Results for 'Names giving'

989 found
Order:
  1.  41
    Science, Names Giving and Names Calling: Change NDM-1 to PCM.AjaiR Singh - 2011 - Mens Sana Monographs 9 (1):294.
    A journal editor recently apologised for publishing a 2010 paper in which authors designated an enzyme as New Delhi metallo-β-lactamase-1 (NDM-1) and its related gene blaNDM-1 after a city, New Delhi. This name had raised an outcry in India, with health authorities, media and medical practitioners demanding New Delhi be dropped from the name. The name was actually first given in another 2009 paper, whose corresponding author remains the same as the 2010 paper. There is a tradition of eponymous (...) in science. But those found derogatory to races, groups, cities, and countries have been changed. For example, Mongolism was changed to Down's syndrome; Australia antigen to HBsAg; Mexican Swine flu to H1N1; GRID (Gay Related Immune Deficiency) and 4H-Disease (Haitians, Homosexuals, Haemophiliacs and Heroin Users Disease) to AIDS. It is necessary that NDM-1 also be changed to a name based on scientific characteristics. NDM-1 must be changed to PCM (plasmid-encoding carbapenem-resistant metallo-β-lactamase). It is also necessary to review the tradition of naming organisms, diseases, genes, etc. after cities, countries and races. Often, such names giving amounts to names calling. It needs to be discarded by scientists in all new names giving from now on. Geographical and racial names giving must be replaced by scientific names giving. Journal editors must ensure that such scientific names giving is laid down as standard guideline in paper submissions. All such names still in currency need to be phased out by replacing them with names based on scientific characteristics, or in honour of their pioneering scientist/s or institutions. The lead author of the above 2010 paper has said he was not consulted about the final draft and did not agree with the conclusions of the paper. To ensure that corresponding authors do not ride roughshod over co-authors, and lead and other authors do not backtrack on papers, editors must ensure written concurrence of all authors, especially the lead author, to the final draft of a paper and include this in their guidelines for paper submissions. (shrink)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  10
    Proposal about scientific names giving.Ajai R. Singh - 2012 - Mens Sana Monographs 10 (1):181.
  3.  28
    Eblaite Personal Names and Semitic Name Giving: Papers of a Symposium Held in Rome, July 15-17, 1985.M. H. & Alfonso Archi - 1992 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 112 (1):159.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  11
    Who Gives a Fig (Tree a Name)?: Chronotopic Conflicts in Plutarch’s Romulus.Jason Lawrence Banta - 2007 - Intertexts 11 (1):25-41.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  8
    Naming and knowing: Giving forms to things unknown.E. Leary David - 1995 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 62 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  21
    Giving Science a Bad Name: Politically and Commercially Motivated Fallacies in BSE Inquiry.Louise Cummings - 2005 - Argumentation 19 (2):123-143.
    It is a feature of scientific inquiry that it proceeds alongside a multitude of non-scientific interests. This statement is as true of the scientific inquiries of previous centuries, many of which brought scientists into conflict with institutionalised religious thinking, as it is true of the scientific inquiries of today, which are conducted increasingly within commercial and political contexts. However, while the fact of the coexistence of scientific and non-scientific interests has changed little over time, what has changed with time is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  7.  27
    To Give in the Name, or to Give without Names.David A. Borman - 2005 - Philosophy Today 49 (2):145-155.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  50
    You Give Love A Bad Name.Jacob Sparks - 2019 - Business Ethics Journal Review 7 (2):7-13.
    Brennan and Jaworski (2018) accuse me of misunderstanding their thesis and failing to produce a counterexample to it. In this Response, I clarify my central argument in “Can’t Buy Me Love,” explain why I used prostitution as an example, and work to advance the debate.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  24
    Giving the sceptic a good name.Alastair Hannay - 1975 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 18 (4):409 – 436.
