Results for 'Brooks, Richard'

(not author) ( search as author name )
984 found
Order:
  1. Agency and morality.Richard Brook - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):190-212.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  2.  53
    Berkeley's philosophy of science.Richard J. Brook - 1973 - The Hague,: M. Nijhoff.
    INTRODUCTION Philonous: You see, Hylas, the water of yonder fountain, how it is forced upwards, in a round column, to a certain height, at which it breaks ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  3.  12
    Agency and Morality. [REVIEW]Richard Brook - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (4):190-212.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. George Santayana on Bishop Berkeley. Immaterialism and Life.Richard Brook - 2019 - Limbo, Boletín Internacional de Estudios Sobre Santayana 39:47-65.
    Th e recent revival of Berkeley studies in the last three decades or so make it interesting to look back at George Santayana’s discussion of Berkeley. Th ough Santayana understood the latter’s arguments for immaterialism, he claimed no one could both seriously accept immaterialism, and live, as Berkeley certainly did, an embodied life. As he writes of Berkeley, “Th is idealist was no hermit” (205). Santayana claimed that without matter there was nothing (“no machinery”) for the soul to work on. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Berkeley and the Causality of Ideas; a look at PHK 25.Richard Brook - manuscript
    I argue that Berkeley's distinctive idealism/immaterialism can't support his view that objects of sense, immediately or mediately perceived, are causally inert. (The Passivity of Ideas thesis or PI) Neither appeal to ordinary perception, nor traditional arguments, for example, that causal connections are necessary, and we can't perceive such connections, are helpful. More likely it is theological concerns,e.g., how to have second causes if God upholds by continuously creating the world, that's in the background. This puts Berkeley closer to Malebranche than (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Once more Into the numbers.Richard Brook - manuscript
    Abstract Tom Dougherty observes that challenges to counting the numbers often cite John Taurek’s 1977 article, “Should the Numbers Count.” Dougherty, though sympathetic to Taurek’s (and others) critique of consequentialism’s aggregating good across individuals, defends a non-consequentialist principle for addition he calls “the Ends Principle. Take the case (he labels “Drug”) when an agent, possessing a dose of a lifesaving drug, can save one person with the entire dose, or two people, each of whom only need half the dose. Dougherty (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Berkeley and the Passivity of Ideas.Richard Brook - 2017 - Iyyun 66:59-74.
    A number of early modern philosophers deny that corporeal non-minded nature contains efficient or strict causes. For Berkeley the passivity of ideas (hence PI) expresses this view. My aim is to look at two possible arguments – I call them strategy 1, and strategy 2 – Berkeley makes, or others make in his behalf, for PI. I conclude that they are unsatisfactory. I’m particularly interested whether Berkeley’s distinctive doctrine that objects of sense are mind-dependent, i.e., that no corporeal object can (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  62
    Berkeley, Bundles, and Immediate Perception.Richard Brook - 2005 - Dialogue 44 (3):493-504.
    ABSTRACT: I argue in this article that, contrary to some recent views, Berkeley’s bundle theory of physical objects is incompatible with the thinking that we immediately perceive such objects. Those who argue the contrary view rightly stress that immediate perception of ideas or objects must be non-conceptual for Berkeley, that is, the concept of the object cannot be made use of in the perception, otherwise it would be mediate perception. After a brief look at the texts, I contrast how a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  90
    Berkeley’s theory of vision: transparency and signification.Richard Brook - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (4):691 – 699.
    By "transparency" with respect to Berkeley's theory of signs, I mean the notion that because of the often close association between signs and what they signify, we mistakenly think we sense what is signified by the sense that accesses the sign. I argue that although this makes sense for some examples, for a variety of reasons it's not really applicable to Berkeley's claim that we mistakenly think we immediately see distance ('outness') when we, in fact, immediately see only light and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  28
    Dischargeability, optionality, and the duty to save lives.Richard Brook - 1979 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (2):194-200.
