Results for 'social coercion'

978 found
Order:
  1. On the need for social coercion.Michael Huemer - manuscript
    The problem I am concerned with is very general: Why do we need a coercive institution in our society to control our behavior? This question is a little different from "Why do we need a government?" in two ways: First, because "coercive institution" is a broader term than "government"; probably not every coercive institution that controlled people's behavior would be called a government, though every government is a coercive institution (that is, an institution exercising coercion as one of its (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  28
    Coercion and cooperation: What are the measures of social coercion necessary to safeguard the technique of effective cooperation?E. Cannabrava - 1963 - World Futures 2 (sup001):60-64.
    (1963). Coercion and cooperation: What are the measures of social coercion necessary to safeguard the technique of effective cooperation? World Futures: Vol. 2, No. sup001, pp. 60-64.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  83
    A woman's choice? On women, assisted reproduction and social coercion.Thomas Søbirk Petersen - 2004 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (1):81 - 90.
    This paper critically discusses an argument that is sometimes pressed into service in the ethical debate about the use of assisted reproduction. The argument runs roughly as follows: we should prevent women from using assisted reproduction techniques, because women who want to use the technology have been socially coerced into desiring children - and indeed have thereby been harmed by the patriarchal society in which they live. I call this the argument from coercion. Having clarified this argument, I conclude (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Equality, coercion, culture and social norms.Richard J. Arneson - 2003 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 2 (2):139-163.
    Against the libertarian view, this essay argues that coercion aimed at bringing about a more equal distribution across persons can be morally acceptable. Informal social norms might lead toward equality (or another social justice goal) without coercion. If coercion were unnecessary, it would be morally undesirable. A consequentialist integration of social norms and principles of social justice is proposed. The proposal is provided with a preliminary defense against the non-consequentialist egalitarianism of G.A. Cohen (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5. Coercion as enforcement, and the social organization of power relations: A rubric for distinguishing coercion from related phenomena.Scott Anderson - unknown
    The traditional understanding of coercion as exemplified by the use of force and violence to constrain the actions of agents has been challenged by theories that describe coercion instead in terms of the pressure it puts on some agents to act or refrain from acting. Building on earlier work defending the traditional understanding and rejecting the ‘pressure’ accounts of coercion, I argue in this paper that the traditional understanding of coercion, which I dub ‘coercion as (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  47
    Coercion as Enforcement, and the Social Organisation of Power Relations: Coercion in Specific Contexts of Social Power.Scott A. Anderson - 2016 - Jurisprudence 7 (3):525-539.
    Many recent theories of coercion broaden the scope of the concept coercion by encompassing interactions in which one agent pressures another to act, subject to some further qualifications. I have argued previously that this way of conceptualizing coercion undermines its suitability for theoretical use in politics and ethics. I have also explicated a narrower, more traditional approach—“the enforcement approach to coercion”—and argued for its superiority. In this essay, I consider the prospects for broadening this more traditional (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  11
    La ontología social de Wilfrid Sellars: Razonamiento práctico, conexiones instrumentales y coerción social.José Giromini - 2024 - Análisis Filosófico 44 (1):5-34.
    El presente trabajo identifica en la obra de Wilfrid Sellars dos tesis relevantes para el debate contemporáneo en ontología social. La primera dice que podemos entender la realidad social como estando compuesta parcialmente por estructuras causales o coercitivas. La segunda, que la realidad social se le presenta a los agentes como estando constituida por estructuras coercitivas. El trabajo defiende estas tesis interpretativas recurriendo a los escritos de filosofía práctica de Sellars, y especialmente a su explicación del funcionamiento (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  68
    Penal Coercion in Contexts of Social Injustice.Roberto Gargarella - 2011 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 5 (1):21-38.
    This article addresses the theoretical difficulty of justifying the use of penal coercion in circumstances of marked, unjustified social inequality. The intuitive belief behind the text is that in such a context—that of an indecent State—justifying penal coercion becomes very problematic, particularly when directed against the most disfavored members of society.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  28
    Voluntary Coercion. Collective Action and the Social Contract.Magnus Jiborn - unknown
    This work provides a game theoretical analysis of the classical idea of a social contract. According to what we might call the Hobbesian justification of the state, coercion is necessary in order to provide people with basic security and to enable them to successfully engage in mutually beneficial cooperation. The establishment and maintenance of a central coercive power, i.e. a state, can therefore be said to be in everyone's interest. The aim of this essay is to examine and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  20
    Coercion in the Community: A Situated Approach to the Examination of Ethical Challenges for Mental Health Social Workers.Jim Campbell & Gavin Davidson - 2009 - Ethics and Social Welfare 3 (3):249-263.
