Results for 'Ralph Bubrich Winn'

(not author) ( search as author name )
996 found
Order:
  1.  19
    American philosophy.Ralph Bubrich Winn - 1955 - New York,: Greenwood Press.
  2.  5
    A concise dictionary of existentialism.Ralph Bubrich Winn - 1960 - New York,: Philosophical Library.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  3
    Amerikanische Philosophie.Ralph B. Winn - 1948 - A. Francke.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  11
    ed. Hans Reichenbach's From Copernicus to Einstein.Ralph B. Winn - 1943 - Philosophical Review 52:424.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  27
    Is nature rational?Ralph B. Winn - 1939 - Philosophy of Science 6 (3):285-300.
    Most words are like small vessels with constantly changing contents. Life does not wait for adjustments in language, but seeks to give an immediate solution to its most imperative needs and interests. It builds up and sometimes destroys. It is a panorama in flux.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  32
    Reflections on causation and perception.Ralph B. Winn - 1946 - Philosophical Review 55 (January):77-80.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Reflections on infinity.Ralph B. Winn - 1932 - Journal of Philosophy 29 (26):713-717.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  25
    The beauty of nature and art.Ralph B. Winn - 1942 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 2 (5):3-13.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  23
    The language of art.Ralph B. Winn - 1943 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 3 (11/12):49-54.
  10.  18
    The nature of relations.Ralph B. Winn - 1941 - Philosophical Review 50 (1):20-35.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  18
    The nature of causation.Ralph B. Winn - 1940 - Philosophy of Science 7 (2):192-204.
    Strange as it may seem, the traditional principle of causality is based on two contradictory assumptions, both of which are generally accepted, explicitly or implicitly, by the contemporary physicists as well as philosophers. That they are not always willing to acknowledge this paradoxical fact, does not save them from the perplexing situation. The two assumptions, in brief, are: That nothing can act at a distance or across an interval of time, without something mediating between the bodies or events; and That (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Philosophic abstracts.Dagobert D. Runes, Ralph B. Winn & Russell F. Moore (eds.) - 1940 - New York,: Philosophic Abstracts.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  12
    "Aesthetics: The Problem of Art and Beauty," pp. 34-48 in American Philosophy.Van Meter Ames & Ralph B. Winn - 1956 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 15 (2):261-262.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. A cosmological scheme.Ralph B. Winn - 1930 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 11 (4):254.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. American Philosophy.Ralph B. Winn - 1955 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 11 (3):533-533.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  8
    Dialectics: General Principles.Ralph B. Winn - 1938 - Science and Society 2 (4):520 - 526.
  17. John Dewey: Dictionary of Education.Ralph B. Winn - 1960 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 15 (1):129-130.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Logic, living and dead.Ralph B. Winn - 1937 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 18 (2):152.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  23
    Mind and nature.Ralph B. Winn - 1946 - Philosophy of Science 13 (1):41-52.
    Extensive and profound as philosophic speculation on the nature of knowledge may have been during the last twenty-five centuries, it must be conceded that it has, on the whole, failed in its undertaking. In fact, we do not seem to be much closer to the solution of the epistemological problem than were Kant and Hegel or, for that matter, Plato and Aristotle. Obviously enough, the problem should now be approached in some new way, perhaps one growing out of recent scientific (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  47
    Our pre-copernican notion of time.Ralph B. Winn - 1943 - Journal of Philosophy 40 (15):403-411.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  35
    On Zeno's paradox of motion.Ralph B. Winn - 1932 - Journal of Philosophy 29 (15):400-401.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  16
    Philosophy and science.Ralph B. Winn - 1942 - Philosophy of Science 9 (1):1-18.
    Many centuries ago, at the very beginning of the systematic development of philosophy, Plato declared that the thinker's domain comprises “the wholeness of things;” and indeed, the earlier thinkers took all knowledge for their province and did not hesitate to discuss problems now referred to art, psychology, economics, mathematics, or physics. Since then the meaning of philosophy has appreciably changed, however, and the intellectual descendants of the great founder of the Academy no longer claim the monopoly of all fields of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Philosophy at work.Ralph B. Winn - 1960 - New York,: Pageant Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. The distinction between truth and knowledge.Ralph B. Winn - 1933 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 14 (3):185.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. They learn to think.Ralph B. Winn - 1963 - New York,: Pageant Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  13
    Whitehead's concept of process: A few critical remarks.Ralph B. Winn - 1933 - Journal of Philosophy 30 (26):710-714.
