Results for 'Peter Rule'

979 found
Order:
  1.  21
    Dialogue, Horizon and Chronotope: Using Bakhtin’s and Gadamer’s Ideas to Frame Online Teaching and Learning.Peter Rule - 2024 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 43 (3):305-323.
    The information explosion and digital modes of learning often combine to inform the quest for the best ways of transforming information in digital form for pedagogical purposes. This quest has become more urgent and pervasive with the ‘turn’ to online learning in the context of COVID-19. This can result in linear, asynchronous, transmission-based modes of teaching and learning which commodify, package and deliver knowledge for individual ‘customers’. The primary concerns in such models are often technical and economic – technology as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  16
    The pedagogy of Jesus in the parable of the Good Samaritan: A diacognitive analysis.Peter N. Rule - 2017 - HTS Theological Studies 73 (3).
    Jesus of Nazareth, like Socrates, left nothing behind written by himself. Yet, the records of his teaching indicate a rich interest in dialogic pedagogy, reflected in his use of the parable, primarily an oral genre, as a dialogic provocation. Working at the interface of pedagogy, theology and philosophy, this article explores the parable of the Good Samaritan from the perspective of dialogic pedagogy. It employs an analytical approach termed diacognition, developed from the notions of dialogue, position and cognition, to analyse (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3. Bakhtin and Freire: Dialogue, dialectic and boundary learning.Peter Rule - 2011 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 43 (9):924-942.
    Dialogue is a seminal concept within the work of the Brazilian adult education theorist, Paulo Freire, and the Russian literary critic and philosopher, Mikhail Bakhtin. While there are commonalities in their understanding of dialogue, they differ in their treatment of dialectic. This paper addresses commonalities and dissonances within a Bakhtin-Freire dialogue on the notions of dialogue and dialectic. It then teases out some of the implications for education theory and practice in relation to two South African contexts of learning that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  48
    Reviews. [REVIEW]Paul Rule, Patrick Hutchings, Reg Naulty, Joseph LaPorte, Purushottama Bilimoria, Renee Abbott, Peter Kakol, Rob Harle & V. L. Krishnamoorthy - 1999 - Sophia 38 (1):122-166.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  5
    The Rule of Law and Jury Trials.Raymond Peters - 2023 - Stance 16 (1):72-83.
    In The Rule of Law in the Real World, Paul Gowder presents a new account of the rule of law based on three conditions: publicity, regularity, and generality. In this essay, I examine two closely related questions that are prompted by Gowder’s version of the rule of law. First, does the rule of law require citizens to follow the law? Second, what does Gowder’s account mean for jury nullification? I argue that the rule of law (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  41
    General Rules of Language.Peter Zinkernagel - 1959 - Theoria 25 (1):56-64.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Science rules: a historical introduction to scientific methods.Peter Achinstein (ed.) - 2004 - Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
  8.  9
    A Meaningful Mathematical First Order Language: Partial Peano Algebras and Rule Systems.Peter Zahn - 1989 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 35 (2):155-168.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Rules of Meaning and Practical Reasoning.Peter Pagin - 1998 - Synthese 117 (2):207 - 227.
    Can there be rules of language which serve both to determine meaning and to guide speakers in ordinary linguistic usage, i.e., in the production of speech acts? We argue that the answer is no. We take the guiding function of rules to be the function of serving as reasons for actions, and the question of guidance is then considered within the framework of practical reasoning. It turns out that those rules that can serve as reasons for linguistic utterances cannot be (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  10.  77
    The Rule of Law Beyond Thick and Thin.Peter Rijpkema - 2013 - Law and Philosophy 32 (6):793-816.
    In this paper it is argued that different understandings of the requirements of the Rule of Law can to a large extent be explained by the position taken with regard to two interrelated distinctions. On the one hand, the Rule of Law can be regarded as either a principle of law or as a principle of governance. On the other hand, the requirements of the Rule of Law can be regarded as defining either a minimum standard which (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  44
    Comparative narratives: Some rules for the study of action.Peter Abell - 1984 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 14 (3):309–331.
    The paper explores the concept of a Narrative which is defined as a connected structure on a set of constrained actions and forbearances. Explanation via Narratives is compared with explanation through variable centred methodology and an interpretation of correlations in terms of Narratives is also outlined.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  61
    Two rules of legality in criminal law.Peter Westen - 2006 - Law and Philosophy 26 (3):229-305.