    Increasingly, mental health social workers in the United Kingdom and elsewhere in the world are employing coercive interventions with clients. This paper explores this trend in the context of community-based settings, using national and international research literature on this subject. It begins with a discussion about the complex, contested nature of ideas on coercion. The authors then explore debates about how coercion is perceived and applied in practice. They choose two forms of coercion?informal types of leverage, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  13
    Coercion in Social Accounts of Law: Can Coerciveness Undermine Legality?Jean Thomas - 2021 - Law and Philosophy 40 (5):471-508.
    Many recent arguments about the role of coercive sanctions in law suggest that the importance of coercion is underrated. The question has thus been where the lower threshold for coercion might be within a legal system. Very little attention, by contrast, has been paid to whether, at some upper threshold, coerciveness might itself present a problem for law, even on a positivist account. In this article I therefore interrogate the standard positivist picture from this unorthodox direction: Is it (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  13
    Social Cohesion and Legal Coercion: A Critique of Weber, Durkheim, and Marx.Leon Shaskolsky Sheleff (ed.) - 1997 - Brill | Rodopi.
    The book is a critical analysis of the work of Max Weber, Emile Durkheim and Karl Marx. It focuses on their separate analyses of the role of law in society, pointing out their faults and errors, and the resultant impact on modern social science. The author takes issue with Weber's work on rationality, with Durkheim's work on repressive and restitutive law, and with Marx's work on social justice and law as part of the super-structure. In each section of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  21
    Ethics of Coercion and Authority: A Philosophical Study of Social Life.Timo Airaksinen - 1988 - University of Pittsburgh Press.
    "The work would be of great value to philosophers engaged in the conceptual analysis of coercion, to political scientists studying the state or other coercive institutions, and to advanced readers interested in the field of peace research."--Choice.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  37
    Participatory Bioethics Research and its Social Impact: The Case of Coercion Reduction in Psychiatry.Tineke A. Abma, Yolande Voskes & Guy Widdershoven - 2017 - Bioethics 31 (2):144-152.
    In this article we address the social value of bioethics research and show how a participatory approach can achieve social impact for a wide audience of stakeholders, involving them in a process of joint moral learning. Participatory bioethics recognizes that research co-produced with stakeholders is more likely to have impact on healthcare practice. These approaches aim to engage multiple stakeholders and interested partners throughout the whole research process, including the framing of ideas and research questions, so that outcomes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15. Law, Coercion and Folk Intuitions.Lucas Miotto, Guilherme F. C. F. Almeida & Noel Struchiner - 2023 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 43 (1):97-123.
    In discussing whether legal systems are necessarily coercive, legal philosophers usually appeal to thought experiments involving angels or other morally driven beings who need no coercion to organise their social lives. Such appeals have invited criticism. Critics have not only challenged the relevance of such thought experiments to our understanding of legal systems; they have also argued that, contrary to the intuitions of most legal philosophers, the ‘man on the Clapham Omnibus’ would not hold that there is law (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  41
    Poverty Knowledge, Coercion, and Social Rights: A Discourse Ethical Contribution to Social Epistemology.David Ingram - unknown
    In today’s America the persistence of crushing poverty in the midst of staggering affluence no longer incites the righteous jeremiads it once did. Resigned acceptance of this paradox is fueled by a sense that poverty lies beyond the moral and technical scope of government remediation. The failure of experts to reach agreement on the causes of poverty merely exacerbates our despair. Are the causes internal to the poor – reflecting their more or less voluntary choices? Or do they emanate from (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  20
    Liberal eugenics, coercion and social pressure.Blanca Rodríguez López - 2024 - Enrahonar: Quaderns de Filosofía 72:73-89.
    When discussing genetic prenatal enhancement, we often encounter objections related to “eugenics.” Those who want to defend prenatal enhancement either try to avoid using the term “eugenics” or talk about “liberal eugenics”, implying that what was wrong with the old eugenics was its coercive character, and claiming that while old eugenics went against reproductive freedom, the new liberal eugenics promotes freedom. In this paper we first explore the objection that genetic enhancement is a form of eugenics that limits parental freedom. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  92
    Coercion and Moral Responsibility.Denis G. Arnold - 2001 - American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (1):53 - 67.
