Ought-Sentences and the Juristic Description of Rules

Ratio Juris 4 (3):308-321 (1991)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Abstract.According to the normative theory of legal science, juristic ought‐sentences describe rules, since legal science just deals with rules, and rules cannot be described but by means of ought‐sentences. The author challenges this view. Two different constructions of “describing rules” are proposed: Namely, either interpreting or stating the validity of rules. “Interpreting rules,” in its turn, can be understood in three different senses: listing all the possible meanings of rule‐formulations, reporting the different interpretations a rule‐formulation has in fact received by courts, or ascribing meaning to rule‐formulations. However, the author argues that ought‐sentences are not the proper tools to accomplish such tasks. At the same time, juristic ought‐sentences cannot be understood as validity statements, since they neither mention any rule whatsoever, nor include the term “valid.” Further, if validity‐statements were ought‐sentences, their logical behaviour would reflect the logic of rules themselves. However, as the late Kelsen argued, things do not run this way, since two inconsistent ought‐sentences, if understood as validity statements, can paradoxically both be true, as well as both false. Hence, validity‐statements cannot be reduced to ought‐sentences iterating the rules which they (are supposed to) refer to.

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 91,386

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

On the three types of juristic thought.Carl Schmitt - 2004 - Westport, Conn.: Praeger Publishers. Edited by Joseph W. Bendersky.
Understanding sentences.Charles Sayward - 2000 - Philosophical Investigations 23 (1):48–53.
Scepticism and conditions for description.Peter Zinkernagel - 1968 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 11 (1-4):190 – 204.
Rationality of Methodological Rules.Mihailo Marković - 1981 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 12 (1):3-11.
On not forgetting the epistemology of names.Frank Jackson - 2007 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 74 (1):239-250.
Explicit Henkin sentences.Robert M. Solovay - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):91-93.
Questions.Peter Hanks - 2006 - In Donald M. Borchert (ed.), Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol. 10. Detroit et al.: Thomson Gale. pp. 32-37.
Negation, anti-realism, and the denial defence.Imogen Dickie - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 150 (2):161 - 185.
Order relations among efficient decision rules.Jacob Paroush - 1997 - Theory and Decision 43 (3):209-218.

Analytics

Added to PP
2010-09-11

Downloads
23 (#666,649)

6 months
4 (#800,606)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Citations of this work

Detachment and Deontic Language in Law.Robert Mullins - 2018 - Law and Philosophy 37 (4):351-384.
Assessment sensitivity in legal discourse.Andrej Kristan & Massimiliano Vignolo - 2018 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 61 (4):394-421.
Kelsen's concept of the authority of law.Bruno Celano - 2000 - Law and Philosophy 19 (2):173-199.
¿Profundización O caída Del realismo jurídico como teoría descriptiva de normas?Diego Dei Vecchi - 2017 - Isonomía. Revista de Teoría y Filosofía Del Derecho 47:9-38.

Add more citations

References found in this work

The concept of law.Hla Hart - 1961 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Objective knowledge.Karl Raimund Popper - 1972 - Oxford,: Clarendon Press.
Objective knowledge: an evolutionary approach.Karl Raimund Popper - 1972 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Objective knowledge, an evolutionary approach.Karl R. Popper - 1976 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 166 (1):72-73.
Directives and norms.Alf Ross - 1968 - Clark, NJ: Lawbook Exchange. Edited by Brian Loar.

View all 13 references / Add more references