Results for 'Goldstick, Dan'

992 found
Order:
  1.  25
    What Are "Purely Qualitative" Terms?Dan Goldstick - 1986 - American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (1):71 - 81.
  2. Activism and Scientism in the Interpretation of Karl Marx's First and Third Theses on Feuerbach.Dan Goldstick - 1976 - Philosophical Forum 8 (2):269.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  5
    Critical notice.Dan Goldstick - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (2):357-372.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  32
    "Soundness" Unsound.Dan Goldstick - 1999 - Informal Logic 19 (1).
  5.  29
    Critical Notice of Sebastiano Timpanaro, On Materialism. [REVIEW]Dan Goldstick - 1979 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (2):357-372.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  19
    Cognitive Synonymy.D. Goldstick - 1980 - Dialectica 34 (3):183-203.
    SummaryThe crux of Quine's argument against synonymy— and therewith for a version of pragmatism, and independent/y against mentalism — is his challenge to the other side to explain the behavioural difference between the disposition to employ two predicates, say, interchangeably because of habitually “believing“ them coextensive, and the disposition to do so because of “meaning” the same by each. Since synonymy is taught behaviourally, the distinction in question must make a difference behaviourally, but not necessarily one explainable wholly non‐mentalistically. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  7.  14
    Can a Thought's Whole Subject-Matter Be Itself? The Case of Pain.D. Goldstick - 2024 - Dialogue 63 (1):139-145.
    RésuméLa croyance que l'on est (ou pas) dans un état de douleur est singulière en ceci qu'elle semble pouvoir être qualifiée d'infaillibilité ou d'incorrigibilité logique, de même que le cogito. Mais comment se peut-il que l'existence d'une croyance (vraie) et l'existence du fait qui est l'objet de cette croyance puisssent constituer la même existence? Je propose ici une réponse à cette question. Parfois, une croyance peut être un désir.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  10
    In Defence of David Armstrong's Materialist Theory of Perception.D. Goldstick - 2021 - Dialogue 60 (2):379-394.
    RÉSUMÉLes qualia n'existent pas. La différence phénoménologique entre voir et imaginer, c'est que les propositions auxquelles l'expérient commence à croire dans le premier cas sont uniquement considérées dans le second. Nous pouvons savoir «quel effet cela fait d’être une chauve-souris» en sachant que leur faculté d’écholocation les informe non-inférentiellement des formes, grandeurs, et distances directionnelles des surfaces à proximité. Toutefois, les termes désignant les qualités secondes (comme les couleurs) sont les noms des propriétés-types qu'ils désignent, et dérivent causalement d'un «baptême» (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  17
    Review of Dan Goldstick, Reason, Truth, and Reality[REVIEW]Peter Tramel - 2010 - Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2010 (1).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Self-awareness and alterity: a phenomenological investigation.Dan Zahavi - 1999 - Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press.
    ... Let me start my investigation by taking a brief look at the way in which self-awareness is expressed linguistically, as in the sentences "I am tired" or ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   216 citations  
  11. Merleau-Ponty on Husserl: A Reappraisal.Dan Zahavi - 2002 - In Ted Toadvine & Lester E. Embree (eds.), Merleau-Ponty on Husserl: A Reappraisal. Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    If one comes to Phénoménologie de la perception after having read Sein und Zeit (or Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs) one will be in for a surprise. Both works contain a number of both implicit and explicit references to Husserl, but the presentation they give is so utterly different, that one might occasionally wonder whether they are referring to the same author. Thus nobody can overlook that Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation of Husserl differs significantly from Heidegger’s. It is far more charitable. In (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  12. Faultless Disagreement.Dan Zeman - 2020 - In Martin Kusch (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Relativism. Routledge. pp. 486-495.
