Results for ' “judgement,” “deduction,” “abstraction,”'

995 found
Order:
  1.  9
    Judgement and Sense in Modern French Philosophy: A New Reading of Six Thinkers by Henry Somers-Hall.Clayton Crockett - 2022 - Review of Metaphysics 76 (2):365-367.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Judgement and Sense in Modern French Philosophy: A New Reading of Six Thinkers by Henry Somers-HallClayton CrockettSOMERS-HALL, Henry. Judgement and Sense in Modern French Philosophy: A New Reading of Six Thinkers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2022. 264 pp. Cloth, $99.99Henry Somers-Hall's book examines how French philosophers in the twentieth century develop a logic of thinking based on sense that is both influenced by but also counters Kant's paradigm (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  7
    Judgment, Role in Science.Harold I. Brown - 2017 - In W. H. Newton‐Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 194–202.
    According to a widely held view of science, scientific hypotheses are evaluated on the basis of observational data in accordance with the rules of inductive logic. Inductive logic, like deductive logic, is supposed to consist of a set of formal rules. These rules abstract from any details of the specific hypothesis under examination, the context in which the evaluation is taking place, and the individuals who carry out the evaluation. Observational data are also independent of the context or the observer (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  50
    Concepts, judgments, and unity in Kant's metaphysical deduction of the relational categories.Charles Nussbaum - 1990 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (1):89.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Concepts, Judgments, and Unity in Kant's Metaphysical Deduction of the Relational Categories CHARLES NUSSBAUM 1. INTRODUCTION TO ANY ATTENTIVEREADERof the section of the Critique of Pure Reason' known as the "Metaphysical Deduction of the Categories" (A67/B92-A83/B to9), one paragraph in that section stands out particularly by virtue of its special importance for Kant's developing argument: The same function Which gives unity to the various representations in ajudgment also gives (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  77
    Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment (review). [REVIEW]Paul Guyer - 2002 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (3):406-408.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 40.3 (2002) 406-408 [Access article in PDF] Book Review Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment Henry E. Allison. Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001. Pp. xvi + 424. Cloth, $69.95. Paper, $24.95. In his new book, Henry Allison provides a study of the two introductions (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  9
    Believing at Will.Kieran Setiya - 1981 - In Felicia Ackerman (ed.), Midwest Studies in Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. pp. 36–52.
    This chapter contains sections titled: I II III IV References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. Normalization theorems for substructural logics in Gentzen-style natural deduction, abstract of the talk at 2000 Annual Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, June 3‐7, 2000. [REVIEW]O. Watari, K. Nakatogawa & T. Ueno - 2000 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):390-391.
  7.  48
    Natural Deduction for Modal Logic of Judgment Aggregation.Tin Perkov - 2016 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 25 (3-4):335-354.
    We can formalize judgments as logical formulas. Judgment aggregation deals with judgments of several agents, which need to be aggregated to a collective judgment. There are several logical formalizations of judgment aggregation. This paper focuses on a modal formalization which nicely expresses classical properties of judgment aggregation rules and famous results of social choice theory, like Arrow’s impossibility theorem. A natural deduction system for modal logic of judgment aggregation is presented in this paper. The system is sound and complete. As (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Reflective Judgment and the Application of Logic to Nature: Kant's Deduction of the Principle of Purposiveness as an Answer to Hume.Henry E. Allison - 2003 - In Hans-Johann Glock (ed.), Strawson and Kant. Oxford University Press.
  9.  15
    The Deductions in the Critique of Judgment: Comments on Hampshire and Horstmann.Reinhard Brandt - 1988 - In Eckart Förster (ed.), Kant’s Transcendental Deductions: The Three ‘Critiques’ and the ‘Opus Postumum’. Stanford University Press. pp. 177-190.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  17
    Categorical abstract algebraic logic: The criterion for deductive equivalence.George Voutsadakis - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (4):347-352.