  11. Is Geometry about Tangible Extension?Richard Brook - 2009 - Berkeley Studies:5-12.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  24
    On Adding the Good.Richard Brook & Seymour Schwimmer - 1981 - Social Theory and Practice 7 (3):325-335.
  13. Statistical and Identifiable Deaths.richard Brook - 2004 - In John Haldane (ed.), Philosophy and its Public Role.
  14.  9
    Seymour Schwimmer 1924 - 1986.Richard Brook - 1987 - Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 60 (5):862 -.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  38
    Threats and punishment.Richard Brook - 1988 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (3):235-239.
  16.  13
    The Bloomsbury Companion to Berkeley.Richard Brook & Bertil Belfrage (eds.) - 2017 - London, UK: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Due to his theory of 'immaterialism' and Schopenhauer's regard of him as the 'father of idealism', George Berkeley (1685-1753) is one of the most important thinkers of the Early Modern period. "The Bloomsbury Companion to Berkeley "is a comprehensive one volume reference guide to his life, thought and work. In twenty six original essays, a team of leading international scholars of Modern Philosophy cover all of Berkeley's writings, from the major works such as his Principles of Human Knowledge through to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Berkeley and Proof in Geometry.Richard J. Brook - 2012 - Dialogue 51 (3):419-435.
    Berkeley in his Introduction to the Principles of Human knowledge uses geometrical examples to illustrate a way of generating “universal ideas,” which allegedly account for the existence of general terms. In doing proofs we might, for example, selectively attend to the triangular shape of a diagram. Presumably what we prove using just that property applies to all triangles.I contend, rather, that given Berkeley’s view of extension, no Euclidean triangles exist to attend to. Rather proof, as Berkeley would normally assume, requires (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Berkeley, Newton, Explanation, and Causation.Richard Brook - 2019 - Ruch Filozoficzny 74 (4):21.
    Berkeley, Newton, Explanation, and Causation -/- I argue in this paper that Berkeley’s conception of natural law explanations, which echoes Newton’s, fails to solve a fundamental problem, which I label “explanatory asymmetry"; that the model of explanation Berkeley uses fails to distinguish between explanations and justifications, particularly since Berkeley denies real (efficient causes) in non-minded nature. At the end I suggest Berkeley might endorse a notion of understanding, say in astronomy or mechanics, which could be distinguished from explanation.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  25
    Is Smith Obligated That(She)Not Kill the Innocent or That She(Not Kill the Innocent): Expressions and Rationales for Deontological Constraints‹.Richard Brook - 2010 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 35 (4):451-461.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. Deontology, Paradox, and Moral Evil.Richard Brook - 2007 - Social Theory and Practice 33 (3):431-440.
  21.  69
    Berkeley and the Primary Qualities: Idealization vs. Abstraction.Richard Brook - 2016 - Philosophia 44 (4):1289-1303.
    In the First of the Three Dialogues, Berkeley’s Hylas, responding to Philonous’s question whether extension and motion are separable from secondary qualities, says: What! Is it not an easy matter, to consider extension and motion by themselves,... Pray how do the mathematicians treat of them?
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  59
    Berkeley, Causality, and Signification.Richard Brook - 1995 - International Studies in Philosophy 27 (2):15-31.
  23.  36
    Is Smith Obligated That Not Kill the Innocent or That She.Richard Brook - 1997 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 35 (4):451-461.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  29
    Justice and the golden rule: A commentary on some recent work of Lawrence Kohlberg.Richard Brook - 1987 - Ethics 97 (2):363-373.
  25.  7
    Moral Questions. An Introduction to Ethics.Richard Brook - 1994 - Philosophical Books 35 (1):77-78.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  14
    Un‐“natural” Death.Richard Brook - 1976 - Hastings Center Report 6 (6):4-40.
