Results for ' deontic value'

983 found
Order:
  1.  89
    Feeling Wronged: The Value and Deontic Power of Moral Distress.Carla Bagnoli - 2021 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (1):89-106.
    This paper argues that moral distress is a distinctive category of reactive attitudes that are taken to be part and parcel of the social dynamics for recognition. While moral distress does not demonstrate evidence of wrongdoing, it does emotionally articulate a demand for normative attention that is addressed to others as moral providers. The argument for this characterization of the deontic power of moral distress builds upon two examples in which the cognitive value of the victim’s emotional experience (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Deontic alternative worlds and the truth-value of 'OA'.K. Solt - 1984 - Logique Et Analyse 27 (7):349.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3. On Deontic Truth and Values.J. J. Moreso - 2017 - Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía 49 (146):61-74.
    This article analyzes the thesis of ethical relativism, as defended by Alchourrón and Bulygin. These authors offer, on the one hand, a suggestive conception according to which the question “what are our obligations?” is equivalent to thinking about what is to be done; on the other hand, they defend a relativist conception of ethics. They present three objections to constructivist accounts of ethics that are not relativist: a) the argument of the burden of the proof; b) a version of the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  58
    A three-valued calculus for deontic logic.Mark Fisher - 1961 - Theoria 27 (3):107-118.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  18
    Deontic Justice and Organizational Neuroscience.William J. Becker, Sebastiano Massaro & Russell S. Cropanzano - 2017 - Journal of Business Ethics 144 (4):733-754.
    According to deontic justice theory, individuals often feel principled moral obligations to uphold norms of justice. That is, standards of justice can be valued for their own sake, even apart from serving self-interested goals. While a growing body of evidence in business ethics supports the notion of deontic justice, skepticism remains. This hesitation results, at least in part, from the absence of a coherent framework for explaining how individuals produce and experience deontic justice. To address this need, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6.  22
    Deontic meaning making in legislative discourse.Jian Li & Winnie le ChengCheng - 2016 - Semiotica 2016 (209):323-340.
    Modality and negation, as two important linguistic features used to realise subjectivity, have been investigated within various disciplines, such as logic, linguistics and philosophy, and law. The interaction between modality and negation, as a relatively new and undeveloped domain, has however not been paid due attention in scholarship. This corpus-based study investigates three aspects of their interaction: the differentiation of the deontic value by negation, the categorization of deontic modality in Hong Kong legislation via negation, and distribution (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  6
    Naturalizating Morality. From Alethic to Deontic and Axiological Values: The Case of Tocar, a Colombian Spanish Verb.Jonathan Restrepo Rodas, Laura Niño Buitrago & Mercedes Suárez - 2022 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 20:77-99.
    Great thinkers have devoted to explaining morality and ethics in human beings. The major reflections have resulted in a well-known dichotomy, that of matters of fact and matters of value, or what is known as the theoretical world, which is objective, and the practical world, that of affections. With the birth of analytic philosophy, the emphasis is placed on language allowing to explain philosophical problems, such as validity. This study proposes the following thesis: it is possible to derive “ought” (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Flexible Contextualism about Deontic Modals: A Puzzle about Information-Sensitivity.J. L. Dowell - 2013 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 56 (2-3):149-178.
    According to a recent challenge to Kratzer's canonical contextualist semantics for deontic modal expressions, no contextualist view can make sense of cases in which such a modal must be information-sensitive in some way. Here I show how Kratzer's semantics is compatible with readings of the targeted sentences that fit with the data. I then outline a general account of how contexts select parameter values for modal expressions and show, in terms of that account, how the needed, contextualist-friendly readings might (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  9. Deontic Constraints are Maximizing Rules.Matthew Hammerton - 2020 - Journal of Value Inquiry 54 (4):571-588.
    Deontic constraints prohibit an agent performing acts of a certain type even when doing so will prevent more instances of that act being performed by others. In this article I show how deontic constraints can be interpreted as either maximizing or non-maximizing rules. I then argue that they should be interpreted as maximizing rules because interpreting them as non-maximizing rules results in a problem with moral advice. Given this conclusion, a strong case can be made that consequentialism provides (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  67
    Deontic Logic: A Personal View.Georg Henrik Von Wright - 1999 - Ratio Juris 12 (1):26-38.