    Equivalent deductive systems were introduced in [4] with the goal of treating 1-deductive systems and algebraic 2-deductive systems in a uniform way. Results of [3], appropriately translated and strengthened, show that two deductive systems over the same language type are equivalent if and only if their lattices of theories are isomorphic via an isomorphism that commutes with substitutions. Deductive equivalence of π-institutions [14, 15] generalizes the notion of equivalence of deductive systems. In [15, Theorem 10.26] this criterion for the equivalence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. The Conclusion of the Deduction of Taste in the Dialectic of Aesthetic Power of Judgment in Kant.Manuel Sánchez Rodríguez - 2013 - Trans/Form/Ação 36 (2):45-62.
    In this paper, it is argued that only in the section on dialectic in the Critique of Judgment does Kant reach a definitive and conclusive version of deduction, after discovering the concept of the supersensible. In the section on the deduction of pure aesthetic judgments, Kant does not satisfactorily explain the critical distinction between the sensible nature of humanity and the supersensible nature of human reason presupposed in the concept of universal communicability. While the concept of the supersensible illustrates this (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  24
    Categorical abstract algebraic logic: Gentzen π ‐institutions and the deduction‐detachment property.George Voutsadakis - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (6):570-578.
    Given a π -institution I , a hierarchy of π -institutions I is constructed, for n ≥ 1. We call I the n-th order counterpart of I . The second-order counterpart of a deductive π -institution is a Gentzen π -institution, i.e. a π -institution associated with a structural Gentzen system in a canonical way. So, by analogy, the second order counterpart I of I is also called the “Gentzenization” of I . In the main result of the paper, it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  6
    Judgement, Self-Consciousness, and Imagination: Kant’s Transcendental Deduction and Beyond.Paul Crowther - 1998 - In Herman Parret (ed.), Kants Ästhetik · Kant's Aesthetics · L'esthétique de Kant. New York: De Gruyter. pp. 117-135.
  14.  1
    Categorical abstract algebraic logic: The criterion for deductive equivalence: The criterion for deductive equivalence.George Voutsadakis - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (4):347.
    Equivalent deductive systems were introduced in [4] with the goal of treating 1‐deductive systems and algebraic 2‐deductive systems in a uniform way. Results of [3], appropriately translated and strengthened, show that two deductive systems over the same language type are equivalent if and only if their lattices of theories are isomorphic via an isomorphism that commutes with substitutions. Deductive equivalence of π‐institutions [14, 15] generalizes the notion of equivalence of deductive systems. In [15, Theorem 10.26] this criterion for the equivalence (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  31
    Generalizing abstraction and the judgment of subsumption in Aron Gurwitsch's version of Husserl's theory of intentionality.Gilbert T. Null - 1978 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 38 (4):469-488.
  16.  92
    The conclusion of the deduction of taste in the dialectic of the power of judgment aesthetic in Kant.Manuel Sánchez - 2013 - Trans/Form/Ação 36 (2):45-62.
    In this paper, it is argued that only in the section on dialectic in the Critique of Judgment does Kant reach a definitive and conclusive version of deduction, after discovering the concept of the supersensible. In the section on the deduction of pure aesthetic judgments, Kant does not satisfactorily explain the critical distinction between the sensible nature of humanity and the supersensible nature of human reason presupposed in the concept of universal communicability. While the concept of the supersensible illustrates this (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  3
    Experience and Judgement: The Metaphysical Deduction.Anthony Savile - 2005 - In Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: An Orientation to the Central Theme. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 33–47.
    This chapter contains section titled: The Metaphysical Deduction.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  14
    Discussion: Judgment as "the collective becoming abstract.".A. H. Lloyd - 1894 - Psychological Review 1 (3):283-285.
  19. Syntactical learning and judgment, still unconscious and still abstract: Comment on Dulany, Carlson, and Dewey.Arthur S. Reber, Robert F. Allen & S. Regan - 1985 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 114:17-24.