    In this dissertation I develop a general theory of coercion that allows one to distinguish cases of interpersonal coercion from cases of persuasion or manipulation, and cases of institutional coercion from cases of oppression. The general theory of coercion that I develop includes as one component a theory of second-order coercion. Second-order coercion takes place whenever one person intentionally impairs the formation of the second-order desires of another person, or constrains them after their formation, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  19. Coercion and Captivity.Lisa Rivera - 2014 - In Lori Gruen (ed.), The Ethics of Captivity. pp. 248-271.
    This paper considers three modes of captivity with an eye to examining the effects of captivity on free agency and whether these modes depend on or constitute coercion. These modes are: physical captivity, psychological captivity, and social/legal captivity. All these modes of captivity may severely impact capacities a person relies on for free agency in different ways. They may also undermine or destroy a person’s identity-constituting cares and values. On a Nozick-style view of coercion, coercion amounts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  30
    Ethics of Coercion and Authority: A Philosophical Study of Social Life, by Timo Airaksinen. [REVIEW]Denise Myerson - 1991 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (3):704-707.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  6
    Coercion.Grant Lamond - 2010 - In Dennis Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 642–653.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Coercion Law References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. Coercion, the basic structure, and the family.Blain Neufeld - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (1):37-54.
    In this article I revise and defend a core feature of political liberalism, namely, the idea that principles of political justice should be limited in their scope of application to what John Rawls calls the ‘basic structure of society.’ I refer to this feature as the ‘basic structure restriction’ of political liberalism. According to my account of the basic structure restriction, the basic structure includes all and only those institutions that have a profound effect on the lives of all citizens, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  23. Coercion of foreigners, territory and compensation.Chris Bertram - manuscript
    Justifications for state authority are typically directed towards the good of those subject to that authority. But, because of their territorial nature, states exercise coercion not only towards insiders but also towards non-members. Such coercion can take the form of denying outsiders the right to enter a territory or to settle in it permanently, as well as various restraints on trade and association. When coercion is directed at insiders, it often comes packaged with various claims about distributive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Kant, coercion, and the legitimation of inequality.Benjamin L. McKean - 2022 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 25 (4):528-550.
    Immanuel Kant’s political philosophy has enjoyed renewed attention as an egalitarian alternative to contemporary inequality since it seems to uncompromisingly reassert the primacy of the state over the economy, enabling it to defend the modern welfare state against encroaching neoliberal markets. However, I argue that, when understood as a free-standing approach to politics, Kant’s doctrine of right shares essential features with the prevailing theories that legitimate really existing economic inequality. Like Friedrich Hayek and Milton Friedman, Kant understands the state’s function (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Expanding the Frame of "Voluntariness" in Informed Consent: Structural Coercion and the Power of Social and Economic Context.Jill A. Fisher - 2013 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23 (4):355-379.
    Whether intended or not, conceptions of informed consent are often rooted in archetypal notions of the researcher and prospective study participant. The former is assumed problematically to be a disinterested yet humanitarian individual who is well trained to conduct robust science. The latter is often characterized as being motivated by some altruistic notions about the contribution to science and society they are making even as they seek some personal benefit from the research. Cast in a dyad, the researcher has the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  26.  24
    Structural coercion in the context of community engagement in global health research conducted in a low resource setting in Africa.Deborah Nyirenda, Salla Sariola, Patricia Kingori, Bertie Squire, Chiwoza Bandawe, Michael Parker & Nicola Desmond - 2020 - BMC Medical Ethics 21 (1):1-10.
    Background While community engagement is increasingly promoted in global health research to improve ethical research practice, it can sometimes coerce participation and thereby compromise ethical research. This paper seeks to discuss some of the ethical issues arising from community engagement in a low resource setting. Methods A qualitative study design focusing on the engagement activities of three biomedical research projects as ethnographic case studies was used to gain in-depth understanding of community engagement as experienced by multiple stakeholders in Malawi. Data (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  65
    Justifying coercion.Paula K. Vuckovich & Barbara M. Artinian - 2005 - Nursing Ethics 12 (4):370-380.