    This article contains an overview of the author's long‐standing involvement with deontic logic, both from a technical and from a wider philosophical point of view. As far as the formal aspects of deontic logic are concerned, the author describes his intellectual development from the original discovery of the analogy between modal (and deontic) notions on the one hand, and quantifiers on the other, through the formulation of a systematic theory of dyadic deontic concepts, to the proposal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  11. Consequence and Contrast in Deontic Semantics.Fabrizio Cariani - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy 113 (8):396-416.
    Contrastivists view ought-sentences as expressing comparisons among alternatives. Deontic actualists believe that the value of each alternative in such a comparison is determined by what would actually happen if that alternative were to be the case. One of the arguments that motivates actualism is a challenge to the principle of agglomeration over conjunction—the principle according to which if you ought to run and you ought to jump, then you ought to run and jump. I argue that there is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  12.  22
    Deontic Fallacies and the Arguments against Conscientious Objections.Stephen Napier - 2021 - Christian Bioethics 27 (2):140-157.
    The respect for one’s conscience is rooted in a broader respect for the human person. The conscience represents a person’s ability to identify the values and goods that inform her moral identity. Ignoring or overriding a person’s conscience can lead to significant moral and emotional distress. Refusals to respect a person’s conscientious objection to cases of killing are a source of incisive distress, since judgments that it is impermissible to kill so-and-so are typically held very strongly and serve as central (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  41
    Deontic database constraints, violation and recovery.José Carmo & Andrew J. I. Jones - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):139 - 165.
    The paper discusses the potential value of a deontic approach to database specification. More specifically, some different types of integrity constraints are considered and a distinction is drawn between necessary (hard) and deontic (soft) constraints.Databases are compared with other normative systems. A deontic logic for database specification is proposed and the problems of how to react to, and of how to correct, or repair, a situation which arises through norm violation are discussed in the context of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  45
    On Logic of Strictly-Deontic Modalities. A Semantic and Tableau Approach.Tomasz Jarmużek & Mateusz Klonowski - 2020 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 29 (3):335–380.
    Standard deontic logic (SDL) is defined on the basis of possible world semantics and is a logic of alethic-deontic modalities rather than deontic modalities alone. The interpretation of the concepts of obligation and permission comes down exclusively to the logical value that a sentence adopts for the accessible deontic alternatives. Here, we set forth a different approach, this being a logic which additionally takes into consideration whether sentences stand in relation to the normative system or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  15. Evaluative vs. Deontic Concepts.Christine Tappolet - 2022 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Wiley. pp. 1791-99.
    Ethical thought is articulated around normative concepts. Standard examples of normative concepts are good, reason, right, ought, and obligatory. Theorists often treat the normative as an undifferentiated domain. Even so, it is common to distinguish between two kinds of normative concepts: evaluative or axiological concepts, such as good, and deontic concepts, such as ought. This encyclopedia entry discusses the many differences between the two kinds of concepts.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  16. Deontic reasoning.Ken I. Manktelow & David E. Over - 1995 - Perspectives on Thinking and Reasoning: Essays in Honour of Peter Wason.
    The following values have no corresponding Zotero field: PB - Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Ltd Hove,, UK.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  17.  18
    Deontic Relationship in the Context of Jan Woleński’s Metaethical Naturalism.Rafał Palczewski, Mateusz Klonowski & Tomasz Jarmużek - 2020 - Studia Humana 9 (3-4):120-130.
    In this paper, we indicate how Jan Woleński’s non-linguistic concept of the norm allows us to clarify the deontic relationship between sentences and the given normative system. A relationship of this kind constitutes a component of the metalogic of relating deontic logic, which subjects the logical value of the deontic sentence to the logical value of the constituent sentence and its relationship with a given normative system in the accessible possible worlds.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  27
    Deontic morality and control. Ishtiyaque Haji. Cambridge: Cambridge university press, 2002. Pp. XIV, 288.Michael J. Zimmerman - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):492–495.