  20. Judgement aggregation under constraints.Franz Dietrich & Christian List - 2008 - In Thomas A. Boylan & Ruvin Gekker (eds.), Economics, Rational Choice and Normative Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 111-123.
    In solving judgment aggregation problems, groups often face constraints. Many decision problems can be modelled in terms the acceptance or rejection of certain propositions in a language, and constraints as propositions that the decisions should be consistent with. For example, court judgments in breach-of-contract cases should be consistent with the constraint that action and obligation are necessary and sufficient for liability; judgments on how to rank several options in an order of preference with the constraint of transitivity; and judgments on (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21.  23
    Is Kant's Deduction of Judgement of Taste Free from the Two Criticisms Raised about It?Ji Young Kang - 2019 - Journal of the Society of Philosophical Studies 60:43-73.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  25
    Heterogeneous Fibring of Deductive Systems Via Abstract Proof Systems.Luis Cruz-Filipe, Amílcar Sernadas & Cristina Sernadas - 2008 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 16 (2):121-153.
    Fibring is a meta-logical constructor that applied to two logics produces a new logic whose formulas allow the mixing of symbols. Homogeneous fibring assumes that the original logics are presented in the same way . Heterogeneous fibring, allowing the original logics to have different presentations , has been an open problem. Herein, consequence systems are shown to be a good solution for heterogeneous fibring when one of the logics is presented in a semantic way and the other by a calculus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  19
    Kant's Deduction of the Principle of Reflective Judgement.Stale R. S. Finke - 2001 - In Ralph Schumacher, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Volker Gerhardt (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des Ix. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Bd. I: Hauptvorträge. Bd. Ii: Sektionen I-V. Bd. Iii: Sektionen Vi-X: Bd. Iv: Sektionen Xi-Xiv. Bd. V: Sektionen Xv-Xviii. New York: De Gruyter. pp. 737-747.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Concepts of Objects as Prescribing Laws: A Kantian and Pragmatist Line of Thought.James O'Shea - 2016 - In Robert Stern and Gabriele Gava, eds., Pragmatism, Kant, and Transcendental Philosophy (London: Routledge): pp. 196–216. London, UK: pp. 196-216.
    Abstract: This paper traces a Kantian and pragmatist line of thinking that connects the ideas of conceptual content, object cognition, and modal constraints in the form of counterfactual sustaining causal laws. It is an idea that extends from Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason through C. I. Lewis’s Mind and the World-Order to the Kantian naturalism of Wilfrid Sellars and the analytic pragmatism of Robert Brandom. Kant put forward what I characterize as a modal conception of objectivity, which he developed as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25. Judgment aggregation without full rationality.Franz Dietrich & Christian List - 2008 - Social Choice and Welfare 31:15-39.
    Several recent results on the aggregation of judgments over logically connected propositions show that, under certain conditions, dictatorships are the only propositionwise aggregation functions generating fully rational (i.e., complete and consistent) collective judgments. A frequently mentioned route to avoid dictatorships is to allow incomplete collective judgments. We show that this route does not lead very far: we obtain oligarchies rather than dictatorships if instead of full rationality we merely require that collective judgments be deductively closed, arguably a minimal condition of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  26. A case of syntactical learning and judgment: How conscious and how abstract?Donelson E. Dulany, Richard A. Carlson & G. I. Dewey - 1984 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 113:541-555.
  27.  16
    Corrigendum to “Categorical abstract algebraic logic: The criterion for deductive equivalence”.George Voutsadakis - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (6):644-644.
    We give a correction to the paper [2] mentioned in the title.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  2
    Law’s Abstract Judgement (LAJ) and Intelligent Fidelity: On William Lucy’s Law’s Judgement.Imer B. Flores - 2019 - Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoria Del Derecho:33-54.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Constructivism and Practical Reason: On Intersubjectivity, Abstraction, and Judgment.Miriam Ronzoni - 2010 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (1):74-104.
