Results for ' authority of rules'

997 found
Order:
  1. Dewey and Dancy and the Moral Authority of Rules.Tom Spector - 2007 - Contemporary Pragmatism 4 (2):65-75.
    Dewey's pragmatist regard for the place of rules in moral deliberation occupies a middle ground between the rejection of rules found in Jonathan Dancy's moral particularism and full scale subsumptivism of actions to rules. Concerning the authority rules should play in one's moral thinking, however, Dewey is closely aligned with the particularists: he rejects their authority over individual cases. This essay takes Dewey's naturalistic approach to the derivation of rules to argue that in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  41
    The authority of moral rules.J. Moreh - 1989 - Theory and Decision 27 (3):257-273.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  12
    The Authority of the Rules of Baseball: The Commissioner as Judge.Stephen G. Utz - 1989 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 16 (1):89-99.
  4. The authority of law: essays on law and morality.Joseph Raz - 1979 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Legitimate authority -- The claims of law -- Legal positivism and the sources of law -- Legal reasons, sources, and gaps -- The identity of legal systems -- The institutional nature of law -- Kelsen's theory of the basic norm -- Legal validity -- The functions of law -- Law and value in adjudication -- The rule of law and its virtue -- The obligation to obey the law -- Respect for law -- A right to dissent? : civil (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  5.  26
    The authority of moral oversight: On the legitimacy of criminal law.Christopher Bennett - 2019 - Legal Theory 25 (3):153-177.
    ABSTRACTAn influential view in recent philosophy of punishment is that the apparatus of criminal justice should be geared at least in part to state censure of wrongdoing. I argue that if it were to be so geared, such an apparatus would make ambitious claims to authority, and that the legitimacy of the relevant state would then depend on whether those claims can be vindicated. This paper looks first at what kind of authority is being claimed by this apparatus. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  12
    The Influence Of Magna Carta Libertatum In The Development Of The Principle Of Rule Of Law.Andrej Bozhinovski - 2015 - Seeu Review 11 (1):175-182.
    The concept of Rule of Law is the cornerstone of the proper functioning of the judicial system in any modern democratic society. It is a basic concept of defined rights and liberties to all persons, which offers protection from arbitrary prosecution and incarceration. This principle was firstly stipulated by the instrument of Magna Carta and it is considered as a key principle for good governance in any modern democratic society. The development of the rule of law principle is personified through (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. The Authority of Formality.Jack Woods - 2018 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 13.
    Etiquette and other merely formal normative standards like legality, honor, and rules of games are taken less seriously than they should be. While these standards are not intrinsically reason-providing in the way morality is often taken to be, they also play an important role in our practical lives: we collectively treat them as important for assessing the behavior of ourselves and others and as licensing particular forms of sanction for violations. This chapter develops a novel account of the normativity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  8.  27
    The problem of rule-following in Michael Oakeshott.Juan Antonio González de Requena Farré - 2021 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 17:289-310.
    The role of rules in our normative practices constitutes a relevant philosophical problema, mainly associated with Wittgenstein’s philosophy, but to which Michael Oakeshott has also attempted to answer. Not surprisingly, some scholars have found parallels between their conceptions of human practices and rule-following. Through an exegesis of the notion and uses of the rule in Oakeshott's works, this article aims to clarify the link between rule-following and normative authorization. In this way, it will be possible to to decide the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  75
    The problem of rule-following in compositional semantics.Tomoji Shogenji - 1995 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 33 (1):97-108.
    One of the central issues in the recent discussion of rule-following has been the apparent gap between the finitude of any facts about the rule-follower and the infinitude of possible applications of rules. In this paper the author argues that the combination of the rule-follower's disposition and explicit directions can fill this gap with respect to the interpretation of individual words, but that the problem of finitude remains a serious threat to compositional semantics for natural language because there are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  79
    The Reason of Rules: Constitutional Political Economy.Geoffrey Brennan & James M. Buchanan - 1985 - Cambridge University Press.