    In this entry, I tackle the phenomenon known as "faultless disagreement", considered by many authors to pose a challenge to the main views on the semantics of subjective expressions. I first present the phenomenon and the challenge, then review the main answers given by contextualist, absolutist and relativist approaches to the expressions in question. I end with signaling two issues that might shape future discussions about the role played by faultless disagreement in semantics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  13.  40
    The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology.Dan Zahavi (ed.) - 2012 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology presents twenty-eight essays by some of the leading figures in the field, and gives an authoritative overview of the type of work and range of topics found and discussed in contemporary phenomenology. It is the definitive guide to what is currently going on in phenomenology, and offers a rich source of insight and stimulation for philosophers, students of philosophy, and for people working in other disciplines of the humanities, social sciences, and sciences, who are (...)
  14. Thinking about consciousness: Phenomenological perspectives.Dan Zahavi - 2006 - In Uriah Kriegel & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Self-Representational Approaches to Consciousness. MIT Press.
  15. Relativism and Retraction: The Case Is Not Yet Lost.Dan Zeman - manuscript
    Many times, what we say proves to be wrong. It might turn out that what we took to be a comforting remark was, in fact, making things worse. Or that a joke was inappropriate. Or that yelling out loud was rude. More importantly for this paper, there are plenty of cases in which what we said turns out to be false: we spoke without paying attention, we were misinformed or tricked, or we made a reasoning mistake. -/- A particular instance (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  59
    Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology.Dan Zahavi (ed.) - 2018 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The Oxford Handbook of the History of Phenomenology contains thirty-seven new essays by leading scholars in the field. The essays all highlight historical influences, connections, and developments and provide an in-depth coverage of the development of phenomenology; one that allows for a better comprehension and assessment of the continuity as well as diversity of the phenomenological tradition. The handbook is divided into three distinct parts. The first part contains chapters that address the way phenomenology has been influenced by earlier periods (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17. Merleau-ponty's reading of Husserl.Dan Zahavi - 2002 - In Ted Toadvine & Lester E. Embree (eds.). Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 3-30.
  18.  91
    A contribution towards the development of the causal theory of knowledge.D. Goldstick - 1972 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):238-248.
    1 Cf. D. M. Armstrong, A Materialist Theory of Mind (London, 1968), Chapter 9; 'A Causal Theory of Knowledge' by Alvin I. Goldman, The Journal of Philosophy , Vol. LXIV, No. 12, June 22, 1967. A striking parallelism would appear to exist between 'the causal theory of knowledge' and the orthodox Stoic doctrine regarding the kataleptike phantasia . See, for example, Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos 7.248 (reprinted in Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta , edited by H. F. A. von Arnim, Leipzig, 1921, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  75
    The 'Two Hats' Problem in Consequentialist Ethics.D. Goldstick - 2002 - Utilitas 14 (1):108.
    A largely deontological conscience will probably optimize consequences. But Bernard Williams objects to the, if one therefore embraces indirect consequentialism, of. Admittedly the strategy is painful, and a counsel of imperfection at best. But it need not be psychologically impossible, inconsistent, or even self-deceptive, given ethical cognitivism.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  33
    Beliefs, Desires and Moral Realism.Daniel Goldstick - 2006 - Philosophy 81 (315):153 - 160.
    An argument against the claim that moral realism cannot be sustained because moral beliefs, being affective-conative states, cannot themselves be true or false. In fact moral claims can fail both in terms of a failure of the standard it expresses to be realised by a given agent and also in terms of whatever it commends to be good or bad, right or wrong, in actual fact.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  22
    Property Identity and 'Intrinsic' Designation.D. Goldstick - 1997 - Philosophy 72 (281):449 - 452.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  13
    The Welfare of the Dead.D. Goldstick - 1988 - Philosophy 63 (243):111 - 113.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  52
    Cognitive reason.D. Goldstick - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1):117-124.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  6
    Cognitive Reason.D. Goldstick - 1992 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52 (1):117-124.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  30
    On what there is.D. Goldstick - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (3):313–320.