    The article offers an account of the constructivist methodology in ethics and political philosophy as 1) deriving from an agnostic moral ontology and 2) proposing intersubjective justifiability as the criterion of justification for normative principles. It then asks whether constructivism, conceived in this way, can respond to the challenge of “content skepticism about practical reason”, namely whether it can provide sufficiently precise normative guidance whilst remaining faithful to its methodological commitment. The paper critically examines to alternative way of meeting this (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  30.  21
    Why Must There Be a Transcendental Deduction in Kant's Critique of Judgment?Rolf-Peter Horstmann - 1988 - In Eckart Förster (ed.), Kant’s Transcendental Deductions: The Three ‘Critiques’ and the ‘Opus Postumum’. Stanford University Press. pp. 157-176.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  31.  53
    From applied ethics to empirical ethics to contextual ethics.Barry Hoffmaster - 2017 - Bioethics 32 (2):119-125.
    Bioethics became applied ethics when it was assimilated to moral philosophy. Because deduction is the rationality of moral philosophy, subsuming facts under moral principles to deduce conclusions about what ought to be done became the prescribed reasoning of bioethics, and bioethics became a theory comprised of moral principles. Bioethicists now realize that applied ethics is too abstract and spare to apprehend the specificity, particularity, complexity and contingency of real moral issues. Empirical ethics and contextual ethics are needed to incorporate these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32.  21
    Systematicity and Symbolisation in Kant's Deduction of Judgements of Taste.Alexander Rueger - 2011 - Hegel Bulletin 32 (1-2):232-251.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Judgment aggregation with consistency alone.Franz Dietrich & Christian List - 2007 - Maastricht University.
    All existing impossibility theorems on judgment aggregation require individual and collective judgment sets to be consistent and complete, arguably a demanding rationality requirement. They do not carry over to aggregation functions mapping profiles of consistent individual judgment sets to consistent collective ones. We prove that, whenever the agenda of propositions under consideration exhibits mild interconnections, any such aggregation function that is "neutral" between the acceptance and rejection of each proposition is dictatorial. We relate this theorem to the literature.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  34. Signs as Means for Discoveries. Peirce and His Concepts of 'Diagrammatic Reasoning,' 'Theorematic Deduction,' 'Hypostatic Abstraction,' and 'Theoric Transformation'.Michael H. G. Hoffmann - 1996 - In Das Problem der Zukunft im Rahmen holistischer Ethiken. Im Ausgang von Platon und Peirce. Edition Tertium.
    The paper aims to show how by elaborating the Peircean terms used in the title creativity in learning processes and in scientific discoveries can be explained within a semiotic framework. The essential idea is to emphasize both the role of external representations and of experimenting with those representations , and to describe a process consisting of three steps: First, looking at diagrams "from a novel point of view" offers opportunities to synthesize elements of these diagrams which have never been perceived (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35.  28
    Doing ‘judgemental rationality’ in empirical research: the importance of depth-reflexivity when researching in prison.Matthew L. N. Wilkinson, Mallory Schneuwly Purdie, Lamia Irfan & Muzammil Quraishi - 2022 - Journal of Critical Realism 21 (1):25-45.
    ABSTRACT Critical realist thought has theorised convincingly that epistemic relativism is constellationally embedded in ontological realism which in turn necessitates judgemental rationality. In social science, judgemental rationality involves acting upon plausible decisions about competing points of view. However, the tools for doing this are, as yet, under-articulated. This paper addresses this absence by articulating triangulation and depth-reflexivity as two tools for doing judgemental rationality in empirical research. It draws on the experiences of a diverse team working on an international comparative (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36. Suspended judgment.Jane Friedman - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 162 (2):165-181.