    The word 'sceptic' usually refers to a theoretical figure whose philosophical importance lies exclusively in his challenge to any attempt to justify the belief in the possibility of knowledge. But the label was once applied to living persons - the so-called Pyrrhonists - whose scepticism encompassed a way of life. Following Sextus Empiricus's portrayal of the Pyrrhonists, Arne Naess has provided comprehensive arguments both in rebuttal of the frequent claims either that scepticism is logically inconsistent or that at least it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  10
    Naming and Knowing: Giving Forms to Things Unknown.David Leary - 1995 - Social Research: An International Quarterly 62.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11. Where an endnote simply gives a reference to what is mentioned in the text, the entry refers to the page of the text: where an endnote introduces fresh references or material, its own page is given. Medieval authors are listed under their Christian names (eg Thomas Aquinas), though not where they are usually known by surnames (for instance, Chaucer).Acta Pauli et Theclae & Theological Rules - 2009 - In John Marenbon (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Boethius. Cambridge University Press. pp. 343.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Vacuous Names in Early Analytic Philosophy: Frege, Russell, and Moore.Mark Textor - 2016 - Philosophy Compass 11 (6):316-326.
    Empty proper names give rise to intriguing questions. Frege, Moore and Russell stand at the beginning of analytic philosophy's engagement with these questions. In this paper I will therefore introduce and assess their views on the topic of empty names and draw connections to recent work.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  54
    Incongruent Names: A Theme in the History of Chinese Philosophy.Paul J. D’Ambrosio, Hans-Rudolf Kantor & Hans-Georg Moeller - 2018 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 17 (3):305-330.
    This essay is meant to shed light on a discourse that spans centuries and includes different voices. To be aware of such trans-textual resonances can add a level of historical understanding to the reading of philosophical texts. Specifically, we intend to demonstrate how the notion of the ineffable Dao 道, prominently expressed in the Daodejing 道德經, informs a long discourse on incongruent names in distinction to a mainstream paradigm that demands congruity between names and what they designate. Thereby, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14.  15
    Naming the Ethological Subject.Etienne S. Benson - 2016 - Science in Context 29 (1):107-128.
    ArgumentIn recent decades, through the work of Jane Goodall and other ethologists, the practice of giving personal names to nonhuman animals who are the subjects of scientific research has become associated with claims about animal personhood and scientific objectivity. While critics argue that such naming practices predispose the researcher toward anthropomorphism, supporters suggest that it sensitizes the researcher to individual differences and social relations. Both critics and supporters agree that naming tends to be associated with the recognition of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15.  13
    The Name-glorifying projects of Alexei Losev and Pavel Florensky: A question of their historical interrelation.Dmitry Biriukov - forthcoming - Studies in East European Thought:1-11.
    This article deals with the question of the interrelation between two papers, both called, in short, “Onomatodoxy”, dedicated to the doctrine of Name-glorification (Imiaslavie, Onomatodoxy), both of which were created in line with the Neo-Patristic movement in the Russian philosophy of the Silver Age. One of these papers is by Alexei Losev and the other by Pavel Florensky. In my opinion, there are sufficient grounds to state that Losev’s “Onomatodoxy” was written either after Florensky created his own “Onomatodoxy”, i.e., after (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  22
    No Name: Paul Celan’s Poetics of Naming.Antti Eemeli Salminen - 2010 - Kritike 4 (1):123-137.
    Name is a powerful sign, and name-giving is also calling one intolanguage. Name identifies, summons and subjects. Paul Celan wasfamiliar with all these uses of name and addresses them in his poeticsand poetry. This article will discuss how poetry like Celan’s, which is heavily influenced by so many philosophical readings, could form a critique of naming,on a poetical basis towards philosophical concepts that underline problematics of name-giving in poetic text in particular.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Calling names.J. Biro - 2012 - Analysis 72 (2):285-293.
    Many who agree with Kripke that ‘sloppy, colloquial speech’ often confuses use and mention would deem ‘ a is called N’ an example of such confusion, insisting on ‘ a is called "N"’ as the properly philosophical, un-sloppy, way of saying what is usually intended. Delia Graff Fara demurs – in my view, rightly. But the reasons she gives for doing so are, I think, themselves questionable and in any case do not go to the heart of the mistake on (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. Naming with Necessity (Part of the dissertation portfolio Modality, Names and Descriptions).Zsófia Zvolenszky - 2007 - Dissertation, New York University
    In “Naming with Necessity”, it is argued that Kripke’s thesis that proper names are rigid designators is best seen as being motivated by an individual-driven picture of modality, which has two parts. First, inherent in proper-name usage is the expectation that names refer to modally robust individuals: individuals that can sustain modal predications like ‘is necessarily human’. Second, these modally robust individuals are the fundamental building blocks on the basis of which possible worlds should be conceived in a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  26
    Naming as History: Dickinson's Poems of Definition.Sharon Cameron - 1978 - Critical Inquiry 5 (2):223-251.