  27.  19
    Valuing Life.Richard Brook - 1992 - Philosophical Books 33 (4):243-245.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  49
    Book ReviewsMary Anne. Warren, Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things.Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997. Pp. 265. $39.95 ; $19.95. [REVIEW]Richard Brook - 2002 - Ethics 112 (3):644-646.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  23
    What Can Cognitive Science Do for People?Richard W. Prather, Viridiana L. Benitez, Lauren Kendall Brooks, Christopher L. Dancy, Janean Dilworth-Bart, Natalia B. Dutra, M. Omar Faison, Megan Figueroa, LaTasha R. Holden, Cameron Johnson, Josh Medrano, Dana Miller-Cotto, Percival G. Matthews, Jennifer J. Manly & Ayanna K. Thomas - 2022 - Cognitive Science 46 (6):e13167.
    Cognitive Science, Volume 46, Issue 6, June 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30.  83
    Critical Thinking: Evaluating Claims and Arguments in Everyday Life.Brooke Noel Moore & Richard Parker - 1986 - Palo Alto, CA: Mayfield.
    More than any other textbook, Moore and Parker's Critical Thinking has defined the structure and content of the critical thinking course at colleges and universities across the country--and has done so with a witty writing style that students enjoy. Now in full-color, the eighth edition brings the concepts of critical thinking to life in vivid detail, with current examples relevant to today's students.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31. The developing artificial geography of the solar system.Richard Brook Cathcart - 1979 - Monticello, Ill.: Vance Bibliographies.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. History of the human sciences.Richard Bellamy, Peter M. Logan, John I. Brooks Iii, David Couzens Hoy, Michael Donnelly & James M. Glass - forthcoming - History of the Human Sciences.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  55
    Interpretation and Overinterpretation.Umberto Eco, Richard Rorty, Jonathan Culler, Christine Brooke-Rose & Stefan Collini - 1993 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (4):632-634.
  34.  45
    Nonequilibrium thermodynamics and different axioms of evolution.Daniel R. Brooks & Richard T. O'Grady - 1986 - Acta Biotheoretica 35 (1-2):77-106.
    Proponents of two axioms of biological evolutionary theory have attempted to find justification by reference to nonequilibrium thermodynamics. One states that biological systems and their evolutionary diversification are physically improbable states and transitions, resulting from a selective process; the other asserts that there is an historically constrained inherent directionality in evolutionary dynamics, independent of natural selection, which exerts a self-organizing influence. The first, the Axiom of Improbability, is shown to be nonhistorical and thus, for a theory of change through time, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35. Carnap, Rudolf, 17,114,115 n, 227, 252 Cams, Paul, 43 Chisholm, Roderick, 17 Chomsky, Noam, 130.St Thomas Aquinas, Richard J. Bernstein, Bernard Bosanquet, Robert Brandom, James Henry Breasted, Joseph Brent, Rodney A. Brooks & Wendell T. Bush - 2002 - In F. Thomas Burke, D. Micah Hester & Robert B. Talisse (eds.), Dewey's logical theory: new studies and interpretations. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  34
    Round Table: “Religion vs Philosophy?”.John Brooke, Antony Flew, Douglas Hedley, Janet Radcliffe Richards & Anja Steinbauer - 2000 - Philosophy Now 26:38-41.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Self-Reference Amd Self-Awareness, Advances in Consciousness Research Volume 11.Andrew Brook & Richard Devidi (eds.) - 2001 - John Benjamins.
  38.  26
    Sequential memory for pictures and the role of the verbal system.Douglas L. Nelson, David H. Brooks & Richard C. Borden - 1973 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 101 (2):242.
  39.  40
    Imponderables. [REVIEW]Brook Moore & Richard Parker - 1987 - Teaching Philosophy 10 (4):369-369.
  40.  12
    Imponderables. [REVIEW]Brook Moore & Richard Parker - 1987 - Teaching Philosophy 10 (4):369-369.
