining its current reconstructions advanced in the literature and their limitations. We propose an alternative account of good sense, seen as promoting social consensus in science, (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Friedman’s Relativised A Priori and Structural Realism: In Search of Compatibility.Milena Ivanova - 2011 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 25 (1):23-37.
    In this article I discuss a recent argument due to Dan McArthur, who suggests that the charge that Michael Friedman’s relativised a priori leads to irrationality in theory change can be avoided by adopting structural realism. I provide several arguments to show that the conjunction of Friedman’s relativised a priori with structural realism cannot make the former avoid the charge of irrationality. I also explore the extent to which Friedman’s view and structural realism are compatible, a presupposition of McArthur’s argument. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Scientific Discovery Reloaded.Emiliano Ippoliti - 2020 - Topoi 39 (4):847-856.
    The way scientific discovery has been conceptualized has changed drastically in the last few decades: its relation to logic, inference, methods, and evolution has been deeply reloaded. The ‘philosophical matrix’ moulded by logical empiricism and analytical tradition has been challenged by the ‘friends of discovery’, who opened up the way to a rational investigation of discovery. This has produced not only new theories of discovery, but also new ways of practicing it in a rational and more systematic way. Ampliative rules, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What epistemic values should we reclaim for religion and science? A response to J. Wesley Robbins.J. Wentzel Huyssteen - 1993 - Zygon 28 (3):371-376.
  • Realism and nursing.Trevor Hussey - 2000 - Nursing Philosophy 1 (2):98–108.
    It is argued that philosophical realism is well suited to serve as a perspective from which to understand nursing, and that it should be considered as an alternative to positivist, interpretivist, hermeneutical and phenomenological approaches. However, existing forms of realism, including theory and entity realism are shown to be faced with serious problems. In response, an alternative form ‘constraint realism’ is outlined, and shown to be apposite for illuminating the rule or convention governed behaviour characteristic of human beings. A brief (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Theory Status, Inductive Realism, and Approximate Truth: No Miracles, No Charades.Shelby D. Hunt - 2011 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 25 (2):159 - 178.
    The concept of approximate truth plays a prominent role in most versions of scientific realism. However, adequately conceptualizing ?approximate truth? has proved challenging. This article argues that the goal of articulating the concept of approximate truth can be advanced by first investigating the processes by which science accords theories the status of accepted or rejected. Accordingly, this article uses a path diagram model as a visual heuristic for the purpose of showing the processes in science that are involved in determining (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kuhnian paradigms as representational spaces: New perspectives on the problems of incommensurability, scientific explanation, and physical necessity.Edwin H.-C. Hung - 2001 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (3):275 – 292.
    This paper starts with an intuitive notion of representational spaces, which is intended to provide an improved version of Kuhn's concept of paradigms. It then proceeds to study the following topics in terms of this new notion: incommensurability, paradigm change, explanation of anomalies, explanation of regularities, explanation of irregularities, and physical necessity. In the course of the investigation, "representational space" gets clarified and defined. It is envisaged that this new concept should throw light on many issues in the philosophy of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Rationality as Effective Organisation of Interaction and Its Naturalist Framework.Cliff Hooker - 2011 - Axiomathes 21 (1):99-172.
    The point of this paper is to provide a principled framework for a naturalistic, interactivist-constructivist model of rational capacity and a sketch of the model itself, indicating its merits. Being naturalistic, it takes its orientation from scientific understanding. In particular, it adopts the developing interactivist-constructivist understanding of the functional capacities of biological organisms as a useful naturalistic platform for constructing such higher order capacities as reason and cognition. Further, both the framework and model are marked by the finitude and fallibility (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Some reflections on testing psychoanalytic hypotheses.Robert R. Holt - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):242-244.
  • Why the problem of reductionism in biology has implications for economics.Geoffrey M. Hodgson - 1993 - World Futures 37 (2):69-90.
    For several decades, economists have been preoccupied with an attempt to place their entire subject on the ‘sound microfoundations’ of general equilibrium theory, with its individualistic premises. However, this project has run into seemingly intractable problems. This essay examines underlying questions such as the appropriate building block of analysis and the structure of explanation in economics. The examination of biology is found to be instructive, due to debates concerning the limitations of reductionism within that discipline. The final part of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Repressed infantile wishes as the instigators of all dreams.J. Allan Hobson - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):241-242.
  • A limited defense of the pessimistic induction.Jesse Hobbs - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (1):171-191.
    The inductive argument from the falsity of most past scientific theories (more than 100 years old) to the falsity of most present ones is defensible, I argue, if it is modified to account for the degrees of theoreticity or observationality in such theories, and the extent to which they are hedged. The case of descriptive astronomy is examined to show that most of the true theories of the 1890s were high in observationality and/or significantly hedged. The false theories of that (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Feeding, forward and backward: Mostly red herrings.Philip N. Hineline - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):456.
  • What Is an Immature Science?Ruth Hibbert - 2016 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 30 (1):1-17.
