Results for 'Fred Finley'

(not author) ( search as author name )
1000+ found
Order:
  1. Teaching evolution using historical arguments in a conceptual change strategy.Murray S. Jensen & Fred N. Finley - 1995 - Science Education 79 (2):147-166.
  2. All Americans (Oxford University Press). As a result of the working.Fred Finley - 1995 - Science & Education 4:105-106.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  17
    A Summary of Research in Science Education‐1990.Fred Finley, Frances Lawrenz & Patricia Heller - 1992 - Science Education 76 (3):239-281.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Third International History, Philosophy and Science Teaching Conference.Fred Finley - 1994 - Science & Education 3:209-211.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  15
    Lines of force: Faraday's and students' views.M. Cecilia Pocovi & Fred Finley - 2002 - Science & Education 11 (5):459-474.
  6.  15
    Historical evolution of the field view and textbook accounts.M. Cecilia Pocovi & Fred N. Finley - 2003 - Science & Education 12 (4):387-396.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. Conscious experience.Fred Dretske - 1993 - Mind 102 (406):263-283.
  8. Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or pragmatic understanding?Fred Adams & Annie Steadman - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):173–181.
    Among philosophers, there are at least two prevalent views about the core concept of intentional action. View I (Adams 1986, 1997; McCann 1986) holds that an agent S intentionally does an action A only if S intends to do A. View II (Bratman 1987; Harman 1976; and Mele 1992) holds that there are cases where S intentionally does A without intending to do A, as long as doing A is foreseen and S is willing to accept A as a consequence (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  9. Perception without awareness.Fred Dretske - 2006 - In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 147--180.
  10.  45
    Emergence and its place in nature: a case study of biochemical networks.Fred C. Boogerd, Frank J. Bruggeman, Robert C. Richardson, Achim Stephan & Hans V. Westerhoff - 2005 - Synthese 145 (1):131-164.
    We will show that there is a strong form of emergence in cell biology. Beginning with C.D. Broad’s classic discussion of emergence, we distinguish two conditions sufficient for emergence. Emergence in biology must be compatible with the thought that all explanations of systemic properties are mechanistic explanations and with their sufficiency. Explanations of systemic properties are always in terms of the properties of the parts within the system. Nonetheless, systemic properties can still be emergent. If the properties of the components (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  11. The good life: A defense of attitudinal hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):604-628.
    The students and colleagues of Roderick Chisholm admired and respected Chisholm. Many were filled not only with admiration, but with affection and gratitude for Chisholm throughout the time we knew him. Even now that he is dead, we continue to wish him well. Under the circumstances, many of us probably think that that wish amounts to no more than this: we hope that things went well for him when he lived; we hope that he had a good life.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  12. Adjusting utility for justice: A consequentialist reply to the objection from justice.Fred Feldman - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (3):567-585.
    1. Introduction. In a famous passage near the beginning of A Theory of Justice, John Rawls discusses utilitarianism’s notorious difficulties with justice. According to classic forms of utilitarianism, a certain course of action is morally right if it produces the greatest sum of satisfactions. And, as Rawls points out, the perplexing implication is “…that it does not matter, except indirectly, how this sum of satisfactions is distributed among individuals any more than it matters, except indirectly, how one man distributes his (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  13. Mental events as structuring causes of behavior.Fred Dretske - 1993 - In John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford University Press.
    1. Causal explanations depend on our interests, our purposes, and our prior knowledge. ⇒ No uniquely real causal explanation.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  14.  67
    The Good Life: A Defense of Attitudinal Hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):604-628.
    What makes a life go well for the one who lives it? Hedonists hold that pleasure enhances the value of a life; pain diminishes it. Hedonism has been subjected to a number of objections. Some are (a) based on the claim that hedonism is a form of “mental statism”. Others are (b) based on the claim that some pleasures are base or degrading. Yet others are (c) based on the claim that when a bad person enjoys a pleasure, his receipt (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  15.  81
    Adjusting Utility for Justice.Fred Feldman - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (3):567-585.