  27.  9
    American Philosophy.Criticism and Construction in the Philosophy of the American New Realism.A. C. Ewing, Ralph B. Winn & Lars Boman - 1956 - Philosophical Quarterly 6 (25):372.
  28.  25
    Spinoza: A Life of Reason. Abraham Wolfson. [REVIEW]Ralph B. Winn - 1933 - Journal of Philosophy 30 (19):530-531.
  29. Copernicus.Harold Spencer Jones, Hans Reichenbach & Ralph B. Winn - 1944 - Philosophy 19 (73):174-175.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  24
    Copernicus. By Sir Harold Spencer Jones, F.R.S. (University of Wales Press. 1943. Pp. 30. Price 1s. 6d.)From Copernicus to Einstein. By Hans Reichenbach. Translated by Ralph B. Winn. (New York: Philosophical Library, Inc. 1942. Pp. 123. Price $2.). [REVIEW]A. D. Ritchie - 1944 - Philosophy 19 (73):174-.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly.Ralph Wedgwood - 2003 - In Sarah Stroud & Christine Tappolet (eds.), Weakness of will and practical irrationality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 201--229.
    Let us take an example that Bernard Williams (1981: 102) made famous. Suppose that you want a gin and tonic, and you believe that the stuff in front of you is gin. In fact, however, the stuff is not gin but petrol. So if you drink the stuff (even mixed with tonic), it will be decidedly unpleasant, to say the least. Should you choose to drink the stuff or not?
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  32. The internalist virtue theory of knowledge.Ralph Wedgwood - 2020 - Synthese 197 (12):5357–5378.
    Here is a definition of knowledge: for you to know a proposition p is for you to have an outright belief in p that is correct precisely because it manifests the virtue of rationality. This definition resembles Ernest Sosa’s “virtue theory”, except that on this definition, the only virtue that must be manifested in all instances of knowledge is rationality, and no reductive account of rationality is attempted—rationality is assumed to be an irreducibly normative notion. This definition is compatible with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  33. The Reasons Aggregation Theorem.Ralph Wedgwood - 2022 - Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 12:127-148.
    Often, when one faces a choice between alternative actions, there are reasons both for and against each alternative. On one way of understanding these words, what one “ought to do all things considered (ATC)” is determined by the totality of these reasons. So, these reasons can somehow be “combined” or “aggregated” to yield an ATC verdict on these alternatives. First, various assumptions about this sort of aggregation of reasons are articulated. Then it is shown that these assumptions allow for the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. Primitively rational belief-forming processes.Ralph Wedgwood - 2011 - In Andrew Reisner & Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen (eds.), Reasons for Belief. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 180--200.
    Intuitively, it seems that some belief-forming practices have the following three properties: 1. They are rational practices, and the beliefs that we form by means of these practices are themselves rational or justified beliefs. 2. Even if in most cases these practices reliably lead to correct beliefs (i.e., beliefs in true propositions), they are not infallible: it is possible for beliefs that are formed by means of these practices to be incorrect (i.e., to be beliefs in false propositions). 3. The (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  35. The meaning of 'ought'.Ralph Wedgwood - 2006 - In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics: Volume 1. Clarendon Press. pp. 127-160.
    In this paper, I apply the "conceptual role semantics" approach that I have proposed elsewhere (according to which the meaning of normative terms is given by their role in practical reasoning or deliberation) to the meaning of the term 'ought'. I argue that this approach can do three things: It can give an adequate explanation of the special connection that normative judgments have to practical reasoning and motivation for action. It can give an adequate account of why the central principles (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  36.  4
    Groaning for the Kingdom of God: Spirituality, Social Justice, and the Witness of the Blumhardts.Christian T. Collins Winn - 2013 - Journal of Spiritual Formation and Soul Care 6 (1):56-75.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Objective and Subjective 'Ought'.Ralph Wedgwood - 2016 - In Nate Charlow & Matthew Chrisman (eds.), Deontic Modality. Oxford University Press. pp. 143-168.
    This essay offers an account of the truth conditions of sentences involving deontic modals like ‘ought’, designed to capture the difference between objective and subjective kinds of ‘ought’ This account resembles the classical semantics for deontic logic: according to this account, these truths conditions involve a function from the world of evaluation to a domain of worlds (equivalent to a so-called “modal base”), and an ordering of the worlds in such domains; this ordering of the worlds itself arises from two (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  38. Intrinsic values and reasons for action.Ralph Wedgwood - 2009 - Philosophical Issues 19 (1):342-363.