    In everyday life it is common to judge people morally responsible for their actions, but there is a time-honored philosophical challenge to this practice with which we are all familiar. The challenge can be put briefly as follows: moral responsibility requires that agents have a certain kind of control that is compatible with neither causal determinism nor its contradictory, causal indeterminism; hence moral responsibility is impossible. Haji notes that judgments about moral responsibility- which I will call hypological judgments—are not the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. The Deontic Quadecagon.Paul F. Mcnamara - 1990 - Dissertation, University of Massachusetts Amherst
    There are a number of concepts of common-sense morality, what one must do, what one ought to do, the supererogatory, the minimum that duty allows, the morally optional and the morally indifferent, that philosophers have been hard-pressed to represent in an integrated conceptual framework. Indeed, many philosophers have despaired at the attempt and concluded that only a fragment of these concepts belong to that fundamental sphere of morality that is the central focus of the ethicist. For example, the traditional scheme, (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  20. Evidence Sensitivity in Weak Necessity Deontic Modals.Alex Silk - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (4):691-723.
    Kolodny and MacFarlane have made a pioneering contribution to our understanding of how the interpretation of deontic modals can be sensitive to evidence and information. But integrating the discussion of information-sensitivity into the standard Kratzerian framework for modals suggests ways of capturing the relevant data without treating deontic modals as “informational modals” in their sense. I show that though one such way of capturing the data within the standard semantics fails, an alternative does not. Nevertheless I argue that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  21. Review: Soren Hallden, On the Logic of `Better.'; Lennart Aqvist, Deontic Logic Based on a Logic of `Better.'; Mark Fisher, A Three-Valued Calculus for Deontic Logic. [REVIEW]E. E. Dawson - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (2):278-281.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  17
    Sören Halldén. On the logic of ‘better.’ Library of Theoria, no. 2. C. W. K. Gleerup, Lund, and Ejnar Munksgaard, Copenhagen, 1957, 112 pp. - Lennart Åqvist. Deontic logic based on a logic of ‘better.’Proceedings of a Colloquium on Modal and Many-valued Logics, Helsinki, 23–26 August, 1962, Acta philosophica Fennica, no. 16, Helsinki1963, pp. 285–290. - Mark Fisher. A three-valued calculus for deontic logic. Theoria , vol. 27 , pp. 107–118. - Lennart Åqvist. Postulate sets and decision procedures for some systems of deontic logic. Theoria , vol. 29 , pp. 154–175. [REVIEW]E. E. Dawson - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (2):278-281.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  26
    Staking our future: deontic long-termism and the non-identity problem.Andreas Mogensen - 2019 - Gpi Working Paper.
    Greaves and MacAskill argue for ​axiological longtermism​, according to which, in a wide class of decision contexts, the option that is ​ex ante best is the option that corresponds to the best lottery over histories from ​t onwards, where ​t ​is some date far in the future. They suggest that a ​stakes-sensitivity argument may be used to derive ​deontic longtermism from axiological longtermism, where deontic longtermism holds that in a wide class of decision contexts, the option one ought (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24. Boulesic logic, Deontic Logic and the Structure of a Perfectly Rational Will.Daniel Rönnedal - 2020 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 27 (2):187–262.
    In this paper, I will discuss boulesic and deontic logic and the relationship between these branches of logic. By ‘boulesic logic,’ or ‘the logic of the will,’ I mean a new kind of logic that deals with ‘boulesic’ concepts, expressions, sentences, arguments and systems. I will concentrate on two types of boulesic expression: ‘individual x wants it to be the case that’ and ‘individual x accepts that it is the case that.’ These expressions will be symbolised by two sentential (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  17
    Deontic Morality and Control. [REVIEW]Michael J. Zimmerman - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):492-495.
    In everyday life it is common to judge people morally responsible for their actions, but there is a time-honored philosophical challenge to this practice with which we are all familiar. The challenge can be put briefly as follows: moral responsibility requires that agents have a certain kind of control that is compatible with neither causal determinism nor its contradictory, causal indeterminism; hence moral responsibility is impossible. Haji notes that judgments about moral responsibility- which I will call hypological judgments—are not the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  11
    Deontic Morality and Control. [REVIEW]Michael J. Zimmerman - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (2):492-495.