    1. Introduction. In a famous passage near the beginning of A Theory of Justice, John Rawls discusses utilitarianism’s notorious difficulties with justice. According to classic forms of utilitarianism, a certain course of action is morally right if it produces the greatest sum of satisfactions. And, as Rawls points out, the perplexing implication is “…that it does not matter, except indirectly, how this sum of satisfactions is distributed among individuals any more than it matters, except indirectly, how one man distributes his (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  16.  17
    Psychological Analysis and the Philosophy of John Stuart Mill.Fred Wilson - 1990
    John Stuart Mill underwent a mental crisis in the 1820s. He emerged from it, argues Fred Wilson, with a new understanding of the notion of introspective analysis more dequare as an empirical method than the sort of analysis that had been used by earlier utilitarian thinkiers such as Bentham and James Mill. Wilson's study places Mill's innovations in the context of earlier work in ethics and perception and of subsequent developments in the history of psychology. He shows the significance (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17. Mental events as structuring causes of behavior.Fred Dretske - 1993 - In John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 121--135.
  18.  41
    Reply to Reviewers.Fred Dretske - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (4):819 - 839.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  19. Empty names and pragmatic implicatures.Fred Adams & Gary Fuller - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):449-461.
    What are the meanings of empty names such as ‘Vulcan,’ ‘Pegasus,’ and ‘Santa Claus’ in such sentences as ‘Vulcan is the tenth planet,’ ‘Pegasus flies,’ and especially ‘Santa Claus does not exist’?Our view, developed in Adams et al., consists of a direct-reference account of the meaning of empty names in combination with a pragmatic-implicature account of why we have certain intuitions that seem to conflict with a direct-reference account.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  30
    Community-equipoise and the ethics of randomized clinical trials.Fred Gifford - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (2):127–148.
    This paper critically examines a particular strategy for resolving the central ethical dilemma associated with randomized clinical trials — the “community equipoise” strategy . The dilemma is that RCTs appear to violate a physician's duty to choose that therapy which there is most reason to believe is in the patient's best interest, randomizing patients even once evidence begins to favor one treatment. The community equipoise strategy involves the suggestion that our judgment that neither treatment is to be preferred is to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  21. Hyperventilating about intrinsic value.Fred Feldman - 1998 - The Journal of Ethics 2 (4):339-354.
    Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Brentano, Moore, and Chisholm have suggested marks or criteria of intrinsic goodness. I distinguish among eight of these. I focus in this paper on four: (a) unimprovability, (b) unqualifiedness, (c) dependence upon intrinsic natures, and (d) incorruptibility. I try to show that each of these is problematic in some way. I also try to show that they are not equivalent – they point toward distinct conceptions of intrinsic goodness. In the end it appears that none of them (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  22. What good is consciousness?Fred Dretske - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):1-15.
    If consciousness is good for something, conscious things must differ in some causally relevant way from unconscious things. If they do not, then, as Davies and Humphreys conclude, too bad for consciousness: ‘psychological theory need not be concerned with this topic.’Davies and Humphreys are applying a respectable metaphysical idea — the idea, namely, that if an object's having a property does not make a difference to what that object does, if the object's causal powers are in no way enhanced by (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  23.  29
    Empty Names and Pragmatic Implicatures.Fred Adams & Gary Fuller - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):449-461.
    What are the meanings of empty names such as ‘Vulcan,’ ‘Pegasus,’ and ‘Santa Claus’ in such sentences as ‘Vulcan is the tenth planet,’ ‘Pegasus flies,’ and especially ‘Santa Claus does not exist’?Our view, developed in Adams et al., consists of a direct-reference account of the meaning of empty names in combination with a pragmatic-implicature account of why we have certain intuitions that seem to conflict with a direct-reference account.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  24.  25
    What Good is Consciousness?Fred Dretske - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):1-15.
    If consciousness is good for something, conscious things must differ in some causally relevant way from unconscious things. If they do not, then, as Davies and Humphreys conclude, too bad for consciousness: ‘psychological theory need not be concerned with this topic.’Davies and Humphreys are applying a respectable metaphysical idea — the idea, namely, that if an object's having a property does not make a difference to what that object does, if the object's causal powers are in no way enhanced by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  25.  15
    Community‐Equipoise and the Ethics of Randomized Clinical Trials.Fred Gifford - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (2):127-148.