    For Emily Dickinson, perhaps no more so than for the rest of us, there was a powerful discrepancy between what was "inner than the Bone"1 and what could be acknowledged. To the extent that her poems are a response to that discrepancy—are, on one hand, a defiant attempt to deny that the discrepancy poses a problem and, on the other, an admission of defeat at the problem's enormity—they have much to teach us about the way in which language articulates our (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Type-Ambiguous Names.Anders J. Schoubye - 2017 - Mind 126 (503):715-767.
    The orthodox view of proper names, Millianism, provides a very simple and elegant explanation of the semantic contribution of referential uses of namesnames that occur as bare singulars and as the argument of a predicate. However, one problem for Millianism is that it cannot explain the semantic contribution of predicative uses of names. In recent years, an alternative view, so-called the-predicativism, has become increasingly popular. According to the-predicativists, names are uniformly count nouns. This straightforwardly explains (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  21. Proper Names, Contingency A Priori and Necessity A Posteriori.Chen Bo - 2011 - History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (2):119 - 138.
    After a brief review of the notions of necessity and a priority, this paper scrutinizes Kripke's arguments for supposedly contingent a priori propositions and necessary a posteriori propositions involving proper names, and reaches a negative conclusion, i.e. there are no such propositions, or at least the propositions Kripke gives as examples are not such propositions. All of us, including Kripke himself, still have to face the old question raised by Hume, i.e. how can we justify the necessity and universality (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  10
    Inside names.Denis Delfitto & Gaetano Fiorin - 2022 - Evolutionary Linguistic Theory 4 (2):153-190.
    In this contribution, we offer a contextualist analysis of names whereby a name N is used as a felicitous referential term in all and only those contexts of utterance in which N is intended to refer to a unique referent by all cognitive agents that are relevant in the context. This analysis has important across-the-board virtues. It reduces the distance between common nouns and names, under the insight that names are a highly specific case of a more (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. My Life Gives the Moral Landscape its Relief.Marc Champagne - 2023 - In Sam Harris: Critical Responses. Carus Books. pp. 17–38.
    Sam Harris (2010) argues that, given our neurology, we can experience well-being, and that seeking to maximize this state lets us distinguish the good from the bad. He takes our ability to compare degrees of well-being as his starting point, but I think that the analysis can be pushed further, since there is a (non-religious) reason why well-being is desirable, namely the finite life of an individual organism. It is because death is a constant possibility that things can be assessed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. The game of the name: introducing logic, language, and mind.Gregory McCulloch - 1989 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This introduction to modern work in analytic philosophy uses the example of the proper name to give a clear explanation of the logical theories of Gottlob Frege, and explain the application of his ideas to ordinary language. McCulloch then shows how meaning is rooted in the philosophy of mind and the question of intentionality, and looks at the ways in which thought can be "about" individual material objects.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  25.  17
    Giving Naturalism a Chance: Interactivism, Emergence, and Nonlinearity.Robert L. Campbell - 2014 - Cosmos and History 10 (1):118-130.
    This paper offers a defense of naturalism, which might improve its chance of being adopted as a direction, both for theory and for empirical research. This defense responds in particular to three themes:: the emergence of mind , the pervasiveness of nonlinearity in biology and psychology, and the need for levels and degrees of self . Normal 0 false false false EN-US X-NONE X-NONE /* Style Definitions */ table.MsoNormalTable {mso-style-name:"Table Normal"; mso-tstyle-rowband-size:0; mso-tstyle-colband-size:0; mso-style-noshow:yes; mso-style-priority:99; mso-style-qformat:yes; mso-style-parent:""; mso-padding-alt:0in 5.4pt 0in 5.4pt; (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. The double life of names.Gail Leckie - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 165 (3):1139-1160.