    Abstract In this paper I undertake an in-depth examination of an oft mentioned but rarely expounded upon state: suspended judgment. While traditional epistemology is sometimes characterized as presenting a “yes or no” picture of its central attitudes, in fact many of these epistemologists want to say that there is a third option: subjects can also suspend judgment. Discussions of suspension are mostly brief and have been less than clear on a number of issues, in particular whether this third option should (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   188 citations  
  37.  43
    Categorical Abstract Algebraic Logic: Models of π-Institutions.George Voutsadakis - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (4):439-460.
    An important part of the theory of algebraizable sentential logics consists of studying the algebraic semantics of these logics. As developed by Czelakowski, Blok, and Pigozzi and Font and Jansana, among others, it includes studying the properties of logical matrices serving as models of deductive systems and the properties of abstract logics serving as models of sentential logics. The present paper contributes to the development of the categorical theory by abstracting some of these model theoretic aspects and results from the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  38.  49
    Automated deduction in a graphical temporal logic.L. E. Moser, P. M. Melliar-Smith, Y. S. Ramakrishna, G. Kutty & L. K. Dillon - 1996 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 6 (1):29-47.
    ABSTRACT Real-time graphical interval logic is a modal logic for reasoning about time in which the basic modality is the interval. The logic differs from other logics in that it has a natural intuitive graphical representation that resembles the timing diagrams drawn by system designers. We have developed an automted deduction system for the logic, which includes a theorem prover and a user interface. The theorem prover checks the validity of proofs in the logic and produces counterexamples to invalid proofs. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  12
    Hegel's Concept of Life: Self-Consciousness, Freedom, Logic by Karen Ng (review).Marina F. Bykova - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (3):527-528.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Hegel's Concept of Life: Self-Consciousness, Freedom, Logic by Karen NgMarina F. BykovaKaren Ng. Hegel's Concept of Life: Self-Consciousness, Freedom, Logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020. Pp. iii + 319. Hardback, $85.00.In her insightful book, Karen Ng defends the fundamental significance of Hegel's concept of life, which she considers "constitutive" not merely of his dynamic account of reason but also of his "idealist program" itself (3–4), the very core (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  8
    The Place of the Logical Functions of Judgment in Kant's Logic and its Significance in the Deductions of the Categories.Robert Greenberg - 2001 - In Ralph Schumacher, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Volker Gerhardt (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des Ix. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Bd. I: Hauptvorträge. Bd. Ii: Sektionen I-V. Bd. Iii: Sektionen Vi-X: Bd. Iv: Sektionen Xi-Xiv. Bd. V: Sektionen Xv-Xviii. New York: De Gruyter. pp. 298-304.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  33
    Natural Deduction: An Introduction to Logic with Real Arguments, a Little History and Some Humour.Richard T. W. Arthur - 2011 - Peterborough, Ontario, Canada: Broadview Press.
    Richard Arthur’s _Natural Deduction_ provides a wide-ranging introduction to logic. In lively and readable prose, Arthur presents a new approach to the study of logic, one that seeks to integrate methods of argument analysis developed in modern “informal logic” with natural deduction techniques. The dry bones of logic are given flesh by unusual attention to the history of the subject, from Pythagoras, the Stoics, and Indian Buddhist logic, through Lewis Carroll, Venn, and Boole, to Russell, Frege, and Monty Python.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  34
    Deduction Difficulties.Robert Howell - 2018 - Kantian Review 23 (1):111-121.
    I argue, contrary to Dennis Schulting inKant’s Radical Subjectivism, that the main reasoning of Kant’s transcendental deduction of the categories is progressive, not regressive. Schulting is right, however, to emphasize that the deduction takes the object cognized to be constituted in an idealism-entailing way. But his reasoning has gaps and bypasses Kant’s most explicit deduction argument, independent of the Transcendental Aesthetic, for idealism. Finally, Schulting’s claim that Kantian discursivity itself requires idealism overlooks the fact that Kantian general judgements can be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  24
    Deduction Theorem in Congruential Modal Logics.Krzysztof A. Krawczyk - 2023 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 64 (2):185-196.