    Societies function on the basis of rules. These rules, rather like the rules of the road, coordinate the activities of individuals who have a variety of goals and purposes. Whether the rules work well or ill, and how they can be made to work better, is a matter of major concern. Appropriately interpreted, the working of social rules is also the central subject matter of modern political economy. This book is about rules - what (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  11. Where an endnote simply gives a reference to what is mentioned in the text, the entry refers to the page of the text: where an endnote introduces fresh references or material, its own page is given. Medieval authors are listed under their Christian names (eg Thomas Aquinas), though not where they are usually known by surnames (for instance, Chaucer).Acta Pauli et Theclae & Theological Rules - 2009 - In John Marenbon (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Boethius. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 343.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  44
    The Role of Rules.Ota Weinberger - 1988 - Ratio Juris 1 (3):224-240.
    . The author conceives rules as action‐determining ideas. They are general and of hypothetical form, and they are of three semantic types: descriptive, technological, and normative rules. The most important categorisation of normative rules is the distinction between rules of behaviour and power‐conferring rules. Both kinds of rules are necessary to establish institutions. Principles are a special kind of normative rules. The social existence of normative rules is connected with their institutionalisation as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  10
    Logics of rule and the politics of exodus: Twenty years of Empire.Joseph Tanke - 2022 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 54 (7):956-963.
    This essay offers a new interpretation of Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri’s landmark work of critical social theory Empire. It develops an account of the politics of exile by situating this political strategy in terms of Hardt and Negri’s claim that it is no longer feasible to confront capitalist power head-on. It attends closely to Hardt and Negri’s account of Empire’s pyramidal structure, and the problems that this structure creates for the multitude’s passage from virtuality to actuality. It criticizes the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  88
    Two concepts of rules.John Rawls & Andrei Korbut - 2013 - Russian Sociological Review 12 (2):16-40.
    In his famous paper John Rawls outlines a version of utilitarianism that takes into account the existing criticism of the utilitarian approach. Author shows that the traditional objections expressed in relation to two test cases of utilitarianism — punishment and promise-keeping — are based on the misunderstanding of utilitarian position, because they don’t make a distinction between justifying a practice and justifying a particular action falling under it. In the case of punishment, there two justifications of it: the retributive view (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  15.  65
    On the epistemic authority of courts.Alex Stein - 2008 - Episteme 5 (3):pp. 402-410.
    This paper uses Carl Ginet's concept of “disinterested justification” to identify the boundaries of the epistemic authority of courts. It claims that courts exercise this authority only in the “interest-free” zone, in which their determinations of disputed facts’ probabilities can be made and justified on epistemic grounds alone. This is not the case with the “interest-laden” domain, where courts allocate risks of error under conditions of uncertainty. This domain is controlled by the risk-allocating evidentiary rules: burdens of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  26
    On the Author of Christ and the Author of The Anti-Christ.Ian Cutler - 2012 - Philo 15 (1):5-18.
    Our world is littered with examples of the cannibalisation by secondary authors of the thoughts of original thinkers, rehashed as rule-books and manuals on how to live our lives. No such distortion of an idea has had the lasting success of Saint Paul’s corruption of the life and thoughts of Jesus of Nazareth—man or myth we’ll never know. Nietzsche’s over quoted remark, “God is dead,” belies his frustration that in 2,000 years, Western civilisation has not invented for itself a new (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  15
    Aristotle on the Authority of the Many: Politics III 11, 1281a40–b21.Antony Hatzistavrou - 2021 - Apeiron 54 (2):203-232.
    In this article I propose a new interpretation of Aristotle’s arguments about the authority of the many at Politics III 11, 1281a40–b21. It consists of the following main tenets. First, the multitude that Aristotle refers to in his arguments should be understood on the model of the multitude which rules in polities and the members of which are accomplished in only a part of political excellence, namely, military excellence. Second, the best citizens with whom he compares that multitude (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  69
    Boomerang defense of rule following.Tomoji Shogenji - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (3):115-122.
    Can there be a good argument for the total denial of rule following? The question concerns the "total" denial, where the targeted rules include those meta-rules presumably required for philosophical argumentation. In this paper the author contends that such a self-undermining argument can never be a good argument even in a "reductio ad absurdum" form, but that the defender of rule following cannot dismiss a challenge on this ground when the opponent adopts "the virus strategy".
