Results for ' Cartesian psychology'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind.Robert Andrew Wilson - 1995 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book offers the first sustained critique of individualism in psychology, a view that has been the subject of debate between philosophers such as Jerry Fodor and Tyler Burge for many years. The author approaches individualism as an issue in the philosophy of science and by discussing issues such as computationalism and the mind's modularity he opens the subject up for non-philosophers in psychology and computer science. Professor Wilson carefully examines the most influential arguments for individualism and identifies (...)
  2.  24
    Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds.Robert A. Wilson - 1997 - Philosophical Quarterly 47 (188):392-395.
    This book offers a sustained critique of individualism in psychology, a view that has been the subject of debate between philosophers such as Jerry Fodor and Tyler Burge for many years. The author approaches individualism as an issue in the philosophy of science and by discussing issues such as computationalism and the mind's modularity he opens the subject up for non-philosophers in psychology and computer science. Professor Wilson carefully examines the most influential arguments for individualism and identifies the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  3.  44
    Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind.Alva Noë - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):434.
    Perhaps the most influential compatibilist response to this question is Fodor's strategy of levels. Fodor argues that although psychological laws range over world-involving propositional attitudes and their contents, these laws are implemented in computational mechanisms that supervene on the individual's intrinsic states.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  4.  57
    Cartesian Psychology of Antoine Le Grand.Gary Hatfield - 2014 - In Mihnea Dobre & Tammy Nyden (eds.), Cartesian Empiricisms. Springer. pp. 251-274.
    In the Aristotelian curriculum, De anima or the study of the soul fell under the rubric of physics. This area of study covered the vital (“vegetative”), sensitive, and rational powers of the soul. Descartes’ substance dualism restricted reason or intellect, and conscious sensation, to human minds. Having denied mind to nonhuman animals, Descartes was required to explain all animal behavior using material mechanisms possessing only the properties of size, shape, position, and motion. Within the framework of certainty provided by the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5.  30
    Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind.Keith Butler - 1995 - Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 58 (3):723-726.
    This book is an extended discussion of individualism in the philosophy of mind.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6. Cartesian Psychology.Miroslav Popper & Visnovsky Emil - 1996 - Human Affairs 6 (2):121-134.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  24
    Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds. [REVIEW]Keith Butler - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (3):723-726.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  32
    Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds. [REVIEW]Alva Noë - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):434-436.
    Perhaps the most influential compatibilist response to this question is Fodor's strategy of levels. Fodor argues that although psychological laws range over world-involving propositional attitudes and their contents, these laws are implemented in computational mechanisms that supervene on the individual's intrinsic states.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Robert A. Wilson, Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind Reviewed by.Agustin Vicente - 1996 - Philosophy in Review 16 (3):227-229.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Wilson, RA-Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds.J. M. Howarth - 1997 - Philosophical Books 38:55-56.
  11. Robert A. Wilson, Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind.D. Shier - 1996 - Minds and Machines 6:430-434.
  12.  51
    Barbara Hannan, Review of Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind by Robert A. Wilson. [REVIEW]Barbara Hannan - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (3):515-516.
  13.  53
    Review of Robert Andrew Wilson: Cartesian Psychology and Physical Minds: Individualism and the Sciences of the Mind[REVIEW]Gabriel Segal - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (1):151-156.
  14.  10
    Review of Robert A. Wilson: Cartesian psychology and physical minds: Iindividualism and the sciences of mind. [REVIEW]Gabriel Segal - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (1):151--156.
  15.  4
    Cartesian Philosophy and the Flesh: Reflections on Incarnation in Analytical Psychology.Frances Gray - 2012 - Routledge.
    How do you know anything is true? What relation is there between my psyche and your psyche, does one exist? Can we doubt everything or are some things indubitable? What does Jung have to say about body and psyche, body and mind? Cartesian Philosophy and the Flesh is an analysis and critique of interpretations of Cartesian philosophy in analytical psychology. It focuses on readings of Descartes that have important implications for understanding Jung, and analytical and existential (...) generally. Frances Gray's book raises questions about the 'place' of the body in a theory of the human psyche and about what kind of psyche, if any, is essential to concepts of human being. Gray claims that the debates around Descartes and metaphysical dualism have been oversimplified and that this has had a profound effect on conceptualizing an on-going relation between psyche and body. The book also explores the relationship between Jung's conception of the phenomenological standpoint and that of Edmund Husserl and Maurice Merleau-Ponty. Cartesian Philosophy and Flesh brings together Descartes’ idea of self-interrogation and self-reflection and Jung's project in The Red Book, the practice of spiritual exercises is the underpinning orientation of both men. It recommends similar practices to anyone interested in the truths of their own living. Gray’s book will be of interest to Jung scholars, and those with an interest in Jungian studies, Analytical Psychologists and Philosophers. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Cartesian Cogito ergo sum and Kants Criticism of Rational Psychology.John Watson - 1898 - Société Française de Philosophie, Bulletin 2:22.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  56
    The Cartesian Cogito ergo sum and Kant’s Criticism of Rational Psychology.John Watson - 1898 - Kant Studien 2 (1-3):22-49.