    This paper is a counter to the view that names are always predicates with the same extension as a metalinguistic predicate with the form “is a thing called “N”” (the Predicate View). The Predicate View is in opposition to the Referential View of names. In this paper, I undermine one argument for the Predicate View. The Predicate View’s adherents take examples of uses of names that have the surface appearance of a predicate and generalise from these to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  27.  66
    Naming worlds in modal and temporal logic.D. M. Gabbay & G. Malod - 2002 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 11 (1):29-65.
    In this paper we suggest adding to predicate modal and temporal logic a locality predicate W which gives names to worlds (or time points). We also study an equal time predicate D(x, y)which states that two time points are at the same distance from the root. We provide the systems studied with complete axiomatizations and illustrate the expressive power gained for modal logic by simulating other logics. The completeness proofs rely on the fairly intuitive notion of a configuration in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  13
    Naming pain: sense of suffering and sense of self in Girolamo Cardano.Anna Corrias - 2020 - History of European Ideas 46 (3):227-241.
    ABSTRACTHardly a few people manage to escape big fears without dying [of them]; not so with pains. This statement captures Cardano's understanding of the difference between mental and physical pain. As a physician with a lifelong history of anxiety and alienation, Cardano inquired ceaselessly into the nature of the delicate interaction between the two kinds of pain. It was his belief that the subtle nature of mental suffering makes it difficult, if not impossible, to identify, name, and give a meaning (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  15
    The name for Kojman–Shelah collapsing function.Bohuslav Balcar & Petr Simon - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 109 (1-2):131-137.
    In the previous paper of this volume, Kojman and Shelah solved our long standing problem of collapsing cardinal κ0 to ω1 by the forcing for singular κ with countable cofinality. The aim of the present paper is to give an explicit construction of the Boolean matrix for this collapse.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  52
    The Name of the Euxine Pontus.A. C. Moorhouse - 1940 - Classical Quarterly 34 (3-4):123-.
    It will be best to explain here, at the start, that I do not propose new etymologies for the words εὒξεινος and πόντος. I regard, then, εὒξεινος πόντος as meaning ‘the hospitable way’. My purpose is to show how such a name came to be given to the Black Sea by the Greeks. First, the word πόντος. The familiar explanation connects it with a series of words, of which I give the most important: Gk. πάτος ‘trodden path’; Skt. pάnthā ‘way’, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  11
    Giving birth to a settlement: Maternal thinking and political action of jewish women on the west bank.Gideon Aran & Tamar El-or - 1995 - Gender and Society 9 (1):60-78.
    On October 27, 1991, a Jewish woman named Rachel Drouk, a settler in the West Bank, was killed by Palestinian Intifada fighters. Twenty-five women spontaneously gathered at the site of the murder and held a vigil—a vigil that eventually developed into a protest settlement. The women, all of whom were married mothers, presented their initiative in maternal narratives: grounds, motives, and justifications for the act, and targets and anticipations were all related to the practice of care. This article conducts an (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Empty Names.R. Mark Sainsbury - 2000 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 6:57-66.
    This paper explores the idea that a name should be associated with a reference condition, rather than with a referent, just as a sentence should be associated with a truth condition, rather than with a truth value. The suggestion, to be coherent, needs to be set in a freelogical framework (following Burge). A prominent advantage of the proposal is that it gives a straight-forward semantics for empty names. A problem discussed in this paper is that of reconciling the rigidity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Names, fictional names, and 'really'.R. M. Sainsbury - 1999 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1):243–269.
    [R. M. Sainsbury] Evans argued that most ordinary proper names were Russellian: to suppose that they have no bearer is to suppose that they have no meaning. The first part of this paper addresses Evans's arguments, and finds them wanting. Evans also claimed that the logical form of some negative existential sentences involves 'really' (e.g. 'Hamlet didn't really exist'). One might be tempted by the view, even if one did not accept its Russellian motivation. However, I suggest that Evans (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  14
    Names, Fictional Names, and 'Really'.R. M. Sainsbury & David Wiggins - 1999 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73:243-286.