    We present an algebraic proof of the theorem stating that there are continuum many axiomatic extensions of global consequence associated with modal system E that do not admit the local deduction detachment theorem. We also prove that all these logics lack the finite frame property and have exactly three proper axiomatic extensions, each of which admits the local deduction detachment theorem.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Infinite Judgements and Transcendental Logic.Ekin Erkan, Anna Longo & Madeleine Collier - 2020 - Cosmos and History : The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy 20 (2):391-415.
    The infinite judgement has long been forgotten and yet, as I am about to demonstrate, it may be urgent to revive it for its critical and productive potential. An infinite judgement is neither analytic nor synthetic; it does not produce logical truths, nor true representations, but it establishes the genetic conditions of real objects and the concepts appropriate to them. It is through infinite judgements that we reach the principle of transcendental logic, in the depths of which all reality can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  48
    Clinical judgment and the rationality of the human sciences.Eugenie Gatens-Robinson - 1986 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 11 (2):167-178.
    Rationality in medicine is frequently construed as hypotheticodeductive. This article argues that such a model gives a distorted view of the rational character of an enterprise that makes judgments about individual human well-being. Medicine as a science is a practical human science. Seen as such, its rational orientation is one that applies general knowledge to particular situations. It is argued that such an orientation is not deductive but interpretative. The Aristotelian concept of practical wisdom (‘phron sis’) is used as a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  46. The Generals and Particulars of Law’s Abstract Judgement and the Trouble with Responsibility in Negligence Law.Haris Psarras - 2019 - Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoria Del Derecho:23-31.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  36
    An Abstract Approach to Consequence Relations.Petr Cintula, José Gil-férez, Tommaso Moraschini & Francesco Paoli - 2019 - Review of Symbolic Logic 12 (2):331-371.
    We generalise the Blok–Jónsson account of structural consequence relations, later developed by Galatos, Tsinakis and other authors, in such a way as to naturally accommodate multiset consequence. While Blok and Jónsson admit, in place of sheer formulas, a wider range of syntactic units to be manipulated in deductions (including sequents or equations), these objects are invariablyaggregatedvia set-theoretical union. Our approach is more general in that nonidempotent forms of premiss and conclusion aggregation, including multiset sum and fuzzy set union, are considered. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. Kant’s Deduction From Apperception: An Essay on the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories.Dennis Schulting - 2019 - Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.
    In focusing on the systematic deduction of the categories from a principle, Schulting takes up anew the controversial project of the eminent German Kant scholar Klaus Reich, whose monograph “The Completeness of Kant's Table of Judgments” made the case that the logical functions of judgement can all be derived from the objective unity of apperception and can be shown to link up with one another systematically. -/- Common opinion among Kantians today has it that Kant did not mean to derive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  49.  32
    Deductive Cardinality Results and Nuisance-Like Principles.Sean C. Ebels-Duggan - 2021 - Review of Symbolic Logic 14 (3):592-623.
    The injective version of Cantor’s theorem appears in full second-order logic as the inconsistency of the abstraction principle, Frege’s Basic Law V (BLV), an inconsistency easily shown using Russell’s paradox. This incompatibility is akin to others—most notably that of a (Dedekind) infinite universe with the Nuisance Principle (NP) discussed by neo-Fregean philosophers of mathematics. This paper uses the Burali–Forti paradox to demonstrate this incompatibility, and another closely related, without appeal to principles related to the axiom of choice—a result hitherto unestablished. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  38
    Deductive program verification (a practitioner's commentary).David A. Nelson - 1992 - Minds and Machines 2 (3):283-307.
    A proof of ‘correctness’ for a mathematical algorithm cannot be relevant to executions of a program based on that algorithm because both the algorithm and the proof are based on assumptions that do not hold for computations carried out by real-world computers. Thus, proving the ‘correctness’ of an algorithm cannot establish the trustworthiness of programs based on that algorithm. Despite the (deceptive) sameness of the notations used to represent them, the transformation of an algorithm into an executable program is a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 995