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  31
    Interpretation, jurisdiction, and the authority of law.Timothy Endicott - 2007 - American Philosophical Association Newsletter 6:14-19.
    People can be autonomous, if they are subject to authority. In particular, they can be autonomous if they are subject to the authority of law. I defend the first claim through a study of Joseph Raz's compelling account of authority; I claim that his work leads to the conclusion that autonomous judgment is needed to determine the jurisdiction of an authority, and to interpret its directives. I defend the second claim by arguing that law does not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  28
    The unity of rule and virtue: a critique of a supposed parallel between Confucian ethics and virtue ethics.Yuli Liu - 2004 - Singapore: Eastern Universities Press.
    Some philosophers argue that throughout its long history, Confucian ethics have stressed character formation or personal cultivation of virtues. Thus, it seems appropriate to characterise Confucian ethics as ethics of virtue. in this book, the author attempts to critique the apparent similarity and show, on the contrary, that Confucian ethics are better conceived of as a unique kind of ethics, in which rule-based morality and virtues are united. Through a unique analysis of Confucian ethics and comparison between Confucian ethics and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  16
    The Authority of Writing in Plato’s Laws.Shawn Fraistat - 2015 - Political Theory 43 (5):657-677.
    While traditionally Plato has been read as a critic of democracy and an advocate of philosopher-kingship, a number of more recent interpretations have argued that Plato’s views about these issues changed over the course of his life. Several scholars argue that Plato shifts from an authoritarian outlook in “middle period” dialogues, such as the Republic, to a more democratic view in “late” dialogues, such as the Laws. In contrast to these scholars, this article argues that Plato’s attitude towards authority (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  31
    Convention for protection of human rights and dignity of the human being with regard to the application of biology and biomedicine: Convention on human rights and biomedicine.Council of Europe - 1997 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 7 (3):277-290.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Convention for Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with Regard to the Application of Biology and Biomedicine: Convention on Human Rights and BiomedicineCouncil of EuropePreambleThe Member States of the Council of Europe, the other States and the European Community signatories hereto,Bearing in mind the Universal Declaration of Human Rights proclaimed by the General Assembly of the United Nations on 10 December 1948;Bearing in mind the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  23.  30
    Arendt and the Authority of Science in Politics.Robert P. Crease - 2017 - Arendt Studies 1:43-60.
    Arendt’s explorations of the dynamics of politics, facts, and truth in the public sphere contain important insights into the authority of science and science denial. This article reviews and contextualizes Arendt’s views on modern science and technology, discusses her views on authority, and identifies some insights that her writings provide on the dynamics of science denial. Arendt’s writings point to another possible source of authority besides Weber’s three categories (traditional, legal-rational, charismatic), based on a relationship between ruler (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  65
    Political theology: The authority of God.Avishai Margalit - 2005 - Theoria 44 (106):37-50.
    In this article, I will explore an idea of authority as depicted by a religious picture (note the indefinite article). It is a picture, not the picture. It is the picture of God as the supreme decision maker without him being a deliberator. I shall call it the decisionist picture of God. His authority is based on his absolute will unhindered by any laws and rules and in particular by any laws of morality. One may call the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  45
    Normativity and factualism: Wright’s critique of Kripke’s understanding of rules.Michal Sladecek - 2011 - Filozofija I Društvo 22 (1):103-122.
    This paper deals with Wright’s criticism of Kripke’s interpretation of Wittgeinstein and his understanding of the problem of following the rules, and particularly the understanding of a so called skeptical paradox. In the first part of the text, the author gives the basic points of Kripke’s position, whereas the second part examines Wright’s answer to the skeptical solution, that is, Wright’s defense of the objectivity of both the meaning and the connections of rules and their use. The third (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. The Relative Authority of International Law and Courts in the Human Rights and Trade Regimes: A Survey Experiment.Oisin Suttle - manuscript
    This paper presents preliminary results of a survey experiment examining the effects of international illegality on public support for proposed public policies. It adds three specific dimensions to the existing literature. First, it tests whether the effects of international illegality differ depending on the international regime whose rules are violated, testing the effects of violations of both human rights and trade regimes. Second, it tests how far the involvement of international courts vary these effects. And third, it examines these (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  27
    Ought-Sentences and the Juristic Description of Rules.Riccardo Guastini - 1991 - Ratio Juris 4 (3):308-321.