    Dispositions depend on "categorical" facts definitionally and pedagogically. Must they always depend on them also ontologically for "grounding"? Does there really have to be an ultimate "bottom level" of matter, and must it be "categorical"? The concepts microphysics supplies, however, are dispositional in meaning. What predicates aren't? Besides "shaping" and "locating" predicates, predicates expressing degrees of similarity and dissimilarity are nondispositional enough in meaning: but the predication of all these features of things depends upon other features for these to bound (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  35
    On what there is (in space).D. Goldstick - 2008 - Philosophy 83 (3):353-357.
    Dispositions depend on "categorical" facts definitionally and pedagogically. Must they always depend on them also ontologically for "grounding"? Does there really have to be an ultimate "bottom level" of matter, and must it be "categorical"? The concepts microphysics supplies, however, are dispositional in meaning. What predicates aren't? Besides "shaping" and "locating" predicates, predicates expressing degrees of similarity and dissimilarity are nondispositional enough in meaning: but the predication of all these features of things depends upon other features for these to bound (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  11
    On What There Is.D. Goldstick - 2008 - Philosophy 83 (3):353-357.
    Dispositions depend on “categorical” facts definitionally and pedagogically. Must they always depend on them also ontologically for “grounding”? Does there really have to be an ultimate “bottom level” of matter, and must it be “categorical”? The concepts microphysics supplies, however, are dispositional in meaning. What predicates aren't? Besides “shaping” and “locating” predicates, predicates expressing degrees of similarity and dissimilarity are nondispositional enough in meaning: but the predication of all these features of things depends upon other features for these to bound (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  10
    On What There Is.D. Goldstick - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (3):313-320.
    This paper programmatically outlines a case for “nominalism”. If brown and colored are so related logically that being colored is nothing over and above being brown, then whatever “exists”other than concreta is nothing over and above concreta. Possibilities of rain and “universals” like the shape, circularity (= the logical possibility of being so shaped), lack “existence” in another sense. (“There are things that don't exist” shows that ‘there are’ is used even more broadly than ‘there exist’.) The univocity of ‘exist’ (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  6
    Philosophical abstracts.Daniel Goldstick Belief - 1989 - American Philosophical Quarterly 26 (3).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. A New Old Meaning of “Ideology”.Charles W. Mills & Danny Goldstick - 1989 - Dialogue 28 (3):417-.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31. Knowledge Attributions and Relevant Epistemic Standards.Dan Zeman - 2010 - In François Récanati, Isidora Stojanovic & Neftalí Villanueva (eds.), Context Dependence, Perspective and Relativity. Mouton de Gruyter.
    The paper is concerned with the semantics of knowledge attributions(K-claims, for short) and proposes a position holding that K-claims are contextsensitive that differs from extant views on the market. First I lay down the data a semantic theory for K-claims needs to explain. Next I present and assess three views purporting to give the semantics for K-claims: contextualism, subject-sensitive invariantism and relativism. All three views are found wanting with respect to their accounting for the data. I then propose a hybrid (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  32. Invariantist, Contextualist, and Relativist Accounts of Gender Terms.Dan Zeman - 2020 - EurAmerica 4 (50):739-781.
    In this paper, I explore a range of existent and possible ameliorative semantic theories of gender terms: invariantism, according to which gender terms are not context-sensitive, contextualism, according to which the meaning of gender terms is established in the context of use, and relativism, according to which the meaning of gender terms is established in the context of assessment. I show that none of these views is adequate with respect to the plight of trans people to use their term of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Meaning and relevance.Deirdre Wilson & Dan Sperber - 2012 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by Dan Sperber.
    When people speak, their words never fully encode what they mean, and the context is always compatible with a variety of interpretations. How can comprehension ever be achieved? Wilson and Sperber argue that comprehension is an inference process guided by precise expectations of relevance. What are the relations between the linguistically encoded meanings studied in semantics and the thoughts that humans are capable of entertaining and conveying? How should we analyse literal meaning, approximations, metaphors and ironies? Is the ability to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  34.  36
    I, You, and We: Beyond Individualism and Collectivism.Dan Zahavi - forthcoming - Australasian Philosophical Review.