  18.  31
    Psychological Doubt and the Cartesian Circle.Morris Lipson - 1989 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (2):225 - 246.
    Suppose that in the Meditations Descartes thinks he needs to prove that his clear and distinct perceptions are true. There can be little doubt that if he does think he needs to do this, he thinks that the way to do it is to prove that ‘a non-deceiving God exists’ is true. Now suppose that Descartes does come up with such a proof. Presumably he clearly and distinctly perceives both the premisses and that ‘a non-deceiving God exists’ follows from them. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Idealizing the Cartesian-Newtonian Paradigm as Reality: The Impact of New-Paradigm Physics on Psychological Theory.J. Wade - 1997 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 56:9-34.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Cartesian scientia and the human soul.Lilli Alanen - 2008 - Vivarium 46 (3):418-442.
    Descartes's conception of matter changed the account of physical nature in terms of extension and related quantitative terms. Plants and animals were turned into species of machines, whose natural functions can be explained mechanistically. This article reflects on the consequences of this transformation for the psychology of human soul. In so far the soul is rational it lacks extension, yet it is also united with the body and affected by it, and so it is able to act on extended (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21. Cartesian critters can't remember.Devin Sanchez Curry - 2018 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 69:72-85.
    Descartes held the following view of declarative memory: to remember is to reconstruct an idea that you intellectually recognize as a reconstruction. Descartes countenanced two overarching varieties of declarative memory. To have an intellectual memory is to intellectually reconstruct a universal idea that you recognize as a reconstruction, and to have a sensory memory is to neurophysiologically reconstruct a particular idea that you recognize as a reconstruction. Sensory remembering is thus a capacity of neither ghosts nor machines, but only of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  14
    Non‐Cartesian Substance Dualism.E. J. Lowe - 2018 - In Jonathan J. Loose, Angus John Louis Menuge & J. P. Moreland (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Substance Dualism. Oxford, U.K.: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 168–182.
    Non‐Cartesian substance dualism is a position in the philosophy of mind concerning the nature of the mind‐body relation or, more exactly, the person‐body relation. Whereas Cartesian substance dualism takes subjects of experience to be necessarily immaterial and indeed nonphysical substances, non‐Cartesian substance dualism does not insist on this. This distinctive feature of non‐Cartesian substance dualism gives it certain advantages over Cartesian dualism, without compelling it to forfeit any of the intuitive appeal that attaches to its (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23. Cartesian conscientia.Boris Hennig - 2007 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (3):455-484.
    Although Descartes is often said to have coined the modern notion of ‘consciousness’, he defines it neither explicitly nor implicitly. This may imply (1) that he was not the first to use ‘conscientia’ in its modern, psychological sense, or (2) that he still used it in its traditional moral sense. In this paper, I argue for the latter assumption. Descartes used ‘conscientia’ according to the meaning we also find in texts of St. Paul, Augustine, Aquinas and later scholastics. Thus the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  24.  62
    Cartesian dualism and the concept of medical placebos.Anthony Campbell - 1994 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 1 (2):230-233.
    Discusses the placebo concept and its purported concealment of a philosophical trap related to Cartesian dualism. The author points out that in discussing the placebo concept there is a temptation to say, in effect, that there is the body, which is a physiological system on which drugs and other medical treatments are supposed to operate, and there is the mind, which can be affected by suggestion to produce a spurious effect. Within this context, the author discusses the notion of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Cartesian Dualism.Charles Champe Taliaferro - 1984 - Dissertation, Brown University
    "Cartesian Dualism" is a systematic examination of a version of mind-body dualism in light of recent work in the philosophy of mind and the theory of reference. I analyze Descartes' modal argument for dualism and argue that some of the principal objections against dualism are not decisive. The thesis is divided into five sections. ;The first section sets forth the main features of Descartes' ontology and his theory of mind. I defend Descartes' theory of individuation and discuss recent conceptions (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Two cartesian arguments for the simplicity of the soul.Dean Zimmerman - 1991 - American Philosophical Quarterly 28 (3):127-37.
