Results for 'Yvonne Nagel'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  9
    Moral judgment.Michael R. Waldmann, Jonas Nagel & Alex Wiegmann - 2012 - The Oxford Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning.
    The past decade has seen a renewed interest in moral psychology. A unique feature of the present endeavor is its unprecedented interdisciplinarity. For the first time, cognitive, social, and developmental psychologists, neuroscientists, experimental philosophers, evolutionary biologists, and anthropologists collaborate to study the same or overlapping phenomena. This review focuses on moral judgments and is written from the perspective of cognitive psychologists interested in theories of the cognitive and affective processes underlying judgments in moral domains. The review will first present and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  2.  8
    Archaeological possibilities for feminist theories of transition and transformation.Yvonne Marshall - 2008 - Feminist Theory 9 (1):25-45.
    Archaeology takes up material fragments from distant and recent pasts to create narratives of personal and collective identity. It is, therefore, a powerful voice shaping our current and future social worlds. Feminist theory has to date made little reference to archaeology and its projects, in part because archaeologists have primarily chosen to work with normative forms of gender theory rather than forge new theory informed by archaeological insights. This paper argues that archaeology has considerably more potential for feminist theorizing than (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Knowledge as a Mental State.Jennifer Nagel - 2013 - Oxford Studies in Epistemology 4:275-310.
    In the philosophical literature on mental states, the paradigmatic examples of mental states are beliefs, desires, intentions, and phenomenal states such as being in pain. The corresponding list in the psychological literature on mental state attribution includes one further member: the state of knowledge. This article examines the reasons why developmental, comparative and social psychologists have classified knowledge as a mental state, while most recent philosophers--with the notable exception of Timothy Williamson-- have not. The disagreement is traced back to a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  4. Intuitions and Experiments: A Defense of the Case Method in Epistemology.Jennifer Nagel - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (3):495-527.
    Many epistemologists use intuitive responses to particular cases as evidence for their theories. Recently, experimental philosophers have challenged the evidential value of intuitions, suggesting that our responses to particular cases are unstable, inconsistent with the responses of the untrained, and swayed by factors such as ethnicity and gender. This paper presents evidence that neither gender nor ethnicity influence epistemic intuitions, and that the standard responses to Gettier cases and the like are widely shared. It argues that epistemic intuitions are produced (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  5.  96
    Death.Thomas Nagel - 1970 - Noûs 4 (1):73-80.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   255 citations  
  6. Lay Denial of Knowledge for Justified True Beliefs.Jennifer Nagel, Valerie San Juan & Raymond A. Mar - 2013 - Cognition 129 (3):652-661.
    Intuitively, there is a difference between knowledge and mere belief. Contemporary philosophical work on the nature of this difference has focused on scenarios known as “Gettier cases.” Designed as counterexamples to the classical theory that knowledge is justified true belief, these cases feature agents who arrive at true beliefs in ways which seem reasonable or justified, while nevertheless seeming to lack knowledge. Prior empirical investigation of these cases has raised questions about whether lay people generally share philosophers’ intuitions about these (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   118 citations  
  7. Moral Luck.Thomas Nagel - 1993 - In Daniel Statman (ed.), Moral Luck. SUNY Press. pp. 141--166.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   211 citations  
  8. Epistemic anxiety and adaptive invariantism.Jennifer Nagel - 2010 - Philosophical Perspectives 24 (1):407-435.
    Do we apply higher epistemic standards to subjects with high stakes? This paper argues that we expect different outward behavior from high-stakes subjects—for example, we expect them to collect more evidence than their low-stakes counterparts—but not because of any change in epistemic standards. Rather, we naturally expect subjects in any condition to think in a roughly adaptive manner, balancing the expected costs of additional evidence collection against the expected value of gains in accuracy. The paper reviews a body of empirical (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  9. Knowledge ascriptions and the psychological consequences of changing stakes.Jennifer Nagel - 2008 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (2):279-294.