    Cognitive and social sciences such as psychology and sociology are often described as immature sciences. But what is immaturity? According to the received view, immaturity is disunity, where disunity can usefully be cashed out in terms of having a plurality of disunified frameworks in play, where these frameworks consist of concepts, theories, goals, practices, methods, criteria for what counts as a good explanation, etc. However, there are some reasons to think that the cognitive and social sciences should be disunified in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A response to the critique of rational choice theory: Lakatos' and Laudan's conceptions applied.Kaisa Herne & Maija Setälä - 2004 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 47 (1):67 – 85.
    This paper analyzes the main features of rational choice theory and evaluates it with respect to the conceptions of Lakatos' research program and Laudan's research tradition. The analysis reveals that the thin rationality assumption, the axiomatic method and the reduction to the micro level are the only features shared by all rational choice models. On these grounds, it is argued that rational choice theory cannot be characterized as a research program. This is due to the fact that the thin rationality (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Revisiting ‘Weinberg’s Choice’: Classic Tensions in the Concept of Scientific Merit. [REVIEW]Tomas Hellström & Merle Jacob - 2012 - Minerva 50 (3):381-396.
    Alvin Weinberg’s classic and much debated two articles in Minerva, “Criteria for Scientific Choice” (1963) and “Criteria for Scientific Choice II – The Two Cultures” (1964), represent two of the first and most important attempts to create a meta-discourse about priority setting in science policy, and many of the points advanced remain relevant. The goal of this paper is to elaborate on the relevance of some of Weinberg’s original arguments to priority setting today. We have singled out four issues for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Internally represented grammars.Gilbert Harman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):408.
  • Computational commitment and physical realization.Robert M. Harrish - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):408-409.
  • Reinforcement without representation.Stephen José Hanson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):141-142.
  • Economics and Laudan's normative naturalism: Bad news from instrumental rationality's front line.D. Wade Hands - 1996 - Social Epistemology 10 (2):137 – 152.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Blaug's economic methodology.Douglas W. Hands - 1984 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 14 (1):115-125.
  • The nature of research methodology: Editorial introduction.Brian D. Haig - 1992 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 24 (2):1–7.
  • Scientific problems and the conduct of research.Brian D. Haig - 1987 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 19 (2):22–32.
  • On the semiotic dimension of ecological theory: The case of island biogeography. [REVIEW]Yrjö Haila - 1986 - Biology and Philosophy 1 (4):377-387.
    The Macarthur-Wilson equilibrium theory of island biogeography has had a contradictory role in ecology. As a lasting contribution, the theory has created a new way of viewing insular environments as dynamical systems. On the other hand, many of the applications of the theory have reduced to mere unimaginative curve-fitting. I analyze this paradox in semiotic terms: the theory was mainly equated with the simple species-area relationship which became a signifier of interesting island ecology. The theory is, however, better viewed as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Research perspectives and the anomalous status of modern ecology.Joel B. Hagen - 1989 - Biology and Philosophy 4 (4):433-455.
    Ecology has often been characterized as an immature scientific discipline. This paper explores some of the sources of this alleged immaturity. I argue that the perception of immaturity results primarily from the fact that historically ecologists have based their work upon two very different approaches to research.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Naturalism, normativity, and explanation: Some scientistic biases of contemporary naturalism.Guy Axtell - 1993 - Metaphilosophy 24 (3):253-274.
    The critical focus of this paper is on a claim made explicitly by Gilbert Harman and accepted implicitly by numerous others, the claim that naturalism supports concurrent defense of scientific objectivism and moral relativism. I challenge the assumptions of Harman's ‘argument from naturalism' used to support this combination of positions, utilizing. Hilary Putnam’s ‘companions in guilt’ argument in order to counter it. The paper concludes that while domain-specific anti-realism is often warranted, Harman’s own views about the objectivity of facts and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A few analogies with computing.Maurice Gross - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):407.
  • Prediction in Selectionist Evolutionary Theory.Rasmus Gr⊘Nfeldt Winther - 2009 - Philosophy of Science 76 (5):889-901.
    Selectionist evolutionary theory has often been faulted for not making novel predictions that are surprising, risky, and correct. I argue that it in fact exhibits the theoretical virtue of predictive capacity in addition to two other virtues: explanatory unification and model fitting. Two case studies show the predictive capacity of selectionist evolutionary theory: parallel evolutionary change in E. coli, and the origin of eukaryotic cells through endosymbiosis.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Précis of The Foundations of Psychoanalysis: A Philosophical Critique.Adolf Grünbaum - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):217-228.
    This book critically examines Freud's own detailed arguments for his major explanatory and therapeutic principles, the current neorevisionist versions of psychoanalysis, and the hermeneuticists' reconstruction of Freud's theory and therapy as an alternative to what they claim was a “scientistic” misconstrual of the psychoanalytic enterprise. The clinical case for Freud's cornerstone theory of repression – the claim that psychic conflict plays a causal role in producing neuroses, dreams, and bungled actions – turns out to be ill-founded for two main reasons: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Is Freud's theory well-founded?Adolf Grünbaum - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):266-284.