    Abstract.According to the normative theory of legal science, juristic ought‐sentences describe rules, since legal science just deals with rules, and rules cannot be described but by means of ought‐sentences. The author challenges this view. Two different constructions of “describing rules” are proposed: Namely, either interpreting or stating the validity of rules. “Interpreting rules,” in its turn, can be understood in three different senses: listing all the possible meanings of rule‐formulations, reporting the different interpretations a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  48
    The relevance of rules to a critical social science.J. Jeremy Wisnewski - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (4):391-419.
    The aim of this article is to argue for a conception of critical social science based on the model of constitutive rules. The author argues that this model is pragmatically superior to those models that employ notions like "illusion" and " ideology," as it does not demand a specification of the "real (but hidden) interests" of social actors. Key Words: constitutive rules • critical theory • ideology • recommendations • social facts.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  2
    The logic of choice: an investigation of the concepts of rule and rationality.Gidon Gottlieb - 1968 - London,: Allen & Unwin.
    Originally published in 1968. This is a critical study of the concept of 'rule' featuring in law, ethics and much philosophical analysis which the author uses to investigate the concept of 'rationality'. The author indicates in what manner the modes of reasoning involved in reliance upon rules are unique and in what fashion they provide an alternative both to the modes of logico-mathematical reasoning and to the modes of scientific reasoning. This prepares the groundwork for a methodology meeting the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  30.  29
    Politics Is a Mushroom: Worldly Sources of Rule and Exception in Carl Schmitt and Walter Benjamin.Kam Shapiro - 2007 - Diacritics 37 (2/3):121-134.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Politics Is a Mushroom: Worldly Sources of Rule and Exception in Carl Schmitt and Walter BenjaminKam Shapiro (bio)Life is not a mushroom growing out of death.—Carl Schmitt, The Visibility of the ChurchTo isolate death from life, not leaving the one intimately woven in the other, and each one entering into the other’s midst—this is what one must never do.—Jean-Luc Nancy, L’intrus1Carl Schmitt’s theory of the exception was bound up (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  11
    Political Theology: The Authority of God.Avishai Margalit - 2005 - Theoria 52:37-50.
    In this article, I will explore an idea of authority as depicted by a religious picture. It is a picture, not the picture. It is the picture of God as the supreme decision maker without him being a deliberator. I shall call it the decisionist picture of God. His authority is based on his absolute will unhindered by any laws and rules and in particular by any laws of morality. One may call the decisionist picture of God (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  90
    From Shared Agency to the Normativity of Law: Shapiro’s and Coleman’s Defence of Hart’s Practice Theory of Rules Reconsidered.Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco - 2009 - Law and Philosophy 28 (1):59 - 100.
    Colemanand Shapiro have recently advanced a second at- tempt to reconcile Hart’s practice theory of rules and the idea of the normativity of law; i.e., the idea that legal rules qua social rules give reasons for actions and, in some circumstances create and impose duties and obligations. Their argumentative strategy is to resort to elements in Bratman’s work on shared agency and planning, though they introduce important and substantive modifications to Bratman’s own explanation. Bratman describes his own (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  30
    Oakeshott on the Authority of Law.Richard B. Friedman - 1989 - Ratio Juris 2 (1):27-40.
    The author explains Michael Oakeshott's distinctive theory of law through an explanation of its notion of authority. He explains the view that modern states are ambiguous, consisting partly of civil associations and partly of enterprise associations. Authority is not a function of people's attitudes to those in power, but exists when a government's action is itself accepted as sufficient reason for unconditional obedience. Authority in this sense cannot exist in enterprise association, commitment to which must be contingent (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  34. The Rule of St. Benedict and Modern Liberal Authority.Linda Zagzebski - 2010 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 2 (1):65 - 84.