    Criminal law scholars approach legality in various ways. Some scholars eschew over-arching principles and proceed directly to one or more distinct “rules”: (1) the rule against retroactive criminalization; (2) the rule that criminal statutes be construed narrowly; (3) the rule against the judicial creation of common-law offenses; and (4) the rule that vague criminal statutes are void. Other scholars seek a single principle, i.e., the “principle of legality,” that they claim underlies the four rules. In contrast, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  13.  24
    Wittgenstein: Rules, Grammar and Necessity.Peter Carruthers - 1988 - Philosophical Quarterly 38 (150):131-134.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  14. Classical harmony: Rules of inference and the meaning of the logical constants.Peter Milne - 1994 - Synthese 100 (1):49 - 94.
    The thesis that, in a system of natural deduction, the meaning of a logical constant is given by some or all of its introduction and elimination rules has been developed recently in the work of Dummett, Prawitz, Tennant, and others, by the addition of harmony constraints. Introduction and elimination rules for a logical constant must be in harmony. By deploying harmony constraints, these authors have arrived at logics no stronger than intuitionist propositional logic. Classical logic, they maintain, cannot be justified (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  15.  42
    Evidence and Method: Scientific Strategies of Isaac Newton and James Clerk Maxwell.Peter Achinstein - 2013 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    In this book, Peter Achinstein proposes and defends several objective concepts of evidence. He then explores the question of whether a scientific method, such as that represented in the four "Rules for the Study of Natural Philosophy" that Isaac Newton invoked in proving his law of gravity, can be employed in demonstrating how the proposed definitions of evidence are to be applied to real scientific cases.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  16.  82
    The Rule of Metaphor: Multi-Disciplinary Studies of the Creation of Meaning in Language.Peter Lamarque - 1979 - Philosophical Quarterly 29 (115):188-190.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  17. Scepticism, Rules and Language.Gordon P. Baker & Peter Michael Stephan Hacker - 1984 - [New York]: Blackwell. Edited by P. M. S. Hacker.
  18.  71
    Rules and similarity processes in artificial grammar and natural second language learning: What is the “default”?Peter Robinson - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (1):32-33.
    Are rules processes or similarity processes the default for acquisition of grammatical knowledge during natural second language acquisition? Whereas Pothos argues similarity processes are the default in the many areas he reviews, including artificial grammar learning and first language development, I suggest, citing evidence, that in second language acquisition of grammatical morphology “rules processes” may be the default.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  31
    Rules and Representations.Peter Lamarque - 1982 - Philosophical Quarterly 32 (127):180-181.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  20.  39
    Is Moral Perception Essentially Rule-Governed? A Critical Assessment of Generalism and a Limited Defense of Particularism.Peter Shiu-Hwa Tsu - 2021 - Critica 52 (156).
    Moral perception, for the purposes of this article, is taken to be the perception of moral properties, unless contexts dictate otherwise. While both particularists and generalists agree that we can perceive the moral properties of an action or a feature, they disagree, however, over whether rules play any essential role in moral perception. The particularists argue for a ‘no’ answer, whereas the generalists say ‘yes’. In this paper, I provide a limited defense of particularism by rebutting several powerful generalist arguments. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  16
    Turn-allocation and gaze: A multimodal revision of the “current-speaker-selects-next” rule of the turn-taking system of conversation analysis.Peter Auer - 2021 - Discourse Studies 23 (2):117-140.
    It is argued in this paper that a multimodal analysis of turn-taking, one of the core areas of conversation analytic research, is needed and has to integrate gaze as one of the most central resources for allocating turns, and that new technologies are available that can provide a solid and reliable empirical foundation for this analysis. On the basis of eye-tracking data of spontaneous conversations, it is shown that gaze is the most ubiquitous next-speaker-selection technique. It can function alone or (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  17
    The Discourses of Identity in Hellenistic Erythrai: Institutions, Rhetoric, Honour and Reciprocity.Peter Liddel - 2021 - Polis 38 (1):74-107.
    Recent research in the field of New Institutionalist analysis has developed the view that institutions are grounded not only upon authoritative rules but also upon accepted practices and narratives. In this paper I am interested in the ways in which honorific practices and accounts of identity set out in ancient Greek inscriptions contribute towards the persistence of polis institutions in the Hellenistic period. A diachronic survey of Erythraian inscriptions of the classical and Hellenistic periods gives an impression of the adaptation (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Ruling-out realism.Peter Carruthers - 1985 - Philosophia 15 (1-2):61-78.
    The case for anti-realism in the theory of meaning, as presented by Dummen and Wright, 1 is only partly convincing. There is, I shall suggest, a crucial lacuna in the argument, that can only be filled by the later Wittgenstein's following-a-rule considerations. So it is the latter that provides the strongest argument for the rejection of semantic realism.