  41.  20
    Effects of formal similarity: Phonetic, graphic, or both?Douglas L. Nelson, David H. Brooks & Richard C. Borden - 1974 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 103 (1):91.
  42.  25
    Ontogeny of prosocial behavior across diverse societies.Bailey R. House, Joan B. Silk, Joseph Henrich, H. Clark Barrett, Brooke A. Scelza, Adam H. Boyette, Barry S. Hewlett, Richard McElreath & Stephen Laurence - 2013 - Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 110 (36):14586-14591.
    Humans are an exceptionally cooperative species, but there is substantial variation in the extent of cooperation across societies. Understanding the sources of this variability may provide insights about the forces that sustain cooperation. We examined the ontogeny of prosocial behavior by studying 326 children 3–14 y of age and 120 adults from six societies (age distributions varied across societies). These six societies span a wide range of extant human variation in culture, geography, and subsistence strategies, including foragers, herders, horticulturalists, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  43.  45
    Patient, physician and presentational influences on clinical decision making for breast cancer: results from a factorial experiment.John B. McKinlay, Risa B. Burns, Richard Durante, Henry A. Feldman, Karen M. Freund, Brooke S. Harrow, Julie T. Irish, Linda E. Kasten & Mark A. Moskowitz - 1997 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 3 (1):23-57.
  44.  20
    No Effect of Featural Attention on Body Size Aftereffects.Ian D. Stephen, Chloe Bickersteth, Jonathan Mond, Richard J. Stevenson & Kevin R. Brooks - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  29
    Levels of processing and cuing: Sensory versus meaning features.Douglas L. Nelson, Joseph W. Wheeler, Richard C. Borden & David H. Brooks - 1974 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 103 (5):971.
  46.  12
    The Thin White Line: Adaptation Suggests a Common Neural Mechanism for Judgments of Asian and Caucasian Body Size.Lewis Gould-Fensom, Chrystalle B. Y. Tan, Kevin R. Brooks, Jonathan Mond, Richard J. Stevenson & Ian D. Stephen - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  21
    Richard Owen, William Whewell, and the Vestiges.John Hedley Brooke - 1977 - British Journal for the History of Science 10 (2):132-145.
    In The life of Richard Owen by his grandson there is an inference to the effect that Owen had objected to his name being used to authorize various statements that Whewell was drafting in opposition to the Vestiges. The inference is drawn from letters that Whewell wrote to Owen on 13 and 15 February 1845. Corroboration of this would corne from a letter of Owen to Whewell, dated 14 February 1845, if extant. Among the Whewell papers at Trinity College, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48.  14
    William Keith Brooks and the naturalist’s defense of Darwinism in the late-nineteenth century.Richard Nash - 2015 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 37 (2):158-179.
    William Keith Brooks was an American zoologist at Johns Hopkins University from 1876 until his death in 1908. Over the course of his career, Brooks staunchly defended Darwinism, arguing for the centrality of natural selection in evolutionary theory at a time when alternative theories, such as neo-Lamarckism, grew prominent in American biology. In his book The Law of Heredity, Brooks addressed problems raised by Darwin’s theory of pangenesis. In modifying and developing Darwin’s pangenesis, Brooks proposed a new theory of heredity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Against ethical criticism.Richard A. Posner - 1997 - Philosophy and Literature 21 (1):1-27.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Against Ethical CriticismRichard A. PosnerOscar Wilde famously remarked that “there is no such thing as a moral or an immoral book. Books are well written, or badly written. That is all.” He was echoed by Auden, who said in his poem in memory of William Butler Yeats that poetry makes nothing happen (though the poem as a whole qualifies this overstatement), by Croce, and by formalist critics such as (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  50.  13
    The Politics and Rhetoric of Scientific Method: Historical StudiesJohn A. Schuster Richard R. Yeo.John H. Brooke - 1987 - Isis 78 (1):93-94.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 984