    Why do our intuitive knowledge ascriptions shift when a subject's practical interests are mentioned? Many efforts to answer this question have focused on empirical linguistic evidence for context sensitivity in knowledge claims, but the empirical psychology of belief formation and attribution also merits attention. The present paper examines a major psychological factor (called ?need-for-closure?) relevant to ascriptions involving practical interests. Need-for-closure plays an important role in determining whether one has a settled belief; it also influences the accuracy of one's cognition. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  10.  20
    Brain bisection and the unity of consciousness.Thomas Nagel - 1971 - Synthese 22 (3-4):396-413.
    There has been considerable optimism recently, among philosophers and neuroscientists, concerning the prospect for major discoveries about the neurophysiological basis of mind. The support for this optimism has been extremely abstract and general. I wish to present some grounds ..
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  11.  32
    Moral conflict and political legitimacy.Thomas Nagel - 1987 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (3):215-240.
  12.  14
    Knowledge ascriptions and the psychological consequences of thinking about error.Jennifer Nagel - 2010 - Philosophical Quarterly 60 (239):286-306.
    Epistemologists generally agree that the stringency of intuitive ascriptions of knowledge is increased when unrealized possibilities ofenor are mentioned. Non-sceptical invanantists (Williamson, Hawthorne) think it a mistake to yield in such cases to the temptation to be more stringent, but they do not deny that we feel it. They contend that the temptation is best explained as the product of a psychological bias known as the availability heuristic. I argue against the availability explanation, and sketch a rival account of what (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  13. Epistemic intuitions.Jennifer Nagel - 2007 - Philosophy Compass 2 (6):792–819.
    We naturally evaluate the beliefs of others, sometimes by deliberate calculation, and sometimes in a more immediate fashion. Epistemic intuitions are immediate assessments arising when someone’s condition appears to fall on one side or the other of some significant divide in epistemology. After giving a rough sketch of several major features of epistemic intuitions, this article reviews the history of the current philosophical debate about them and describes the major positions in that debate. Linguists and psychologists also study epistemic assessments; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  14. Armchair-Friendly Experimental Philosophy.Jennifer Nagel & Kaija Mortensen - 2016 - In Wesley Buckwalter & Justin Sytsma (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Experimental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 53-70.
    Once symbolized by a burning armchair, experimental philosophy has in recent years shifted away from its original hostility to traditional methods. Starting with a brief historical review of the experimentalist challenge to traditional philosophical practice, this chapter looks at research undercutting that challenge, and at ways in which experimental work has evolved to complement and strengthen traditional approaches to philosophical questions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  15. Equality and Partiality.Thomas Nagel - 1997 - In Louis P. Pojman & Robert Westmoreland (eds.), Equality: Selected Readings. Oup Usa.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   121 citations  
  16.  30
    Goal-directed processes in biology.Ernest Nagel - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (5):261-279.
  17. Defending the Evidential Value of Epistemic Intuitions: A Reply to Stich.Jennifer Nagel - 2013 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 86 (1):179-199.
    Do epistemic intuitions tell us anything about knowledge? Stich has argued that we respond to cases according to our contingent cultural programming, and not in a manner that tends to reveal anything significant about knowledge itself. I’ve argued that a cross-culturally universal capacity for mindreading produces the intuitive sense that the subject of a case has or lacks knowledge. This paper responds to Stich’s charge that mindreading is cross-culturally varied in a way that will strip epistemic intuitions of their evidential (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  18.  39
    Conceiving the impossible and the mind-body problem.Thomas Nagel - 1998 - Philosophy 73 (285):337-52.
    Intuitions based on the first-person perspective can easily mislead us about what is and is not conceivable.1 This point is usually made in support of familiar reductionist positions on the mind-body problem, but I believe it can be detached from that approach. It seems to me that the powerful appearance of contingency in the relation between the functioning of the physical organism and the conscious mind -- an appearance that depends directly or indirectly on the first- person perspective -- must (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  19. Equality.Thomas Nagel - 1979 - In Mortal questions. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  20.  6
    Experimental and Theoretical Studies of Consciousness.Thomas Nagel - 1993 - (Ciba Foundation Symposium 174).