    In this paper I examine the sixth century ’Rule of St. Benedict’, and argue that the authority structure of Benedictine communities as described in that document satisfies well-known principles of authority defended by Joseph Raz. This should lead us to doubt the common assumption that premodern models of authority violate the modern ideal of the autonomy of the self. I suggest that what distinguishes modern liberal authority from Benedictine authority is not the principles that justify (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Rules of Language and First Person Authority.Martin F. Fricke - 2012 - Polish Journal of Philosophy 6 (2):15-32.
    This paper examines theories of first person authority proposed by Dorit Bar-On (2004), Crispin Wright (1989a) and Sydney Shoemaker (1988). What all three accounts have in common is that they attempt to explain first person authority by reference to the way our language works. Bar-On claims that in our language self-ascriptions of mental states are regarded as expressive of those states; Wright says that in our language such self-ascriptions are treated as true by default; and Shoemaker suggests that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36. The Rule of Law in Contemporary Liberal Theory.Jeremy Waldron - 1989 - Ratio Juris 2 (1):79-96.
    Existing accounts of the Rule of Law are inadequate and require fleshing out. The main value of the ideal of rule of law for liberal political theory lies in the notion of predictability, which is essential to individual autonomy. The author examines this connection and argues that conservative theories of rule of law claim too much. Liberal theory equates the rule of law with legality, which is only one of the elements necessary for a just social order.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  37.  14
    Rule-violations sensitise towards negative and authority-related stimuli.Robert Wirth, Anna Foerster, Hannah Rendel, Wilfried Kunde & Roland Pfister - 2017 - Cognition and Emotion 32 (3):480-493.
    Rule violations have usually been studied from a third-person perspective, identifying situational factors that render violations more or less likely. A first-person perspective of the agent that actively violates the rules, on the other hand, is only just beginning to emerge. Here we show that committing a rule violation sensitises towards subsequent negative stimuli as well as subsequent authority-related stimuli. In a Prime-Probe design, we used an instructed rule-violation task as the Prime and a word categorisation task as (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  65
    The Rule of Law and its Limits.Andrei Marmor - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 23 (1):1-43.
    "[W]e must focus on what legalism, per se, means, and then ask why is it a good thing to have. Not less importantly, however, we must also realize that legalism can be excessive. Even if the rule of law is a good thing, too much of it may be bad. So the challenge for a theory of the rule of law is to articulate what the rule of law is, why is it good, and to what extent." "[T]he essense of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  39.  4
    Index of Model Rules and Other Authorities.Daniel Markovits - 2010 - In A Modern Legal Ethics: Adversary Advocacy in a Democratic Age. Princeton University Press. pp. 347-350.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  33
    Rules of Power and the Power of Rules.Roger A. Shiner - 1993 - Ratio Juris 6 (3):279-304.
    The paper describes at length and then discusses critically Frederick Schauer's analysis of rules in his recent book Playing By the RuZes. For most of the book Schauer discusses rules in general, and only at the end talks about legal rules in particular. The chief message of Schauer's analysis is that rules permit, and even constitute, a particular kind of decision‐making, one that quite deliberately insulates the decision‐taker from considerations of what would be in the circumstances (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  7
    The Epistemology of Self-Knowledge and the Presuppositions of Rule-Following.Denis McManus - 1995 - The Monist 78 (4):496-514.
    Phenomena such as our “understanding in a flash” and our immediate knowledge of the meaning of our own utterances seem to point to problems that call for philosophical explanation. Even though the meaning of an utterance appears to depend on where and when we use it, on what we use it for and on what we expect in response, we do not examine such circumstances when asked what we mean. Instead we simply say what we mean. Similarly, our having grasped (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Author's response to peer commentaries: Mexico's rule of law and MRTs.César Palacios-González & María de Jesús Medina-Arellano - 2017 - Journal of Law and the Biosciences 4 (3):623–629.