    The most well-known arguments for the simplicity of the soul - i.e., for the thesis that the subject of psychological states must be an unextended substance -are based upon the logical possibility of disembodiment. Descartes introduced this sort of argument into modern philosophy, and a version of it has been defended recently by Richard Swinburne. Some of the underlying assumptions of both arguments are examined and defended, but a closer look reveals that each depends upon unjustified inferences from the conceivability (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  27. Cartesian Consciousness Reconsidered.Alison Simmons - 2012 - Philosophers' Imprint 12.
    Descartes revolutionized our conception of the mind by identifying consciousness as the mark of the mental: all and only thoughts are conscious. Today the idea that all thoughts are conscious seems obviously wrong. Worse, however, Descartes himself seems to posit a whole host of unconscious thoughts. Something is not as it seems. Either Descartes is remarkably inconsistent, or his claim that all thought is conscious is more nuanced than it appears. In this paper I argue that while Descartes was indeed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  28.  46
    Cartesian Optics and the Geometrization of Nature.Nancy L. Maull - 1978 - Review of Metaphysics 32 (2):253 - 273.
    Significantly, Berkeley, in his Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision, leveled a sustained attack on just this geometrical theory of distance perception. At first glance it may seem, as it did to Berkeley, that Descartes’ geometrical theory is produced by a simple error: namely, by the idea that a physiological optics provides an adequate description of the psychological processes of judging distances. In truth, this is the weakest of Berkeley’s objections to Descartes’ theory. Obviously we do not see the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  29.  33
    The Cartesian doctor, François Bayle (1622–1709), on psychosomatic explanation.Patricia Easton - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 42 (2):203-209.
    There are two standing, incompatible accounts of Descartes’ contributions to the study of psychosomatic phenomena that pervade histories of medicine, psychology, and psychiatry. The first views Descartes as the father of “rational psychology” a tradition that defines the soul as a thinking, unextended substance. The second account views Descartes as the father of materialism and the machine metaphor. The consensus is that Descartes’ studies of optics and motor reflexes and his conception of the body-machine metaphor made early and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Cartesian scientia and the human soul.Lilli Alanen - 2008 - In Dominik Perler (ed.), Transformations of the soul: Aristotelian psychology, 1250-1650. Boston: Brill.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  5
    Cartesian Psychophysics and the Whole Nature of Man: On Descartes’s Passions of the Soul.Richard F. Hassing - 2015 - Lanham: Lexington Books.
    This book describes Descartes's The Passions of the Soul as a foundational work of the Enlightenment, a precursor of later notions of the historicity of the human, and the first psychology of modern type: to understand and heal ourselves, we look not outward at the world in immediate relation to it, but inward, at the self, its brain, and its past history. Special attention is given to Descartes’s account of imagination and its problematic impact on passion and volition.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  32. The cartesian circle.Lynn E. Rose - 1965 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 26 (1):80-89.
    This paper suggests that the appearance of circularity in descartes' arguments is due to a lack of precision in his statements of them, Rather than to any flaw in his reasoning. The clear and distinct perceptions presupposed in the demonstrations of the existence of God are not the same as those whose reliability depends upon the existence of god. He is presupposing the reliability only of those clear and distinct perceptions which are known through the light of nature and have (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33. Cartesian Epistemology without Cartesian Dreams? Commentary on Jennifer Windt's Dreaming.Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa - 2018 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 25 (5-6):30-43.
    Jennifer Windt’s Dreaming is an enormously rich and thorough book, developing illuminating connections between dreaming, the methodology of psychology, and various philosophical subfields. I’ll focus on two epistemological threads that run through the book. The first has to do with the status of certain assumptions about dreams. Windt argues that the assumptions that dreams involve experiences, and that dream reports are reliable — are methodologically necessary default assumptions, akin to Wittgensteinian hinge propositions. I’ll suggest that Windt is quietly pre-supposing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Descartes, the cartesian circle, and epistemology without God.Michael Della Rocca - 2005 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (1):1–33.
    This paper defends an interpretation of Descartes according to which he sees us as having normative (and not merely psychological) certainty of all clear and distinct ideas during the period in which they are apprehended clearly and distinctly. However, on this view, a retrospective doubt about clear and distinct ideas is possible. This interpretation allows Descartes to avoid the Cartesian Circle in an effective way and also shows that Descartes is surprisingly, in some respects, an epistemological externalist. The paper (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  35.  18
    Foundations of Cartesian Ethics.Vance G. Morgan - 1994 - Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanity Books.