    Discusses the various theories of consciousness from different perspectives: psychological, neurophysiological and philosophical. Theories regarding the interaction of pain, schizophrenia, the brain and the nervous system with consciousness are included. Also includes a discussion of the relative merits of the different theories together with the latest data from the experimental disciplines.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  21. Mindreading in Gettier Cases and Skeptical Pressure Cases.Jennifer Nagel - 2012 - In Jessica Brown & Mikkel Gerken (eds.), Knowledge Ascriptions. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    To what extent should we trust our natural instincts about knowledge? The question has special urgency for epistemologists who want to draw evidential support for their theories from certain intuitive epistemic assessments while discounting others as misleading. This paper focuses on the viability of endorsing the legitimacy of Gettier intuitions while resisting the intuitive pull of skepticism – a combination of moves that most mainstream epistemologists find appealing. Awkwardly enough, the “good” Gettier intuitions and the “bad” skeptical intuitions seem to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  22. Authentic Gettier Cases: a reply to Starmans and Friedman.Jennifer Nagel, Valerie San Juan & Raymond Mar - 2013 - Cognition 129 (3):666-669.
    Do laypeople and philosophers differ in their attributions of knowledge? Starmans and Friedman maintain that laypeople differ from philosophers in taking ‘authentic evidence’ Gettier cases to be cases of knowledge. Their reply helpfully clarifies the distinction between ‘authentic evidence’ and ‘apparent evidence’. Using their sharpened presentation of this distinction, we contend that the argument of our original paper still stands.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  23.  14
    Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science.Ernest Nagel (ed.) - 1962 - Stanford, Calif.,: Stanford University Press.
  24.  23
    Equal treatment and compensatory discrimination.Thomas Nagel - 1973 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 (4):348-363.
  25.  20
    Aristotle on Eudaimonia.Thomas Nagel - 1972 - Phronesis 17 (3):252 - 259.
  26. Intuition, Reflection, and the Command of Knowledge.Jennifer Nagel - 2014 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 88 (1):219-241.
    Action is not always guided by conscious deliberation; in many circumstances, we act intuitively rather than reflectively. Tamar Gendler (2014) contends that because intuitively guided action can lead us away from our reflective commitments, it limits the power of knowledge to guide action. While I agree that intuition can diverge from reflection, I argue that this divergence does not constitute a restriction on the power of knowledge. After explaining my view of the contrast between intuitive and reflective thinking, this paper (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  27.  10
    Determinism in history.Ernest Nagel - 1959 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 20 (3):291-317.
  28. Knowledge and Reliability.Jennifer Nagel - 2016 - In Hilary Kornblith & Brian McLaughlin (eds.), Goldman and his Critics. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 237-256.
    Internalists have criticised reliabilism for overlooking the importance of the subject's point of view in the generation of knowledge. This paper argues that there is a troubling ambiguity in the intuitive examples that internalists have used to make their case, and on either way of resolving this ambiguity, reliabilism is untouched. However, the argument used to defend reliabilism against the internalist cases could also be used to defend a more radical form of externalism in epistemology.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  13
    Measurement.Ernest Nagel & C. G. Hempel - 1931 - Erkenntnis 2 (1):313-335.
  30.  12
    Hobbes's concept of obligation.Thomas Nagel - 1959 - Philosophical Review 68 (1):68-83.
  31.  25
    Armstrong on the mind.Thomas Nagel - 1970 - Philosophical Review 79 (July):394-403.
  32.  35
    Functional explanations in biology.Ernest Nagel - 1977 - Journal of Philosophy 74 (5):280-301.
  33.  22
    Mechanistic explanation and organismic biology.Ernest Nagel - 1950 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 11 (3):327-338.
  34.  16
    Impressions and appraisals of analytic philosophy in europe. I.Ernest Nagel - 1936 - Journal of Philosophy 33 (1):5-24.
  35.  11
    Impressions and appraisals of analytic philosophy in europe. II.Ernest Nagel - 1936 - Journal of Philosophy 33 (2):29-53.
  36.  2
    Logic without metaphysics.Ernest Nagel - 1956 - Glencoe, Ill.,: Free Press.