    [R. M. Sainsbury] Evans argued that most ordinary proper names were Russellian: to suppose that they have no bearer is to suppose that they have no meaning. The first part of this paper addresses Evans's arguments, and finds them wanting. Evans also claimed that the logical form of some negative existential sentences involves 'really'. One might be tempted by the view, even if one did not accept its Russellian motivation. However, I suggest that Evans gives no adequate account of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  6
    Naming people on the move according to the political agenda: A study of Belgian media.Valériane Mistiaen - 2021 - Discourse and Communication 15 (3):308-329.
    The aim of this article is to study the different denominations used to name people on the move in the Belgian French- and Dutch-speaking press. The so-called ‘refugee crisis’ has received huge media attention in Europe. In Belgium, media landscape is divided amongst Dutch-, French- and much smaller German-speaking communities, all of which harbour different journalistic traditions. The country is then an excellent case study to observe the divergences between the linguistic repertoire of denominations referencing people in the two main (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  90
    Proper name change.Thomas Sattig - 1998 - Theoria 13 (3):491-501.
    Gareth Evans adduces a case in which a proper name apparently undergoes a change in referent. ‘Madagascar’ was originally the name of a part of Africa. Marco Polo, erroneously thinking he was following native usage, applied the name to an island off the African coast. Today ‘Madagascar’ is the name of that island. Evans argues that this kind of case threatens Kripke ’s picture of naming as developed in Naming and Necessity. According to this picture, the name, as used by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  33
    Proper Name Change.Thomas Sattig - 1998 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 13 (3):491-501.
    Gareth Evans adduces a case in which a proper name apparently undergoes a change in referent. ‘Madagascar’ was originally the name of a part of Africa. Marco Polo, erroneously thinking he was following native usage, applied the name to an island off the African coast. Today ‘Madagascar’ is the name of that island. Evans argues that this kind of case threatens Kripke’s picture of naming as developed in Naming and Necessity. According to this picture, the name, as used by Marco (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  91
    Names, fictional names and 'really': David Wiggins.David Wiggins - 1999 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1):271–286.
    [R. M. Sainsbury] Evans argued that most ordinary proper names were Russellian: to suppose that they have no bearer is to suppose that they have no meaning. The first part of this paper addresses Evans's arguments, and finds them wanting. Evans also claimed that the logical form of some negative existential sentences involves 'really' (e.g. 'Hamlet didn't really exist'). One might be tempted by the view, even if one did not accept its Russellian motivation. However, I suggest that Evans (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39. Giving up levelling down.Campbell Brown - 2003 - Economics and Philosophy 19 (1):111-134.
    The so-called “Levelling Down Objection” is commonly believed to occupy a central role in the debate between egalitarians and prioritarians. Egalitarians think that equality is good in itself, and so they are committed to finding value even in such equality as may only be achieved by “levelling down”–i.e., by merely reducing the better off to the level of the worse off. Although egalitarians might deny that levelling down could ever make for an all-things-considered improvement, they cannot deny that it may (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  40.  4
    Under the Name of Method: On Jacques Rancière's Presumptive Tautology.Charles Bingham - 2010 - In Claudia Ruitenberg (ed.), What do Philosophers of Education do? Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 87–102.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Progressivist and Critical Objections to Traditionalism: Epistemology, Authority and Spectatorship Complicity with Traditionalism Under the Name of Rancière A Method that Belongs to Whom? Philosophical Method, the Literal and Metaphorical Method's Name Conclusion Notes References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41. Giving Each Person Her Due: Taurek Cases and Non-Comparative Justice.Alan Thomas - 2012 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15 (5):661-676.
    Taurek cases focus a choice between two views of permissible action, Can Save One and Must Save Many . It is argued that Taurek cases do illustrate the rationale for Can Save One , but existing views do not highlight the fact that this is because they are examples of claims grounded on non-comparative justice. To act to save the many solely because they form a group is to discriminate against the one for an irrelevant reason. That is a canonical (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  20
    Giving an Account of Oneself (review).Chris Lundberg - 2007 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 40 (3):329-333.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Giving an Account of OneselfChris LundbergGiving an Account of Oneself. Judith Butler. New York: Fordham University Press, 2005. Pp. x + 149. $18.95, softcover.Giving an Account of Oneself, Judith Butler's recent foray into moral philosophy, is a lucid interrogation of the problem of responsibility in the wake of contemporary critiques of the subject. In it, Butler moves beyond her concern with the conditions of subjectivity and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. The significance of names.Robin Jeshion - 2009 - Mind and Language 24 (4):370-403.