    "One of the expected fruits of Descartes' philosophical enterprise is "the highest and most perfect moral system," a system which, organically developed from its metaphysical and physical foundations, will provide the moral agent with direction and purpose in each of life's contingencies. Yet, Descartes' published work contains no such moral system, and commentators have generally agreed that Descartes "has entered the history of philosophy as perhaps the only systematic philosopher of the first rank who failed to provide any methodical treatment (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  36. The cartesian circle.Dugald Murdoch - 1999 - Philosophical Review 108 (2):221-244.
    This paper suggests that the appearance of circularity in descartes' arguments is due to a lack of precision in his statements of them, Rather than to any flaw in his reasoning. The clear and distinct perceptions presupposed in the demonstrations of the existence of God are not the same as those whose reliability depends upon the existence of god. He is presupposing the reliability only of those clear and distinct perceptions which are known through the light of nature and have (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  16
    From Descartes to Cartesian cognitive science: Timothy van Gelder’s and Michael Wheeler’s analyses.Sandrine Roux - 2018 - Methodos 18.
    Dans cet article, nous proposons d’examiner certains des usages qui sont faits de Descartes en sciences cognitives. Il s’agit plus précisément de s’attacher à la façon dont se trouve pensé l’héritage du cartésianisme dans la science cognitive orthodoxe, souvent conçue comme « cartésienne ». Comment en vient-on à former cette idée de science cognitive cartésienne? Nous répondons en nous appuyant sur deux analyses, celles de Timothy van Gelder et de Michael Wheeler, avec pour objectif de mettre au jour les aspects (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Hylomorphism and Post-Cartesian Philosophy of Mind.William Jaworski - 2006 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80:209-224.
    Descartes developed a compelling characterization of mental and physical phenomena which has remained more or less canonical for Western philosophy ever since. The greatest testament to the power of Cartesian thinking is its ubiquity. Even philosophers who are critical of post-Cartesian anthropology (philosophers,for instance, who are self-professed exponents of one or another form of hylomorphism) nevertheless tacitly endorse Cartesian assumptions. Part of what leads to this strange inconsistency is that by and large philosophers no longer know what (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39. Descartes' Mind‐Body Composites, Psychology and Naturalism.Lilli Alanen - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (5):464 – 484.
    This paper reflects on the status of Descartes' notion of the mind-body union as an object of knowledge in the framework of his new philosophy of nature, and argues that it should be taken seriously as representing a third kind of real thing or reality—that of human nature. Because it does not meet the criteria of distinctness that the two natures composing it—those of thinking minds and extended bodies— meet, the phenomena referred to it, which are objects of psychology (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  40.  11
    Commentary on "Non-Cartesian Frameworks".James Phillips - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (3):187-189.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Non-Cartesian Frameworks”James Phillips (bio)Whither psychoanalytic theory and practice? This is the question raised by Louis Berger as he confronts psychoanalysis’s response to the collapse of Cartesianism that has shaken the foundations of other humanist disciplines (as well as the natural sciences) and has finally caught up with Freud’s heirs. Anyone wanting evidence of this shakeup in psychoanalysis need only consult the final 1994 issue of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  17
    Hylomorphism and Post-Cartesian Philosophy of Mind.William Jaworski - 2006 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 80:209-224.
    Descartes developed a compelling characterization of mental and physical phenomena which has remained more or less canonical for Western philosophy ever since. The greatest testament to the power of Cartesian thinking is its ubiquity. Even philosophers who are critical of post-Cartesian anthropology nevertheless tacitly endorse Cartesian assumptions. Part of what leads to this strange inconsistency is that by and large philosophers no longer know what a non-Cartesian anthropology looks like. I discuss some commitments characteristic of post- (...) philosophy of mind, and present an alternative conception of psychological phenomena more consistent with a hylomorphic framework. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  37
    Rethinking the Cartesian theory of linguistic productivity.Pauli Brattico & Lassi Liikkanen - 2009 - Philosophical Psychology 22 (3):251-279.
    Descartes argued that productivity, namely our ability to generate an unlimited number of new thoughts or ideas from previous ones, derives from a single undividable source in the human soul. Cognitive scientists, in contrast, have viewed productivity as a modular phenomenon. According to this latter view, syntactic, semantic, musical or visual productivity emerges each from their own generative engines in the human brain. Recent evidence has, however, led some authors to revitalize the Cartesian theory. According to this view, a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  46
    The trapped infinity: Cartesian volition as conceptual nightmare.Edward S. Reed - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (1):101-121.