    This paper critically examines a particular strategy for resolving the central ethical dilemma associated with randomized clinical trials (RCTs) — the “community equipoise” strategy (CE). The dilemma is that RCTs appear to violate a physician's duty to choose that therapy which there is most reason to believe is in the patient's best interest, randomizing patients even once evidence begins to favor one treatment. The community equipoise strategy involves the suggestion that our judgment that neither treatment is to be preferred (that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  26.  49
    Hyperventilating about Intrinsic Value.Fred Feldman - 1998 - The Journal of Ethics 2 (4):339-354.
    Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Brentano, Moore, and Chisholm have suggested ’’marks‘‘ or criteria of intrinsic goodness. I distinguish among eight of these. I focus in this paper on four: (a) unimprovability, (b) unqualifiedness, (c) dependence upon intrinsic natures, and (d) incorruptibility. I try to show that each of these is problematic in some way. I also try to show that they are not equivalent – they point toward distinct conceptions of intrinsic goodness. In the end it appears that none of them (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  27.  65
    Perception and the Inhuman Gaze: Perspectives from Philosophy, Phenomenology and the Sciences.Fred Cummins, Anya Daly, James Jardine & Dermot Moran (eds.) - 2020 - New York, NY, USA; London, UK: Routledge.
    The diverse essays in this volume speak to the relevance of phenomenological and psychological questioning regarding perceptions of the human. This designation, human, can be used beyond the mere identification of a species to underwrite exclusion, denigration, dehumanization and demonization, and to set up a pervasive opposition in Othering all deemed inhuman, nonhuman, or posthuman. As alerted to by Merleau-Ponty, one crucial key for a deeper understanding of these issues is consideration of the nature and scope of perception. Perception defines (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  47
    Hume’s Defence of Causal Inference.Fred Wilson - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (4):661-694.
    As is well known, the Humean account of causal inference gives a central location to inference habits. Some of these habits one can discipline. Thus, one can so discipline oneself as to reason in accordance with the “rules by which to judge of causes and effects”, that is, one can discipline oneself to think scientifically, rather than, say, in accordance with the rules of prejudice, or of superstition. All such judgments, even those of science, are, however, upon the Humean account (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  29.  22
    Alternative Visions: Paths in the Global Village.Fred Reinhard Dallmayr - 1998 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    Globalization is often seen as a process of universal standardization under the auspices of market economics, technology, and hegemonic power. Resisting this process without endorsing parochial self-enclosure, Fred Dallmayr explores alternative visions that are rooted in distinct vernacular traditions and facilitate cross-cultural learning in an open-ended global arena.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  30.  71
    Differences that make no difference.Fred Dretske - 1994 - Philosophical Topics 22 (1/2):41-57.
  31.  12
    Differences that Make No Difference.Fred Dretske - 1994 - Philosophical Topics 22 (1-2):41-57.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  32. Absent qualia.Fred Dretske - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (1):78-85.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  33.  39
    John Stuart mill.Fred Wilson - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34.  29
    Acquaintance, Ontology, and Knowledge.Fred Wilson - 1970 - New Scholasticism 44 (1):1-48.
  35.  10
    Absent Qualia.Fred Dretske - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (1):78-85.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  36.  73
    The Metaphysics of Freedom.Fred Dretske - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):1-13.
    I offer Jimmy a dollar to wiggle his ears. He wiggles them because he wants the dollar and, as a result of my offer, thinks he will earn it by wiggling his ears. So I cause him to believe something that explains, or helps to explain, why he wiggles his ears. If I push a button, and a bell, wired to the button, rings because the button is depressed, I cause the bell to ring. I make it ring. Indeed, I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  37.  2
    Achieving Our World: Toward a Global and Plural Democracy.Fred Reinhard Dallmayr - 2001 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    In an age marked by global hegemony and festering civilization clashes, Fred Dallmayr's Achieving Our World charts a path toward a cosmopolitan democracy respectful of local differences. Dallmayr draws upon and develops insights from a number of fields: political theory, the study of international politics, recent Continental philosophy, and an array of critical cultural disciplines to illustrate and elucidate his thesis. In Achieving Our World, Dallmayr contends that a genuinely global and plural democracy and 'civic culture' is the only (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38.  17
    The Origins of Hume's Sceptical Argument against Reason.Fred Wilson - 1985 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (3):323 - 335.