    As a class of terms and mental representations, proper names and mental names possess an important function that outstrips their semantic and psycho-semantic functions as common, rigid devices of direct reference and singular mental representations of their referents, respectively. They also function as abstract linguistic markers that signal and underscore their referents' individuality. I promote this thesis to explain why we give proper names to certain particulars, but not others; to account for the transfer of singular thought (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  44.  28
    Venn Diagram with Names of Individuals and Their Absence: A Non-classical Diagram Logic.Reetu Bhattacharjee, Mihir Kr Chakraborty & Lopamudra Choudhury - 2018 - Logica Universalis 12 (1-2):141-206.
    Venn diagram system has been extended by introducing names of individuals and their absence. Absence gives a kind of negation of singular propositions. We have offered here a non-classical interpretation of this negation. Soundness and completeness of the present diagram system have been established with respect to this interpretation.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  76
    On the Very Idea of Metalinguistic Theories of Names.Aidan Gray - 2018 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 5.
    Metalinguistic approaches to names hold that proper names are semantically associated with name-bearing properties. I argue that metalinguistic theorists owe us an account of the metaphysics of those properties. The unique structure of the debate about names gives an issue which might look to be narrowly linguistic an important metaphysical dimension. The only plausible account of name-bearing treats name-bearing properties as a species of response-dependent property. I outline how such an account should look, drawing on forms of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  97
    Paternalism in the Name of Autonomy.Manne Sjöstrand, Stefan Eriksson, Niklas Juth & Gert Helgesson - 2013 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 38 (6):jht049.
    Different ideas of the normative relevance of autonomy can give rise to profoundly different action-guiding principles in healthcare. If autonomy is seen as a value rather than as a right, it can be argued that patients’ decisions should sometimes be overruled in order to protect or promote their own autonomy. We refer to this as paternalism in the name of autonomy. In this paper, we discuss different elements of autonomy (decision-making capacity, efficiency, and authenticity) and arguments in favor of paternalism (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  47.  65
    The Cratylus: Plato's Critique of Naming.Timothy M. S. Baxter (ed.) - 1992 - New York: E.J. Brill.
    This book aims to give a coherent interpretation of the whole dialogue, paying particular attention to these etymologies.The book discusses the rival theories ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  48.  12
    Giving Way: Thoughts on Unappreciated Dispositions by Steven Connor.Rick de Villiers - 2022 - Philosophy and Literature 46 (1):244-247.
    In "Who the Meek Are Not," poet Mary Karr thinks it unlikely that peasants, serfs, and the socially low will inherit the earth. Puzzling out that beatitude, she instead conjures the image of "a great stallion at full gallop / in a meadow, who—/at his master's voice—seizes up to a stunned / but instant halt."1 We are then invited to picture his muscles rippling even when at rest, to see in that rippling an immense power purposely held back. Blessed are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Public Proper Names, Idiolectal Identifying Descriptions.Stavroula Glezakos - 2009 - Linguistics and Philosophy 32 (3):317-326.
    Direct reference theorists tell us that proper names have no semantic value other than their bearers, and that the connection between name and bearer is unmediated by descriptions or descriptive information. And yet, these theorists also acknowledge that we produce our name-containing utterances with descriptions on our minds. After arguing that direct reference proponents have failed to give descriptions their due, I show that appeal to speaker-associated descriptions is required if the direct reference portrayal of speakers wielding and referring (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  8
    ‘To give an imagination to the listeners’: The neglected poetics of Navajo ideophony.Anthony K. Webster - 2008 - Semiotica 2008 (171):343-365.
    Ideophony is a neglected aspect of investigations of world poetic traditions. This article looks at the use of ideophony in a variety of Navajo poetic genres. Examples are given from Navajo place-names, narratives, and songs. A final example involves the use of ideophony in contemporary written Navajo poetry. Using the work of Woodbury, Friedrich, and Becker it is argued that ideophones are an example of form-dependent expression, poetic indeterminacy, and the inherent exuberances and deficiencies of translation and thus strongly (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 989