    A grounded theory study of psychiatric nurses’ experiences of administering medication to involuntary psychiatric patients revealed a basic social process of justifying coercion. Although the 17 nurses interviewed all reported success at avoiding the use of coercion, each had an individual approach to using the nurse-patient relationship to do this. However, all the nurses used the same process to reconcile themselves to using coercion when it became necessary. This has three stages: assessment of need; negotiation; and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  28. Coercion as enforcement.Scott A. Anderson - unknown
    This essay provides a positive account of coercion that avoids significant difficulties that have confronted most other recent accounts. It enters this territory by noting a dispute over whether coercion has to manipulate the will of the coercee, or whether direct force inhibiting action (such as manhandling or imprisoning) is itself coercive. Though this dispute may at first seem a mere matter of taxonomic categorization, I argue that this dispute reflects an important divergence in thought about the nature (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  59
    Coercion, reciprocity, and equality beyond the state.Chris Armstrong - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (3):297-316.
  30.  12
    Coercion, Reciprocity, and Equality Beyond the State.Chris Armstrong - 2009 - Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (3):297-316.
  31.  64
    Coercion, political accountability, and voter ignorance: The mistaken medicaid expansion ruling in NFIB v. Sebelius.Alexander A. Guerrero - 2013 - Public Affairs Quarterly 27 (3).
    Although the individual mandate was upheld and the Commerce Clause may have been cabined, the decision to strike down a significant element of the “Medicaid expansion” may prove to be the most significant aspect of the Supreme Court’s decision in NFIB v. Sebelius. Under the Affordable Care Act (ACA), States were required to extend Medicaid coverage to all individuals under the age of 65 with incomes below 133 percent of the poverty line, a new “essential health benefits” package was required (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  12
    Justified Coercion.Timo Airaksinen - 1990 - Social Philosophy Today 3:21-40.
  33.  72
    The Enforcement Approach to Coercion.Scott A. Anderson - 2010 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 5 (1):1-31.
    This essay differentiates two approaches to understanding the concept of coercion, and argues for the relative merits of the one currently out of fashion. The approach currently dominant in the philosophical literature treats threats as essential to coercion, and understands coercion in terms of the way threats alter the costs and benefits of an agent’s actions; I call this the “pressure” approach. It has largely superseded the “enforcement approach,” which focuses on the powers and actions of the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  34.  6
    Beyond coercion: reframing the influencing other in medically assisted death.Mara Buchbinder & Noah Berens - forthcoming - Journal of Medical Ethics.
    This essay considers how we are to understand the decision to end one’s life under medical aid-in-dying (MAID) statutes and the role of influencing others. Bioethical concerns about the potential for abuse in MAID have focused predominantly on the risk of coercion and other forms of undue influence. Most bioethical analyses of relational influences in MAID have been made by opponents of MAID, who argue that MAID is unethical, in part, because it cannot cleanly accommodate relational influences. In contrast, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  68
    Coercion.Juri Viehoff - 2014 - In The Encyclopedia of Political Thought. Chichester: Wiley.
    Claims about coercion play a significant role in some of the most important questions in political philosophy: most ordinary citizens as well as philosophers think that the exercise of power by the state and other political institutions is coercive, and as such requires special justification. Political philosophy, it has been assumed, must assess both the truth of that claim and its relevance for whether or not states, in general, can be justified. Whether the state is always or necessarily coercive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Coercion, Value and Justice: Redistribution in a Neutral State.Michael Hemmingsen - 2014 - Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 61 (138):37-49.
    I argue that a commitment to liberal neutrality, and an opposition to coercion, means that we ought to support a redistributive state in which wealth, insofar as it is instrumental in allowing us to pursue our ends, is equalised. This is due to the fact that any conception of justice and desert works in favour of some, but against others, and that those who lose out by any particular conception are likely not to consent to it (meaning that its (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Coercion, ownership, and the redistributive state: Justificatory liberalism's classical tilt: Gerald Gaus.Gerald Gaus - 2010 - Social Philosophy and Policy 27 (1):233-275.
    Justificatory liberalism is liberal in an abstract and foundational sense: it respects each as free and equal, and so insists that coercive laws must be justified to all members of the public. In this essay I consider how this fundamental liberal principle relates to disputes within the liberal tradition on “the extent of the state.” It is widely thought today that this core liberal principle of respect requires that the state regulates the distribution of resources or well-being to conform to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  38.  43
    Justified Coercion.Timo Airaksinen - 1990 - Social Philosophy Today 3:21-40.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  43
    Coercion and Practical Reason.Mark Fowler - 1982 - Social Theory and Practice 8 (3):329-355.