    By 'realism', throughout, I should be taken as referring to any conception of meaning that leaves open the possibility that a sentence may (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Rule-following, compositionality and the normativity of meaning.Peter Pagin - 2002 - In D. Prawitz (ed.), Meaning and Interpretation. Konferenser.
    However, if Wittgenstein’s so called rule-following considerations are correct, then this reason for believing in the validity of (C), is mistaken. The conclusion of those considerations is that we must reject the idea that rules are things which determine possible cases of application before those cases are actually encountered and decided by speakers. If this is right, then there is no rule which determines the meanings of new sentences, i.e. before those sentences have actually been used. Therefore, it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  25. Ethics for Drone Operators: Rules versus Virtues.Peter Olsthoorn - 2021 - In Christian Enemark (ed.), Ethics of Drone Violence: Restraining Remote-Control Killing. Eup.
    Until recently most militaries tended to see moral issues through the lens of rules and regulations. Today, however, many armed forces consider teaching virtues to be an important complement to imposing rules and codes from above. A closer look reveals that it is mainly established military virtues such as honour, courage and loyalty that dominate both the lists of virtues and values of most militaries and the growing body of literature on military virtues. Although there is evidently still a role (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Discovery and rule-books.Peter Achinstein - 1980 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 34 (1):109.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27.  3
    Myth and Investigation in Oedipus Rex.Peter T. Koper - 2005 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 12 (1):87-98.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Myth and Investigation in Oedipus RexPeter T. Koper (bio)René Girard's rich interpretations of Attic drama include his discussion in Violence and the Sacred of the sacrificial and reciprocal nature of the mythic violence that underlies Oedipus Rex. "In the myth, the fearful transgression of a single individual is substituted for the universal onslaught of reciprocal violence. Oedipus is responsible for the ills that have befallen his people" (Girard 1977, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  93
    A priori rules: Wittgenstein on the normativity of logic.Peter Railton - 2000 - In Paul Artin Boghossian & Christopher Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 170--96.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  29.  19
    Model of conditioning incorporating the Rescorla-Wagner associative axiom, a dynamic attention process, and a catastrophe rule.Peter W. Frey & Ronald J. Sears - 1978 - Psychological Review 85 (4):321-340.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  30.  29
    The discontinuity between rules and similarity.Peter F. Dominey - 2005 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (1):22-23.
    In arguing for a rules-similarity continuum, Pothos should demonstrate that a single process or mechanism (a neural network model, for example) can handle the entire continuum. Pothos deliberately avoids this exercise as beyond the scope of the current research. In this context, I will present simulation, neuropsychological, neurophysiological, and experimental psychological results, arguing against the continuity hypothesis.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  66
    Rule Following, Rule Scepticism and Indeterminacy in Law: A Conventional Account.Peter Drahos & Stephen Parker - 1992 - Ratio Juris 5 (1):109-119.
  32.  30
    Rules, roles and relations.Peter Winch - 1967 - Philosophical Books 8 (2):11-13.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  34
    Goodman's paradox and rules of acceptance.Peter M. Williams - 1969 - Philosophy of Science 36 (3):311-315.
    The purpose of this note is to examine the claim made by Howard Smokler that “Goodman's paradox should be considered as an independent argument against a conception of inductive logic which makes use of rules of acceptance”.Smokler's claim arises from his treatment of Goodman's paradox in the form given it by Israel Scheffler. Schefflerhas discussed this paradox primarily in the context of a methodology of induction which views inductive rules as rules of acceptance permitting one to assert detached conclusions. The (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Metaphysics.Peter Adamson - 2007 - In Al-Kindī. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter deals with al-Kindī’s metaphysics, which in this context means theology and the idea that being is an emanation or creation from God. Depending on the Neoplatonists, especially Proclus, al-Kindī proves God’s existence by arguing for the need for a “true One”, whose absolute simplicity rules out a multiplicity of divine attributes.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  38
    Labor Rules: D'Accord? A Response to Chilla Bulbeck.Peter Beilharz - 1986 - Thesis Eleven 14 (1):106-108.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Covid rule breakers and the social contract.Peter R. Anstey - 2023 - In Evandro Barbosa (ed.), Moral Challenges in a Pandemic Age. Routledge. pp. 192–203.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Excuse validation: a study in rule-breaking.John Turri & Peter Blouw - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (3):615-634.