  39.  24
    Weinberg's Refutation of Nominalism.Fred Wilson - 1969 - Dialogue 8 (3):460-474.
    Professor Weinberg, in his recention, Relation, and Induction, has critically discussed the nominalistic tradition stemming from Ockham and continuing in the work of Berkeley and Hume. In this tradition there is one fundamental principle, which however divides into two parts. The first is Whatever is distinguishable is distinct, and conversely. The second is Whatever is distinct is separable, and conversely. Weinberg argues that both and are mistaken.In this paper I propose to explore the case against nominalism. I shall suggest that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40. Perception without awareness.Fred Dretske - 2006 - In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press.
  41. Embodied cognition and the extended mind.Fred Adams & Ken Aizawa - 2009 - In Sarah Robins, John Symons & Paco Calvo (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 193--213.
    Summary: A review of the cognitivist/extended cognition and extended mind landscape.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  32
    Between Freiburg and Frankfurt: toward a critical ontology.Fred Reinhard Dallmayr - 1991 - Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press.
    In an age marked by profound rifts and tensions on both political and philosophical levels, a fundamental debate affecting virtually the whole of Western intellectual culture is currently taking place. In one camp are those who would defend traditional metaphysics and its ties to the rise of modernity; in the other camp, those who reject the possibility of foundational thought and argue for the emergence of a postmodern order. Can we still defend the notion of critical reason? How should we (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43.  54
    Polis and Praxis: Exercises in Contemporary Political Theory.Fred Reinhard Dallmayr - 1984 - MIT Press.
    The touchstone of these seven original essays is the relationship between polis and praxis - the public-political space and the political action that maintains and is conditioned by that space. The argument flows from Martin Heidegger's lament in his Letter on Humanism that modern philosophers have failed to understand that the essence of "action" is "accomplishment." Dallmayr's lucid essays are a step toward achieving that understanding.Dallmayr assesses and puts into perspective the work of many of the seminal thinkers of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44.  17
    Peace Talks: Who Will Listen?Fred Reinhard Dallmayr - 2004
    In his Complaint of Peace, the great sixteenth-century humanist Erasmus allows "Peace" to talk. Peace speaks as a plaintiff, protesting her shabby treatment at the hands of humankind and our ever-ready inclination to launch wars. Against this lure of warfare, Erasmus pits the higher task of peace-building, which can only succeed through the cultivation of justice and respect for all human life. First articulated in 1517, the complaint of peace has echoed through subsequent centuries and down to our age--an age (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  45.  42
    The Role of a Principle of Acquaintance in Ontology.Fred Wilson - 1969 - Modern Schoolman 47 (1):37-56.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  6
    The Metaphysics of Freedom.Fred Dretske - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):1-13.
    I offer Jimmy a dollar to wiggle his ears. He wiggles them because he wants the dollar and, as a result of my offer, thinks he will earn it by wiggling his ears. So I cause him to believe something that explains, or helps to explain, why he wiggles his ears. If I push a button, and a bell, wired to the button, rings because the button is depressed, I cause the bell to ring. I make it ring. Indeed, I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  14
    History and theory after the fall: an essay on interpretation.Fred Weinstein - 1990 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    In this ambitious work, Fred Weinstein confronts the obstacles that have increasingly frustrated our attempts to explain social and historical reality. Traditionally, we have relied on history and social theory to describe the ways people understand the world they live in. But the ordering explanations we have always used--derived from the classical social theories originally forged by Marx, Tocqueville, Weber, Durkheim, Freud--have collapsed. In the wake of this collapse or "fall," the rival claims of fiction, psychoanalysis, sociology, anthropology, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  59
    Habermas and rationality.Fred Dallmayr - 1988 - Political Theory 16 (4):553-579.
  49.  43
    Nothingness and Sunyata: A Comparison of Heidegger and Nishitani.Fred Dallmayr - 1992 - Philosophy East and West 42 (1):37-48.
  50.  26
    The half-life of policy rationales: How new technology affects old policy issues.Fred E. Foldvary & Daniel B. Klein - 2002 - Knowledge, Technology & Policy 15 (3):82-92.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000