    The contemporary debate on collective intentionality in analytic philosophy has lasted several decades, but questions concerning the nature of ‘we’ and the relation between the individual and the community are obviously far older. We can find a particularly rich discussion in early phenomenology. Indeed, while starting out with an interest in the individual mind, phenomenologists began their exploration of dyadic forms of interpersonal relations shortly before the start of World War I and were already deeply engaged in extensive analyses of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Rejecting Eco-Authoritarianism, Again.Dan Coby Shahar - 2015 - Environmental Values 24 (3):345-366.
    Ecologically-motivated authoritarianism flourished initially during the 1970s but largely disappeared after the decline of socialism in the late-1980s. Today, 'eco- authoritarianism ' is beginning to reassert itself, this time modelled not after the Soviet Union but modern-day China. The new eco-authoritarians denounce central planning but still suggest that governments should be granted powers that free them from subordination to citizens' rights or democratic procedures. I argue that current eco-authoritarian views do not present us with an attractive alternative to market liberal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36. Intentionality and phenomenality: A phenomenological take on the hard problem.Dan Zahavi - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 29:63-92.
    In his book The Conscious Mind David Chalmers introduced a by now familiar distinction between the hard problem and the easy problems of consciousness. The easy problems are those concerned with the question of how the mind can process information, react to environmental stimuli, and exhibit such capacities as discrimination, categorization, and introspection (Chalmers, 1996, 4, 1995, 200). All of these abilities are impressive, but they are, according to Chalmers, not metaphysically baffling, since they can all be tackled by means (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  37.  34
    Intentionality and Phenomenality: Phenomenological Take on the Hard Problem.Dan Zahavi - 2003 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 33 (sup1):63-92.
    In his bookThe Conscious MindDavid Chalmers introduced a now-familiar distinction between the hard problem and the easy problems of consciousness. The easy problems are those concerned with the question of how the mind can process information, react to environmental stimuli, and exhibit such capacities as discrimination, categorization, and introspection. All of these abilities are impressive, but they are, according to Chalmers, not metaphysically baffling, since they can all be tackled by means of the standard repertoire of cognitive science and explained (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38. Relevance theory.Deirdre Wilson & Dan Sperber - 2002 - In Deirdre Wilson & Dan Sperber (eds.), Relevance theory. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 607-632.
  39.  2
    Testimonial Injustice and the Ideology Which Produces It.Dan Lowe - 2024 - American Philosophical Quarterly 61 (3):215-231.
    Recently, some scholars have argued that testimonial injustice may not only be due to prejudice toward the speaker, but also prejudice toward the content of what the speaker says. I argue that such accounts do not merely expand our picture of epistemic injustice, but give us reason to radically revise our approach to reducing testimonial injustice. The dominant conception of this project focuses on reducing speaker prejudice. But even if one were to successfully do so, the frequency of content prejudice (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Intuitive and reflective beliefs.Dan Sperber - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):67-83.
    Humans have two kinds of beliefs, intuitive beliefs and reflective beliefs. Intuitive beliefs are a most fundamental category of cognition, defined in the architecture of the mind. They are formulated in an intuitive mental lexicon. Humans are also capable of entertaining an indefinite variety of higher-order or "reflective" propositional attitudes, many of which are of a credal sort. Reasons to hold "reflective beliefs" are provided by other beliefs that describe the source of the reflective belief as reliable, or that provide (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  41.  16
    The upside of irrationality: the unexpected benefits of defying logic at work and at home.Dan Ariely - 2010 - New York: Harper.