    Can judging that an agent blamelessly broke a rule lead us to claim, paradoxically, that no rule was broken at all? Surprisingly, it can. Across seven experiments, we document and explain the phenomenon of excuse validation. We found when an agent blamelessly breaks a rule, it significantly distorts people’s description of the agent’s conduct. Roughly half of people deny that a rule was broken. The results suggest that people engage in excuse validation in order to avoid (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  38. The Brier Rule Is not a Good Measure of Epistemic Utility.Don Fallis & Peter J. Lewis - 2016 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (3):576-590.
    Measures of epistemic utility are used by formal epistemologists to make determinations of epistemic betterness among cognitive states. The Brier rule is the most popular choice among formal epistemologists for such a measure. In this paper, however, we show that the Brier rule is sometimes seriously wrong about whether one cognitive state is epistemically better than another. In particular, there are cases where an agent gets evidence that definitively eliminates a false hypothesis, but where the Brier rule (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  39.  71
    Having Linguistic Rules and Knowing Linguistic Facts.Peter Ludlow - 209 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 5:8.
    'Knowledge' doesn't correctly describe our relation to linguistic rules. It is too thick a notion. On the other hand, 'cognize', without further elaboration, is too thin a notion, which is to say that it is too thin to play a role in a competence theory. One advantage of the term 'knowledge'-and presumably Chomsky's original motivation for using it-is that knowledge would play the right kind of role in a competence theory: Our competence would consist in a body of knowledge which (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  14
    Ruling Elites and Decision-Making in Fascist-Era Dictatorships.Peter Monteath - 2013 - The European Legacy 18 (4):519-520.
  41.  7
    Moralities, Rule Choice, and the Universal Legislator.Peter Murphy - 1983 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 50.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  33
    Rules, Norms, and Commitment.Fabienne Peter & Kai Spiekermann - 2011 - In Ian Jarvie & Jesus Zamora-Bonilla (eds.), Handbook of Philosophy of Social Science. Sage Publications. pp. 216--232.
  43.  27
    Scepticism and conditions for description.Peter Zinkernagel - 1968 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 11 (1-4):190 – 204.
    Conditions for description are general rules to which language must conform if it is to serve descriptive purposes. It is argued that the existence of such rules renders scepticism about them incoherent. The only way we can decide whether or not there are such conditions is by seeing in practice whether or not there are certain rules such that we cannot in fact break them without making language unfit for describing. The case is similar to that of, e.g., the law (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Isolation, Assurance and Rules: Can Rational Folly Supplant Foolish Rationality?Peter Hammond - 2008 - In Kaushik Basu & Ravi Kanbur (eds.), Arguments for a Better World: Essays in Honor of Amartya Sen: Volume I: Ethics, Welfare, and Measurement and Volume Ii: Society, Institutions, and Development. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. Behind the Mechitsa: Reflections on The Rules of Textual Reasoning.Peter Ochs - 2002 - Journal of Textual Reasoning 1 (1):43pp..
    After twelve years of productive work, the Society for Textual Reasoning has reason to reflect on the rules of reasoning it has nurtured and tested but has not yet adopted, self-consciously, as the rules of its textual reasoning . This essay illustrates some ways of reflecting on these rules. The first section of the essay presents a brief history of STR. The following section, the focal section of the essay, illustrates the rules of TR as displayed in a recent internet (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  33
    Rules for Fighting in the Culture Wars.Peter Kreeft - 2004 - The Chesterton Review 30 (1/2):175-180.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Why Machines Won't Rule the World. [REVIEW]Peter Gärdenfors - 2024 - Sans 2.
    This is a review of Jobst Landgrebe and Barry Smith, Why Machines Will Neve Rule the World (Routledge, 2023).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  99
    Banning the Former Ruling Party.Peter Niesen - 2012 - Constellations 19 (4):540-561.
  49.  3
    Truth, Survival, and Power.Peter Poellner - 1995 - In Nietzsche and metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    In contrast with views that attribute the biological utility of beliefs to their truth, Nietzsche maintains that their relative utility renders them proportionately more likely to be idiosyncratic expressions of species‐relative concerns. Nietzsche's sceptical ‘argument from utility’—the inference from the practical utility of beliefs to the improbability of their being metaphysically true—is examined and rejected. It is argued that Nietzsche is an early proponent of naturalized epistemology. His objections to the ‘best explanation’ defence of metaphysical realism are discussed. It emerges (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  15
    Gowder, Paul. The Rule of Law in the Real World.New York: Cambridge University Press, 2016. Pp. xii+275. $34.99.Peter Rijpkema - 2017 - Ethics 127 (2):486-491.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 979