    What reasons for action do we have? What explains why we have these reasons? This paper articulates some of the basic structural features of a theory that would provide answers to these questions. According to this theory, reasons for action are all grounded in intrinsic values, but in a way that makes room for a thoroughly non-consequentialist view of the way in which intrinsic values generate reasons for aaction.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  39.  26
    Afterword/Afterwards.Ralph Weber & Arindam Chakrabarti - 2016 - In . pp. 227-246.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40. The normativity of the intentional.Ralph Wedgwood - 2007 - In Brian P. McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Many philosophers have claimed that the intentional is normative. (This claim is the analogue, within the philosophy of mind, of the claim that is often made within the philosophy of language, that meaning is normative.) But what exactly does this claim mean? And what reason is there for believing it? In this paper, I shall first try to clarify the content of the claim that the intentional is normative. Then I shall examine a number of the arguments that philosophers have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  41.  13
    Pricean ignorance.Ralph Wedgwood - forthcoming - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-22.
    Richard Price’s moral epistemology provides a distinctive account, not only of the sources of our moral knowledge, but also of its limits – that is, of the moral truths that we do not and even cannot know. According to this moral epistemology, the fundamental moral truths are necessary rather than contingent; if they are knowable at all, they are knowable a priori. In general, fundamental moral truths are akin to mathematical truths. Specifically, these necessary moral truths are grounded in the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Doxastic Rationality.Ralph Wedgwood - 2022 - In Paul Silva & Luis R. G. Oliveira (eds.), Propositional and Doxastic Justification: New Essays on their Nature and Significance. New York: Routledge. pp. 219-240.
    This chapter is concerned with the distinction that most contemporary epistemologists express by distinguishing between “propositional” and “doxastic” justification. The goal is to develop an account of this distinction that applies, not just to full or outright beliefs, but also to partial credences—and indeed, in principle, to attitudes of all kinds. The standard way of explaining this distinction, in terms of the “basing relation”, is criticized, and an alternative account—the “virtue manifestation” account—is proposed in its place. This account has a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  16
    Taste aversion proneness: A modulator of conditioned consummatory aversions in rats.Ralph L. Elkins & Stephen H. Hobbs - 1982 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 20 (5):257-260.
  44.  5
    With No Attention Specifically Directed to It, Rhythmic Sound Does Not Automatically Facilitate Visual Task Performance.Jorg De Winne, Paul Devos, Marc Leman & Dick Botteldooren - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    In a century where humans and machines—powered by artificial intelligence or not—increasingly work together, it is of interest to understand human processing of multi-sensory stimuli in relation to attention and working memory. This paper explores whether and when supporting visual information with rhythmic auditory stimuli can optimize multi-sensory information processing. In turn, this can make the interaction between humans or between machines and humans more engaging, rewarding and activating. For this purpose a novel working memory paradigm was developed where participants (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Gassendi and skepticism.Ralph Walker - 1983 - In Myles Burnyeat (ed.), The Skeptical Tradition. University of California Press. pp. 319--336.
  46.  6
    Friedrich Nietzsche: Leben, Schriften, Zeugnisse.Ralph-Rainer Wuthenow - 2000 - Frankfurt am Main: Insel.
  47.  96
    Reconsidering Virtue: Differences of Perspective in Virtue Ethics and the Positive Social Sciences.David S. Bright, Bradley A. Winn & Jason Kanov - 2014 - Journal of Business Ethics 119 (4):445-460.
    This paper describes differences in two perspectives on the idea of virtue as a theoretical foundation for positive organizational ethics (POE). The virtue ethics perspective is grounded in the philosophical tradition, has classical roots, and focuses attention on virtue as a property of character. The positive social science perspective is a recent movement (e.g., positive psychology and positive organizational scholarship) that has implications for POE. The positive social science movement operationalizes virtue through an empirical lens that emphasizes virtuous behaviors. From (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  48.  24
    On comparing ancient chinese and greek ethics: The tertium comparationis as tool of analysis and evaluation.Ralph Weber - 2015 - In .
  49.  7
    Religio-philosophical roots.Ralph Weber, Gert Tinggaard Svendsen & Gunnar Lind Haase Svendsen - 2009 - In . pp. 107-123.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Pursuing justice: traditional and contemporary issues in our communities and the world.Ralph A. Weisheit - 2019 - London: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group. Edited by Frank Morn.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 996