  40. State coercion and force.Christopher W. Morris - 2012 - Social Philosophy and Policy 29 (1):28-49.
    Research Articles Christopher W. Morris, Social Philosophy and Policy, FirstView Article.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  41.  15
    Care, Coercion and Dignity at the End of Life.Cathriona Russell - 2019 - Studies in Christian Ethics 32 (1):36-45.
    End-of-life debates in medical ethics often centre around several interrelated issues: improving care, avoiding coercion, and recognising the dignity and rights of the terminally ill. Care ethics advocates relational autonomy and non-abandonment. These commitments, however, face system pressures—economic, social and legal—that can be coercive. This article takes up two related aspects in this domain of ethics. Firstly, that competence and communication are core clinical ethics principles that can sidestep the overplayed dichotomies in end-of-life care. And secondly, it questions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  22
    Coercion as temptation.Dan Lyons - 1986 - Journal of Social Philosophy 17 (3):35-41.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. The Ethics of Coercion and Other Forms of Influence.Kelso Cratsley - 2019 - In Şerife Tekin & Robyn Bluhm (eds.), The Bloomsbury Companion to Philosophy of Psychiatry. London: Bloomsbury. pp. 283-304.
    Across the health sector there is increased recognition of the ethical significance of interventions that constrain or coerce. Much of the recent interest stems from debates in public health over the use of quarantines and active monitoring in response to epidemics, as well as the manipulation of information in the service of health promotion (or ‘nudges’). But perhaps the area in which these issues remain most pressing is mental health, where the spectre of involuntary treatment has always loomed large. Indeed, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  41
    Beyond Coercion: Moral Assessment in the Labour Market.Dan Munter & Lars Lindblom - 2017 - Journal of Business Ethics 142 (1):59-70.
    Some libertarians argue that informed consent alone makes transactions in the labour market morally justified. In contrast, some of their critics claim that such an act of consent is no guarantee against coercion. To know whether agreements are voluntary, we need to assess the quality of the offers or the prevailing background conditions. ISCT theorists argue that it is imperative to take social norms into account when evaluating the labour market. We present a novel framework for moral assessment (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  52
    The Fiction of Economic Coercion: Political Marxism and the Separation of Theory and History.Sébastien Rioux - 2013 - Historical Materialism 21 (4):92-128.
    The theory of social-property relations, or political Marxism, has argued that in contradistinction with pre-capitalist forms of exploitation, capitalism is characterised by the separation of the economic and the political, which makes surplus appropriation under this system uniquely driven by economic coercion. In spite of political Marxism’s various strengths, this article argues that the paradigm puts forward an ahistorical and sanitised conception of capitalism typical of bourgeois economics, which is an outcome of its formal-abstractionist approach to the concept (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  46.  23
    Coercion and Distributive Justice: A Defense.Douglas Paul MacKay - 2016 - Journal of Social Philosophy 47 (2):211-230.
  47.  55
    Public Reason and Structural Coercion.Baldwin Wong - 2020 - Social Theory and Practice 46 (1):231-255.
    Political liberals usually assume the coercion account, which argues that state actions should be publicly justified because they coerce citizens. Recently some critics object this account for it overlooks that some policies are non-coercive but still require public justification. My article argues that, instead of understanding coercion as particular laws or policies, it should be understood as the exercise of collective political power that shapes the basic structure. This revised coercion account explains why those ostensibly non-coercive policies (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48.  24
    Coercion, Legitimacy, and Equality.Jon Mandle - 2006 - Social Theory and Practice 32 (4):617-625.
  49.  15
    Liberty, coercion, and the limits of the state.Alan Wertheimer - 2002 - In Robert L. Simon (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Social and Political Philosophy. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 38–59.
    The prelims comprise: Liberty and Coercion Liberty‐Limiting Principles The Harm Principle The Offense Principle Legal Paternalism Legal Moralism Justice Need Conclusion Bibliography.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  50.  11
    Kant, coercion, and the legitimation of inequality.Benjamin L. McKean - 2022 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 25 (4):528-550.
1 — 50 / 978