  43.  62
    The Rule of Law and Its Predicament.Yasuo Hasebe - 2004 - Ratio Juris 17 (4):489-500.
    Purpose of this article is to assess the validity of the Razian conception of the rule of law by subjecting it to the acid test of Michel Troper's 'realist theory of interpretation'. The author argues that, in light of the Wittgensteinian view of rule-following, a serious indeterminacy can be seen as inherent in both this conception of the rule of law and Troper's theory of interpretation.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Rule utilitarianism, rights, obligations and the theory of rational behavior.John C. Harsanyi - 1980 - Theory and Decision 12 (2):115-133.
    The paper first summarizes the author's decision-theoretical model of moral behavior, in order to compare the moral implications of the act-utilitarian and of the rule-utilitarian versions of utilitarian theory. This model is then applied to three voting examples. It is argued that the moral behavior of act-utilitarian individuals will have the nature of a noncooperative game, played in the extensive mode, and involving action-by-action maximization of social utility by each player. In contrast, the moral behavior of rule-utilitarian individuals will have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  45. Demystifying Normativity: Morality, Error Theory, and the Authority of Norms.Eline Gerritsen - 2022 - Dissertation, University of St. Andrews, University of Stirling & University of Groningen
    We are subject to many different norms telling us how to act, from moral norms to etiquette rules and the law. While some norms may simply be ignored, we live under the impression that others matter for what we ought to do. How can we make sense of this normative authority some norms have? Does it fit into our naturalist worldview? Many philosophers claim it does not. Normativity is conceived to be distinct from ordinary natural properties, making it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Justificatory independence: Interpersonal mutuality and the authority of the law.Matthew Smith - unknown
    Can the laws produced by patently illegitimate political institutions be authoritative, or are they like the rules of etiquette – rules we might have conclusive reasons to follow but which are not authoritative?[2] Exclude from the scope of this question laws that recapitulate or contradict independently valid moral principles and so are authoritative in virtue of their content. Let us instead query only whether laws that (i) do not recapitulate or contradict valid moral principles, and (ii) are products (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. The ethics of virtue and the ethics of rules: Complementary or alternative theories?Z. Palovicova - 2003 - Filozofia 58 (6):396-408.
    In the last decades the ethics of virtue became the central issue of ethical research. This leads to the question, whether the ethics of virtue is an alternative or a complementary theory to the deontological ethics. The question then is, whether the ethics of virtue can be fully independent of moral rules and which of the issues of the ethics of virtue can not, due to their specific character, be resolved in the frame of deontological ethics. The attention is (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  22
    `Ruled By the Spirit': Hans Ulrich's Understanding of Political Existence.Bernd Wannenwetsch - 2007 - Studies in Christian Ethics 20 (2):257-272.
    This essay introduces the political thought of Hans G. Ulrich as it is presented in his seminal work Wie Geschöpfe leben. What sets Ulrich's thought apart from most other authors in the field is that his interest is not in an account of community or citizenship, but in the status politicus — the political form of existence that is bestowed on human beings as God's creatures who are called to be `ruled by the spirit' instead of succumbing to any form (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The epistemology of self-knowledge and the presuppositions of rule-following.Denis McManus - 1995 - The Monist 78 (4):496-514.
    Phenomena such as our “understanding in a flash” and our immediate knowledge of the meaning of our own utterances seem to point to problems that call for philosophical explanation. Even though the meaning of an utterance appears to depend on where and when we use it, on what we use it for and on what we expect in response, we do not examine such circumstances when asked what we mean. Instead we simply say what we mean. Similarly, our having grasped (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  85
    Is the rule of recognition really a duty-imposing rule?Laurenz Ramsauer - 2023 - Journal of Legal Philosophy 48 (2):83-102.
    According to a persistent assumption in legal philosophy, the social rule at the foundation of a legal system (the Rule of Recognition) serves both an epistemic and a duty-imposing function. Thus, some authors have claimed that it would be a formidable problem for legal philosophy to explain how such social rules can impose duties, and some have taken it upon themselves to show how social practices might just do that. However, I argue that this orthodox assumption about the dual (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 997