    In everyday life it is common to judge people morally responsible for their actions, but there is a time-honored philosophical challenge to this practice with which we are all familiar. The challenge can be put briefly as follows: moral responsibility requires that agents have a certain kind of control that is compatible with neither causal determinism nor its contradictory, causal indeterminism; hence moral responsibility is impossible. Haji notes that judgments about moral responsibility- which I will call hypological judgments—are not the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  79
    The Ramifications of Error Theories about the Deontic.Vuko Andrić - 2015 - Acta Analytica 30 (4):429-445.
    Error theories about practical deontic judgements claim that no substantive practical deontic judgement is true. Practical deontic judgements are practical in the sense that they concern actions, and they are deontic in the sense that they are about reasons, rightness, wrongness, and obligations. This paper assumes the truth of an error theory about practical deontic judgements in order to examine its ramifications. I defend three contentions. The first is that, if so-called fitting-attitude analyses of (...) fail, the truth of some substantive evaluative judgements would not be threatened by the fact that no substantive practical deontic judgment is true. Secondly, in light of the truth of these evaluative judgements, the best thing we could do is to continue to make practical deontic judgements despite the truth of an error theory about practical deontic judgements. My third contention is that, if some evaluative judgements are unaffected by an error theory about practical deontic judgements, then such an error theory will eventually lead us to some version of consequentialism. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Moral relativism and deontic logic.Philip Hugly & Charles Sayward - 1990 - Synthese 85 (1):139 - 152.
    If a native of India asserts "Killing cattle is wrong" and a Nebraskan asserts "Killing cattle is not wrong", and both judgments agree with their respective moralities and both moralities are internally consistent, then the moral relativist says both judgments are fully correct. At this point relativism bifurcates. One branch which we call content relativism denies that the two people are contradicting each other. The idea is that the content of a moral judgment is a function of the overall moral (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Infinite options, intransitive value, and supererogation.Daniel Muñoz - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 178 (6):2063-2075.
    Supererogatory acts are those that lie “beyond the call of duty.” There are two standard ways to define this idea more precisely. Although the definitions are often seen as equivalent, I argue that they can diverge when options are infinite, or when there are cycles of better options; moreover, each definition is acceptable in only one case. I consider two ways out of this dilemma.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  25
    Two approaches to deontic logic.Eric Dayton - 1981 - Journal of Value Inquiry 15 (2):137-147.
  31. Desires, Values and Norms.Olivier Massin - 2017 - In Federico Lauria & Julien Deonna (eds.), The Nature of Desire. Oxford University Press. pp. 352.
    The thesis defended, the “guise of the ought”, is that the formal objects of desires are norms (oughts to be or oughts to do) rather than values (as the “guise of the good” thesis has it). It is impossible, in virtue of the nature of desire, to desire something without it being presented as something that ought to be or that one ought to do. This view is defended by pointing to a key distinction between values and norms: positive and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  9
    Who is Right, Who is Wrong? Interpreting 14 Points of Wilson – A Case Study of Deontic Modals and their Meanings.Marek Mikołajczyk & Aleksandra Matulewska - 2021 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 66 (1):83-103.
    The document titled “14 points of Wilson” was announced by the President of the United States Woodrow Wilson in his speech addressed to the United States Congress on 8th January 1918. The speech is one of the most well known documents of the First World War as it touched upon several world issues. The text has been interpreted ever since in respect to the importance and real meaning of points formulated by Wilson. One of the points referred to Poland. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Doing the right things–trivalence in deontic action logic.Piotr Kulicki & Robert Trypuz - 2012 - Trivalent Logics and Their Applications.
    Trivalence is quite natural for deontic action logic, where actions are treated as good, neutral or bad.We present the ideas of trivalent deontic logic after J. Kalinowski and its realisation in a 3-valued logic of M. Fisher and two systems designed by the authors of the paper: a 4-valued logic inspired by N. Belnap’s logic of truth and information and a 3-valued logic based on nondeterministic matrices. Moreover, we combine Kalinowski’s idea of trivalence with deontic action logic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Having Value and Being Worth Valuing.Sigrún Svavarsdóttir - 2014 - Journal of Philosophy 111 (2):84-109.