    Abstract Descartes's theory of volition as expressed in his Passions of the Soul is analyzed and outlined. The focus is not on Descartes's proposed answers to questions about the nature and processes of volition, but on his way of formulating questions about the nature of volition. It is argued that the assumptions underlying Descartes's questions have become ?intellectual strait?jackets? for all who are interested in volition: neuroscientists, philosophers and psychologists. It is shown that Descartes's basic assumption?that volition causes change in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  12
    Commentary on "Non-Cartesian Frameworks".Rom Harre - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (3):185-186.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Non-Cartesian Frameworks”Rom Harré (bio)There are three points in Dr. Berger’s paper that seem to me to call for immediate comment:1. There is the familiar (but in Berger’s case, only a partial) misunderstanding of the upshot of the third phase of Wittgenstein’s private-language argument. Having shown that expressive and descriptive discourse are radically different, and that expressive discourse can be learned only in contexts of action in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  43
    Philosophy and the good life: reason and the passions in Greek, Cartesian, and psychoanalytic ethics.John Cottingham - 1998 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    Can philosophy enable us to lead better lives through a systematic understanding of our human nature? John Cottingham's thought-provoking study examines three major philosophical approaches to this problem. Starting with the attempts of Classical philosophers to cope with the recalcitrant forces of the passions, he moves on to examine the moral psychology of Descartes, and concludes by analyzing the insights of modern psychoanalytic theory into the human predicament. His study provides a fresh and challenging perspective on moral philosophy and (...)
  46.  45
    The Madness and Genius of Post-Cartesian Philosophy: A Distant Mirror.George E. Atwood, Robert D. Stolorow & Donna M. Orange - 2011 - Psychoanalytic Review 98 (3):363-285.
    If the task of a post-Cartesian psychoanalysis is understood as one of exploring the patterns of emotional experience that organize subjective life, one can recognize that this task is pursued within a framework of delimiting assumptions concerning the ontology of the person. In this paper, we discuss these assumptions as they have emerged in the thinking of four major philosophers on whom we have drawn: Søren Kierkegaard, Friedrich Nietzsche, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Martin Heidegger. Our purpose in what follows is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  28
    Psychology's Dilemma: To Explain or To Understand.James A. Beshai - 1971 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 1 (2):209-223.
    At one time behavioristic psychology depreciated the value of introspection and descriptive observation in an attempt to exorcise the ghosts of mentalism and introspectionism. The roots of this bias were traced to a Cartesian dualism of subject and object. Behavioristic research has typically concentrated on a specific kind of data requiring the controls of a detached third-person observer. Its findings have been far removed from the concrete "lived world" of the subject, notwithstanding the sophistication and utility of its (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  27
    Psychology in Philosophy: Historical Perspectives.Gary Hatfield - 2009 - In Sara Heinamaa & Martina Reuter (eds.), Psychology and Philosophy: Inquiries into the Soul from Late Scholasticism to Contemporary Thought. Springer. pp. 1-25.
    The chapter examines some common assumptions regarding the shape of the history of theories of mind. It questions the conception that the Scientific Revolution resulted in placing the mind “outside of nature.” During the seventeenth century, the followers of Descartes routinely placed study of the mind, or, at least, mind–body interaction, within “physics” considered as a science of nature in general (and so including physics in the narrow sense, biology, and psychology). By the end of the eighteenth century, many (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49. The Child as a Cartesian Thinker: Children's Reasonings About Metaphysical Aspects of Reality.Eugene Subbotsky - 1996 - New York: Psychology Press.
    Originally published in 1996, this book presents and analyses children’s reasonings about fundamental metaphysical problems. The first part describes dialogues with children that were constructed on the basis of Descartes’ _Mediations on First Philosophy_ and which look at children’s ideas about the relationships between true and false knowledge, mental images and physical objects, mind and body, personal existence and the external world, dreams and reality, and the existence of the Supreme Being, among others. The second part of the book draws (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  39
    World, Affectivity, Trauma: Heidegger and Post-Cartesian Psychoanalysis.Robert D. Stolorow - 2011 - Routledge.
    Stolorow and his collaborators' post-Cartesian psychoanalytic perspective – intersubjective-systems theory – is a phenomenological contextualism that illuminates worlds of emotional experience as they take form within relational contexts. After outlining the evolution and basic ideas of this framework, Stolorow shows both how post-Cartesian psychoanalysis finds enrichment and philosophical support in Heidegger's analysis of human existence, and how Heidegger's existential philosophy, in turn, can be enriched and expanded by an encounter with post-Cartesian psychoanalysis. In doing so, he creates (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000