    行動経済学によって、さまざまに系統的な不合理さが見えてきた。手をかけることが高評価をもたらすIKEA効果、やる気をそいでいる高額ボーナス、自分で思いついた(と思わせられた)意見は好ましい、雑用は一気に 片づけるほうが楽...。行動経済学研究の第一人者が、わたしたちがなぜ、どのように不合理な行動をしてしまうのかをユニークな実験で紹介。わかりやすい数々の実例で経済の真の姿を解明し、よりよい決断へとつなげ る話題作。.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  30
    Intuitive and Reflective Beliefs.Dan Sperber - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):67-83.
    Humans have two kinds of beliefs, intuitive beliefs and reflective beliefs. Intuitive beliefs are a fundamental category of cognition, defined in the architecture of the mind. They are formulated in an intuitive mental lexicon. Humans are also capable of entertaining an indefinite variety of higher‐order or‘reflective’propositional attitudes, many of which are of a credat sort. Reasons to hold reflective beliefs are provided by other beliefs that describe the source of the reflective belief as reliable, or that provide an explicit argument (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  43.  34
    Truer.D. Goldstick & B. O'Neill - 1988 - Philosophy of Science 55 (4):583-597.
    When can one say that a new theory is truer than the old one it contradicts, even though neither is absolutely true? We are primarily concerned with the case in which the conflicting theories offer answers to the same questions, and so we do not introduce considerations of "logical width". We propose that part of the new theory is truer than part of the old one when the former part gets right whatever the latter-part got right while the former does (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  10
    Landscapes of Sociotechnical Imaginaries in Education: A Theoretical Examination of Integrating Artificial Intelligence in Education.Dan Mamlok - forthcoming - Foundations of Science.
    The vision of integrating artificial intelligence in education is part of an ongoing push for harnessing digital solutions to improve teaching and learning. Drawing from Jasanoff and Hasse, this paper deliberates on how sociotechnical imaginaries are interrelated to the implications of new technologies, such as AI, in education. Complicating Hasses’s call for the development of Socratic ignorance to consider our predispositions about new technologies and open new prospects of thought, this paper revisits postphenomenology and Feenberg’s critical constructivist theories. While embracing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  49
    Methodological Conservatism.D. Goldstick - 1971 - American Philosophical Quarterly 8 (2):186 - 191.
  46. The non-identity problem and genetic Harms – the case of wrongful handicaps.Dan W. Brock - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (3):269–275.
    The Human Genome Project will produce information permitting increasing opportunities to prevent genetically transmitted harms, most of which will be compatible with a life worth living, through avoiding conception or terminating a pregnancy. Failure to prevent these harms when it is possible for parents to do so without substantial burdens or costs to themselves or others are what J call “wrongful handicaps”. Derek Parfit has developed a systematic difficulty for any such cases being wrongs — when the harm could be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  47. Self and Other: Exploring Subjectivity, Empathy, and Shame.Dan Zahavi - 2014 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Dan Zahavi engages with classical phenomenology, philosophy of mind, and a range of empirical disciplines to explore the nature of selfhood. He argues that the most fundamental level of selfhood is not socially constructed or dependent upon others, but accepts that certain dimensions of the self and types of self-experience are other-mediated.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   189 citations  
  48.  94
    The Non‐Identity Problem and Genetic Harms – the Case of Wrongful Handicaps.Dan W. Brock - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (3):269-275.
    The Human Genome Project will produce information permitting increasing opportunities to prevent genetically transmitted harms, most of which will be compatible with a life worth living, through avoiding conception or terminating a pregnancy. Failure to prevent these harms when it is possible for parents to do so without substantial burdens or costs to themselves or others are what J call “wrongful handicaps”. Derek Parfit has developed a systematic difficulty for any such cases being wrongs — when the harm could be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  49. Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective.Dan Zahavi - 2005 - Cambridge MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press.
    The relationship of self, and self-awareness, and experience: exploring classical phenomenological analyses and their relevance to contemporary discussions in ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   352 citations  
  50.  31
    Against 'categories'.D. Goldstick - 1974 - Philosophical Studies 26 (5-6):337 - 356.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 992