    This paper explores the relationship between the ascription of value to an object and an assessment of conative attitudes taken towards that object. It argues that this relationship is captured by an a priori necessary truth that falls out of the mastery conditions for the concept of value: what has value is worth valuing, when valuing is understood to be a relatively stable conative attitude distinct from judging valuable. What kind of assessment of attitude is at stake? (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  35. "The Logic of the Liver". A Deontic View of the Intentionality of Desire.Federico Lauria - 2014 - Dissertation, University of Geneva
    Desires matter. How are we to understand the intentionality of desire? According to the two classical views, desire is either a positive evaluation or a disposition to act: to desire a state is to positively evaluate it or to be disposed to act to realize it. This Ph.D. Dissertation examines these conceptions of desire and proposes a deontic alternative inspired by Meinong. On this view, desiring is representing a state of affairs as what ought to be or, if one (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  24
    Deontic logic and the axoim of necessity: The consequences of a misinterpretation. [REVIEW]L. E. Fleischhacker & J. Kuper - 1982 - Journal of Value Inquiry 16 (1):67-74.
  37.  15
    Fractional-Valued Modal Logic and Soft Bilateralism.Mario Piazza, Gabriele Pulcini & Matteo Tesi - 2023 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 52 (3):275-299.
    In a recent paper, under the auspices of an unorthodox variety of bilateralism, we introduced a new kind of proof-theoretic semantics for the base modal logic \(\mathbf{K}\), whose values lie in the closed interval \([0,1]\) of rational numbers [14]. In this paper, after clarifying our conception of bilateralism – dubbed “soft bilateralism” – we generalize the fractional method to encompass extensions and weakenings of \(\mathbf{K}\). Specifically, we introduce well-behaved hypersequent calculi for the deontic logic \(\mathbf{D}\) and the non-normal modal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Are all practical reasons based on value?Benjamin Kiesewetter - 2022 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 17:27-53.
    According to an attractive and widely held view, all practical reasons are explained in terms of the (instrumental or final) value of the action supported by the reason. I argue that this theory is incompatible with plausible assumptions about the practical reasons that correspond to certain moral rights, including the right to a promised action and the right to an exclusive use of one’s property. The argument is an explanatory rather than extensional one: while the actions supported by the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  39. Value, Reasons, and Oughts.Christine Tappolet - 2005 - In Maria E. Reicher & Johan C. Marek (eds.), Experience and Analysis, The Proceedings of the 27th International Wittgenstein Symposium. Öbv&hpt.
    What’s the relation between values and reasons for action ? According to some all reasons are grounded in values. If one adds to this the thought that values themselves depend on non-evaluative or factual features of things, one gets what one can call after Jonathan Dancy the “layer-cake conception”. According to others, we should replace the layer-cake picture by what he calls the “buck-passing account of values” (Scanlon 1998). The main characteristic of this conception is that it denies that reasons (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Act and value: Expectation and the representability of moral theories.Graham Oddie & Peter Milne - 1991 - Theoria 57 (1-2):42-76.
    According to the axiologist the value concepts are basic and the deontic concepts are derivative. This paper addresses two fundamental problems that arise for the axiologist. Firstly, what ought the axiologist o understand by the value of an act? Second, what are the prospects in principle for an axiological representation of moral theories. Can the deontic concepts of any coherent moral theory be represented by an agent-netural axiology: (1) whatever structure those concepts have and (2) whatever (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  41.  59
    Getting Things Right: Fittingness, Value, and Reasons.Conor McHugh & Jonathan Way - 2022 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    This book has two main aims. First, it develops and defends a constitutive account of normative reasons as premises of good reasoning. This account says, roughly, that to be a normative reason for a response (such as a belief or intention) is to be premise of good reasoning, from fitting responses, to that response. Second, building on the account of reasons, it develops and defends a fittingness-first account of the structure of the normative domain. This account says that there is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  40
    Actions, Values, and States of Affairs in Hildebrand and Reinach.Alessandro Salice - 2015 - Studia Phaenomenologica 15:259-280.
    The present article discusses Dietrich von Hildebrand’s theory of action as presented in his Die Idee der sittlichen Handlung, and focuses on the moral relevance Hildebrand assigns to diff erent kinds of motivations. The act of will which leads to a moral action, Hildebrand claims, can be “founded” or “motivated” in different ways and, in particular, it can be motivated by an act of cognizing or by an act of value-taking. The act of cognizing grasps the state of aff (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  25
    The good, the bad and the right. Formal reductions among deontic concepts.Daniela Glavaničová & Matteo Pascucci - 2021 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 50 (2):151-176.
    The present article provides a taxonomic analysis of bimodal logics of normative ideality and normative awfulness, two notions whose meaning is here explained in terms of the moral values pursued by a given community. Furthermore, the article addresses the traditional problem of a reduction among deontic concepts: we explore the possibility of defining other relevant normative notions, such as obligation, explicit permission and Hohfeldian relations, in terms of ideality and awfulness. Some proposals in this respect, which have been formulated (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  31
    Meinong on the Foundations of Deontic Logic.Seppo Sajama - 1988 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 32 (1):69-81.
    Traditional moral theories appear to be unable to give a credible account of the relationship between deontic and axiological concepts, i.e. duty and value. Of the two traditional solutions to this problem, one emphasises the independence of the two realms, whereas Mill argues that duty is definable in terms of goodness. In this paper I present Meinong's Law of Omission which offers, in my opinion, a promising alternative to these two traditional views.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  10
    Meinong on the Foundations of Deontic Logic.Seppo Sajama - 1988 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 32 (1):69-81.
    Traditional moral theories appear to be unable to give a credible account of the relationship between deontic and axiological concepts, i.e. duty and value. Of the two traditional solutions to this problem, one emphasises the independence of the two realms, whereas Mill argues that duty is definable in terms of goodness. In this paper I present Meinong's Law of Omission which offers, in my opinion, a promising alternative to these two traditional views.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. The Normative and the Evaluative: The Buck-Passing Account of Value.Richard Rowland - 2019 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Many have been attracted to the idea that for something to be good there just have to be reasons to favour it. This view has come to be known as the buck-passing account of value. According to this account, for pleasure to be good there need to be reasons for us to desire and pursue it. Likewise for liberty and equality to be values there have to be reasons for us to promote and preserve them. Extensive discussion has focussed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  47.  35
    That’s Not Fair! How Personal Value for Diversity Influences Reactions to the Perceived Discriminatory Treatment of Minorities.María del Carmen Triana, María Fernanda Wagstaff & Kwanghyun Kim - 2012 - Journal of Business Ethics 111 (2):211-218.
    Using Leventhal’s (Social exchange: Advances in theory and research, Plenum Press, New York, 1980 ) rules of procedural justice as well as deontic justice (Folger in Research in social issues in management, Information Age, Greenwich, CT, 2001 ), we examine how personal value for diversity moderates the negative relationship between perceived discrimination against minorities (i.e., racial minorities and females) at work and the perceived procedural justice of minorities’ treatment by the organization. Through a field survey of 190 employees, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. The insignificance of the distinction between telic and deontic egalitarianism.Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen - 2006 - In Nils Holtug & Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen (eds.), Egalitarianism: New Essays on the Nature and Value of Equality. Clarendon Press.
  49.  97
    A Kantian Reading of 'Good' and 'Good For'. Some Reflections on Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen's Fitting Attitude Analysis of Value.Herlinde Pauer-Studer - 2023 - Value,Morality and Social Reality.
    The paper argues that Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen’s fitting-attitude analysis of ‘good’ and ‘good for’ allows us to interpret and justify Kant’s Formula of Humanity (FH) in a constructive way. His classification of ‘good’ as a non-relational intrinsic final value and ‘good for’ as a relational extrinsic final value sheds light on two main features of FH, namely that it requires us to display a specific attitude to human beings, while also obligating us to recognize this value in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  20
    Getting Things Right: Fittingness, Reasons, and Value.Conor McHugh & Jonathan Way - 2022 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    This book has two main aims. First, it develops and defends a constitutive account of normative reasons as premises of good reasoning. This account says, roughly, that to be a normative reason for a response (such as a belief or intention) is to be premise of good reasoning, from fitting responses, to that response. Second, building on the account of reasons, it develops and defends a fittingness-first account of the structure of the normative domain. This account says that there is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 983