  37.  29
    A Functional Contextual Account of Background Knowledge in Categorization: Implications for Artificial General Intelligence and Cognitive Accounts of General Knowledge.Darren J. Edwards, Ciara McEnteggart & Yvonne Barnes-Holmes - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Psychology has benefited from an enormous wealth of knowledge about processes of cognition in relation to how the brain organizes information. Within the categorization literature, this behavior is often explained through theories of memory construction called exemplar theory and prototype theory which are typically based on similarity or rule functions as explanations of how categories emerge. Although these theories work well at modeling highly controlled stimuli in laboratory settings, they often perform less well outside of these settings, such as explaining (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  2
    Aristotle on Eudaimonia1.Thomas Nagel - 1972 - Phronesis 17 (3):252-259.
  39.  18
    Autonomy Support to Foster Individuals’ Flourishing.Saskia K. Nagel & Peter B. Reiner - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (6):36-37.
  40.  1
    No Agent in the Machine: Being Trustworthy and Responsible about AI.Niël Henk Conradie & Saskia K. Nagel - 2024 - Philosophy and Technology 37 (2):1-24.
    Many recent AI policies have been structured under labels that follow a particular trend: national or international guidelines, policies or regulations, such as the EU’s and USA’s ‘Trustworthy AI’ and China’s and India’s adoption of ‘Responsible AI’, use a label that follows the recipe of [agentially loaded notion + ‘AI’]. A result of this branding, even if implicit, is to encourage the application by laypeople of these agentially loaded notions to the AI technologies themselves. Yet, these notions are appropriate only (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  4
    On a Theorem of Cobham Concerning Undecidable Theories.Robert L. Vaught, Ernest Nagel, Patrick Suppes & Alfred Tarski - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (1):126-127.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42.  4
    Are naturalists materialists?Ernest Nagel - 1949 - Journal of Philosophy 46 (19):515-53.
  43.  14
    Charles S. Peirce, pioneer of modern empiricism.Ernest Nagel - 1940 - Philosophy of Science 7 (1):69-80.
    No account of the development of contemporary empiricism is adequate which neglects the writings and the influence of Charles Peirce. Although he is not easily pigeon-holed and can not be claimed as the exclusive property of any school or movement, it is appropriate that the hundredth anniversary of his birth should be commemorated at this Congress. For the movement of which it is a manifestation is engaged in a coöperative, intensive cultivation of the methods of the sciences with the help (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  44. Empiricism.Jennifer Nagel - 2006 - In Sarkar Pfeifer (ed.), The Philosophy of Science. New York: Routledge.
    Having assigned experience this exclusive role in justification, empiricists then have a range of views concerning the character of experience, the semantics of our claims about unobservable entities, the nature of empirical confirmation, and the possibility of non-empirical warrant for some further class of claims, such as those accepted on the basis of linguistic or logical rules. Given the definitive principle of their position, empiricists can allow that we have knowledge independent of experience only where what is known is not (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. Autonomy and deontology.Thomas Nagel - 1988 - In Samuel Scheffler (ed.), Consequentialism and its critics. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  46. Consciousness and objective reality.Thomas Nagel - 1994 - In Richard Warner & Tadeusz Szubka (eds.), The Mind-Body Problem: A Guide to the Current Debate. Cambridge, USA: Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47. Freedom.Thomas Nagel - 1982 - In Gary Watson (ed.), Free will. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  8
    A frequency theory of probability.Ernest Nagel - 1933 - Journal of Philosophy 30 (20):533-554.
  49. Free will.Thomas Nagel - 2000 - In Steven M. Cahn (ed.), Exploring Philosophy: An Introductory Anthology. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press USA.
  50.  18
    Are plants conscious?Alexandra H. M. Nagel - 1997 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 (3):215-230.
    Views of ‘plant consciousness’ in the literature are classified on a scale ranging from descriptions of plant phenomena using consciousness as a metaphor, to explicit statements that plants are conscious beings. The idea of plant consciousness is far from new, but it has received a new impetus from recent claims by psychics to communicate with plants. The literature surveyed is widely scattered and very diverse, but it can teach us much about the views that various segments of society hold on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000