  • Ad hoc auxiliary hypotheses and falsificationism.Adolf Grünbaum - 1976 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (4):329-362.
  • Explanatory inquiry and the need for explanation.Stephen R. Grimm - 2008 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (3):481-497.
    Explanatory inquiry characteristically begins with a certain puzzlement about the world. But why do certain situations elicit our puzzlement while others leave us, in some epistemically relevant sense, cold? Moreover, what exactly is involved in the move from a state of puzzlement to a state where one's puzzlement is satisfied? In this paper I try to answer both of these questions. I also suggest ways in which our account of scientific rationality might benefit from having a better sense of the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • The case against Freud's cases.Roger P. Greenberg - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):240-241.
  • Has learning been shown to be attractor modification within reinforcement modelling?Robert A. M. Gregson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):140-141.
  • Truth about consequences.George Graham - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):455.
  • Facts and Sensibilities: What Is a Psychoanalytic Innovation?Aner Govrin - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can experiments be used to study science?Michael Gorman & Bernard Carlson - 1989 - Social Epistemology 3 (2):89 – 106.
  • Rorty's new myth of the given.Michael Goldman - 1988 - Metaphilosophy 19 (2):105–112.
    But the dangers to abnormal discourse do not come from science or naturalistic philosophy. They come from the scarcity of food and from the secret police. Given leisure and libraries, the conversation which Plato began will not end in self‐objedification ‐ not because aspects of the world, or of human beings, escape being objects of scientific inquiry, but simply because free and leisured conversation generates abnormal discourse as the sparks fly upward.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Foundations of social epistemics.Alvin I. Goldman - 1987 - Synthese 73 (1):109 - 144.
    A conception of social epistemology is articulated with links to studies of science and opinion in such disciplines as history, sociology, and political science. The conception is evaluative, though, rather than purely descriptive. Three types of evaluative approaches are examined but rejected: relativism, consensualism, and expertism. A fourth, truth-linked, approach to intellectual evaluation is then advocated: social procedures should be appraised by their propensity to foster true belief. Standards of evaluation in social epistemics would be much the same as those (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Epistemology and the theory of problem solving.Alvin I. Goldman - 1983 - Synthese 55 (1):21-48.
    Problem solving has recently become a central topic both in the philosophy of science and in cognitive science. This paper integrates approaches to problem solving from these two disciplines and discusses the epistemological consequences of such an integration. The paper first analyzes problem solving as getting a true answer to a question. It then explores some stages of cognitive activity relevant to question answering that have been delineated by historians and philosophers of science and by cognitive psychologists and artificial intelligencers. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • An economic model of scientific activity and truth acquisition.Alvin I. Goldman & Moshe Shaked - 1991 - Philosophical Studies 63 (1):31-55.
    Economic forms of analysis have penetrated to many disciplines in the last 30 years: political science, sociology, law, social and political philosophy, and so forth. We wish to extend the economic paradigm to certain problems in epistemology and the philosophy of science. Scientific agents, and scholarly inquirers generally, act in some ways like vendors, trying to "sell" their findings, theories, analyses, or arguments to an audience of prospective "buyers". The analogy with the marketplace is imperfect. The ideas or discoveries that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Hattiangadi's theory of scientific problems and the structure of standard epistemologies.Marco Giunti - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4):421-439.
  • Pragmatist themes in Van Fraassen’s stances and Hegel’s forms of consciousness.Paul Giladi - 2016 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 24 (1):95-111.
    The aim of this paper is to establish a substantial positive philosophical connection between Bas van Fraassen and Hegel, by focusing on their respective notions of ‘stance’ and ‘form of consciousness’. In Section I, I run through five ways of understanding van Fraassen’s idea of a stance. I argue that a ‘stance’ is best understood as an intellectual disposition. This, in turn, means that the criteria for assessing a stance are ones which ask whether or not a stance adequately makes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy of science naturalized.Ronald N. Giere - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (3):331-356.
    In arguing a "role for history," Kuhn was proposing a naturalized philosophy of science. That, I argue, is the only viable approach to the philosophy of science. I begin by exhibiting the main general objections to a naturalistic approach. These objections, I suggest, are equally powerful against nonnaturalistic accounts. I review the failure of two nonnaturalistic approaches, methodological foundationism (Carnap, Reichenbach, and Popper) and metamethodology (Lakatos and Laudan). The correct response, I suggest, is to adopt an "evolutionary perspective." This perspective (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Toward a cognitive psychology of science.Barry Gholson & Arthur Houts - 1989 - Social Epistemology 3 (2):107 – 127.
  • Warranting interpretations.Alan Gauld & John Shotter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):239-240.
  • How Successful is Naturalism?Georg Gasser (ed.) - 2007 - Frankfurt: Ontos Verlag.
    The aim of the present volume is to draw the balance of naturalism's success so far.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations