Results for 'Tim Rahschulte'

995 found
Order:
  1.  3
    Organizational and Leadership Implications for Transformational Development.Tim Rahschulte & John Gorlorwulu - 2010 - Transformation: An International Journal of Holistic Mission Studies 27 (3):199-208.
    Transformational development is a concept of change that originated in the Christian context but has now become generally used in the work of both secular and faith-based organizations. The growing use of the concept by organizations that are fundamentally different has naturally led to some confusion about what the concept means and what it takes to effectively implement it. In this article, we describe the key features of the concept and how they are important in determining the organizational requirements for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The meaning of pain expressions and pain communication.Emma Borg, Tim Salomons & Nat Hansen - 2017 - In Simon van Rysewyk (ed.), Meanings of Pain. Springer. pp. 261-282.
    Both patients and clinicians frequently report problems around communicating and assessing pain. Patients express dissatisfaction with their doctors and doctors often find exchanges with chronic pain patients difficult and frustrating. This chapter thus asks how we could improve pain communication and thereby enhance outcomes for chronic pain patients. We argue that improving matters will require a better appreciation of the complex meaning of pain terms and of the variability and flexibility in how individuals think about pain. We start by examining (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3.  13
    Compositionality: A connectionist variation on a classical theme.Tim van Gelder - 1990 - Cognitive Science 14 (3):355-384.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  4.  34
    Human Nature: The Very Idea.Tim Lewens - 2012 - Philosophy and Technology 25 (4):459-474.
    Abstract The only biologically respectable notion of human nature is an extremely permissive one that names the reliable dispositions of the human species as a whole. This conception offers no ethical guidance in debates over enhancement, and indeed it has the result that alterations to human nature have been commonplace in the history of our species. Aristotelian conceptions of species natures, which are currently fashionable in meta-ethics and applied ethics, have no basis in biological fact. Moreover, because our folk psychology (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  5. The Normativity of Nature in Epicurean Ethics and Politics.Tim O’Keefe - 2021 - In Peter Adamson & Christof Rapp (eds.), State and Nature: Studies in Ancient and Medieval Philosophy. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 181-199.
    Appeals to nature are ubiquitous in Epicurean ethics and politics. The foundation of Epicurean ethics is its claim that pleasure is the sole intrinsic good and pain the sole intrinsic evil, and this is supposedly shown by the behavior of infants who have not yet been corrupted, "when nature's judgement is pure and whole." Central to their recommendations about how to attain pleasure is their division between types of desires: the natural and necessary ones, the natural but non-necessary ones, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  3
    Fear, freedom and political culture during COVID-19.Marc Stears & Tim Soutphommasane - 2022 - Monash Bioethics Review 40 (1):110-119.
    Australia’s experience of the COVID-19 pandemic has been widely perceived to have been a successful one, based on the relatively few number of lives lost to the virus compared to the rest of the world. There remain, nonetheless, serious ethical challenges at the heart of the Australian response to COVID-19. The broadly positive outcomes of Australia’s pandemic response mask more troubling developments within its political culture, and the costs it has imposed on its society. This article examines two concerns in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  13
    Animalism and the varieties of conjoined twinning.Tim Campbell & Jeff McMahan - 2010 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 31 (4):285-301.
    We defend the view that we are not identical to organisms against the objection that it implies that there are two subjects of every conscious state one experiences: oneself and one’s organism. We then criticize animalism —the view that each of us is identical to a human organism—by showing that it has unacceptable implications for a range of actual and hypothetical cases of conjoined twinning : dicephalus, craniopagus parasiticus, and cephalopagus.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  8.  14
    On the Unification of Physics.Tim Maudlin - 1996 - Journal of Philosophy 93 (3):129-144.
    There are various senses in which a physical theory may be said to "unify" different forces, with the unification being deeper of more shallow in different cases. This paper discusses some of these distinctions.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  9. There's no time like the present.Tim Button - 2006 - Analysis 66 (2):130–135.
    No-futurists ('growing block theorists') hold that that the past and the present are real, but that the future is not. The present moment is therefore privileged: it is the last moment of time. Craig Bourne (2002) and David Braddon-Mitchell (2004) have argued that this position is unmotivated, since the privilege of presentness comes apart from the indexicality of 'this moment'. I respond that no-futurists should treat 'x is real-as-of y' as a nonsymmetric relation. Then different moments are real-as-of different times. (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  10. Realistic structuralism's identity crisis: A hybrid solution.Tim Button - 2006 - Analysis 66 (3):216–222.
    Keränen (2001) raises an argument against realistic (ante rem) structuralism: where a mathematical structure has a non-trivial automorphism, distinct indiscernible positions within the structure cannot be shown to be non-identical using only the properties and relations of that structure. Ladyman (2005) responds by allowing our identity criterion to include 'irreflexive two-place relations'. I note that this does not solve the problem for structures with indistinguishable positions, i.e. positions that have all the same properties as each other and exactly the same (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  11.  8
    New Foundations for Physical Geometry: The Theory of Linear Structures.Tim Maudlin - 2014 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Tim Maudlin sets out a completely new method for describing the geometrical structure of spaces, and thus a better mathematical tool for describing and understanding space-time. He presents a historical review of the development of geometry and topology, and then his original Theory of Linear Structures.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12. Every now and then, no-futurism faces no sceptical problems.Tim Button - 2007 - Analysis 67 (4):325–332.
    Tallant (2007) has challenged my recent defence of no-futurism (Button 2006), but he does not discuss the key to that defence: that no-futurism's primitive relation 'x is real-as-of y' is not symmetric. I therefore answer Tallant's challenge in the same way as I originally defended no-futurism. I also clarify no-futurism by rejecting a common mis-characterisation of the growing-block theorist. By supplying a semantics for no-futurists, I demonstrate that no-futurism faces no sceptical challenges. I conclude by considering the problem of how (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  13. Achieving Tranquility: Epicurus on Living without Fear.Tim O'Keefe - forthcoming - In Jacob Klein & Nathan Powers (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Hellenistic Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
    Explores the role of eliminating fear in Epicurean ethics and physics, focusing on techniques to eliminate the fear of death and the fear of the gods. Includes a taxonomy of types of fear and types of therapy for fear.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  6
    From bricolage to BioBricks™: Synthetic biology and rational design.Tim Lewens - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44 (4b):641-648.
    Synthetic biology is often described as a project that applies rational design methods to the organic world. Although humans have influenced organic lineages in many ways, it is nonetheless reasonable to place synthetic biology towards one end of a continuum between purely ‘blind’ processes of organic modification at one extreme, and wholly rational, design-led processes at the other. An example from evolutionary electronics illustrates some of the constraints imposed by the rational design methodology itself. These constraints reinforce the limitations of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  15.  24
    Classic invariantism, relevance and warranted assertability manœvres.Tim Black - 2005 - Philosophical Quarterly 55 (219):328–336.
    Jessica Brown effectively contends that Keith DeRose’s latest argument for contextualism fails to rule out contextualism’s chief rival, namely, classic invariantism. Still, even if her position has not been ruled out, the classic invariantist must offer considerations in favor of her position if she is to convince us that it is superior to contextualism. Brown defends classic invariantism with a warranted assertability maneuver that utilizes a linguistic pragmatic principle of relevance. I argue, however, that this maneuver is not as effective (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  16.  14
    Defending a sensitive neo-Moorean invariantism.Tim Black - 2007 - In Vincent Hendricks (ed.), New Waves in Epistemology. Aldershot, England and Burlington, VT, USA: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 8--27.
    I defend a sensitive neo-Moorean invariantism, an epistemological account with the following characteristic features: (a) it reserves a place for a sensitivity condition on knowledge, according to which, very roughly, S’s belief that p counts as knowledge only if S wouldn’t believe that p if p were false; (b) it maintains that the standards for knowledge are comparatively low; and (c) it maintains that the standards for knowledge are invariant (i.e., that they vary neither with the linguistic context of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  17. SAD computers and two versions of the Church–Turing thesis.Tim Button - 2009 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (4):765-792.
    Recent work on hypercomputation has raised new objections against the Church–Turing Thesis. In this paper, I focus on the challenge posed by a particular kind of hypercomputer, namely, SAD computers. I first consider deterministic and probabilistic barriers to the physical possibility of SAD computation. These suggest several ways to defend a Physical version of the Church–Turing Thesis. I then argue against Hogarth's analogy between non-Turing computability and non-Euclidean geometry, showing that it is a non-sequitur. I conclude that the Effective version (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  18. Wa-mā baʻda 2020!: ishkālīyāt ḥaḍārīyah fī ʻawlamah bi-lā huwīyah.Ḥātim ʻAlāmī - 2019 - Bayrūt: Markaz al-Baḥth fī al-Jāmiʻah al-Ḥadīthah lil-Idārah wa-al-ʻUlūm MUBS.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Dadaism: Restrictivism as Militant Quietism.Tim Button - 2010 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 110 (3pt3):387-398.
    Can we quantify over everything: absolutely, positively, definitely, totally, every thing? Some philosophers have claimed that we must be able to do so, since the doctrine that we cannot is self-stultifying. But this treats restrictivism as a positive doctrine. Restrictivism is much better viewed as a kind of militant quietism, which I call dadaism. Dadaists advance a hostile challenge, with the aim of silencing everyone who holds a positive position about ‘absolute generality’.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  20.  28
    Toward a new sociology of masculinity.Tim Carrigan, Bob Connell & John Lee - 1985 - Theory and Society 14 (5):551-604.
  21.  19
    Divine Determinism and the Problem of Hell.Jacobus Erasmus & Tim Stratton - 2018 - Perichoresis 16 (2):3-15.
    Divine determinism, though affirmed by many Calvinists, implicates God in the decisions people make that ultimately damn them to the terrible destiny of hell. In this paper, the authors argue that this scenario is a problem for divine determinism. The article contends that determinism is inconsistent with God’s love and the Scriptures that explicitly state that God does not ‘desire’ anyone to go to hell. Even human love for others strongly suggests that God, who is ‘love’, will not determine anyone (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. The Metamathematics of Putnam’s Model-Theoretic Arguments.Tim Button - 2011 - Erkenntnis 74 (3):321-349.
    Putnam famously attempted to use model theory to draw metaphysical conclusions. His Skolemisation argument sought to show metaphysical realists that their favourite theories have countable models. His permutation argument sought to show that they have permuted models. His constructivisation argument sought to show that any empirical evidence is compatible with the Axiom of Constructibility. Here, I examine the metamathematics of all three model-theoretic arguments, and I argue against Bays (2001, 2007) that Putnam is largely immune to metamathematical challenges.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  19
    Solving the problem of easy knowledge.Tim Black - 2008 - Philosophical Quarterly 58 (233):597-617.
    Stewart Cohen argues that several epistemological theories fall victim to the problem of easy knowledge: they allow us to know far too easily that certain sceptical hypotheses are false and that how things seem is a reliable indicator of how they are. This problem is a result of the theories' interaction with an epistemic closure principle. Cohen suggests that the theories should be modified. I argue that attempts to solve the problem should focus on closure instead; a new and plausible (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24.  15
    Psychopathology and Two Kinds of Narrative Accounts of the Self.Tim Thornton - 2003 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 10 (4):361-367.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 10.4 (2003) 361-367 [Access article in PDF] Psychopathology and Two Kinds of Narrative Account of the Self Tim Thornton Keywords self, narrative, reductionism, embodiment, Dennett, Strawson, McDowell The self plays an important role in psycho pathology. Conditions such as dementia raise the question of how much loss of memory and awareness there can be before there is, if ever, also a loss of the self. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25. Contextualism in epistemology.Tim Black - 2003 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  26.  17
    Galileo's ship and spacetime symmetry.Tim Budden - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (4):483-516.
    The empirical content of the modern definition of relativity given in the Andersonian approach to spacetime theory has been overestimated. It does not imply the empirical relativity Galileo illustrated in his famous ship thought experiment. I offer a number of arguments—some of which are in essential agreement with a recent analysis of Brown and Sypel [1995]—which make this plausible. Then I go on to present example spacetime theories which are modern relativistic but violate Galileo's relativity. I end by briefly discussing (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27.  8
    A star in the minkowskian sky: Anisotropic special relativity.Tim Budden - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (3):325-361.
  28.  8
    Monism, Dualism, Pluralism.Tim Van Gelder - 1998 - Mind and Language 13 (1):76-97.
    The traditional mind‐body debate is chronically unwell. Its problems are largely due to unwitting acceptance of four deep metaphysical assumptions. Rejecting those assumptions leads to a pluralist conception of the ontology of mind and a correspondingly complex account of the fit between mind and world.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  29.  16
    Sport, Aesthetic Experience, and Art as the Ideal Embodied Metaphor.Tim L. Elcombe - 2012 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (2):201-217.
    Despite a prevalence of articles exploring links between sport and art in the 1970s and 1980s, philosophers in the new millennium pay relatively little explicit attention to issues related to aesthetics generally. After providing a synopsis of earlier debates over the questions ‘is sport art?’ and ‘are aesthetics implicit to sport?’, a pragmatically informed conception of aesthetic experience will be developed. Aesthetic experience, it will be argued, vitally informs sport ethics, game logic, and participant meaning. Finally, I will argue that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30.  7
    A warranted-assertability defense of a Moorean response to skepticism.Tim Black - 2008 - Acta Analytica 23 (3):187-205.
    According to a Moorean response to skepticism, the standards for knowledge are invariantly comparatively low, and we can know across contexts all that we ordinarily take ourselves to know. It is incumbent upon the Moorean to defend his position by explaining how, in contexts in which S seems to lack knowledge, S can nevertheless have knowledge. The explanation proposed here relies on a warranted-assertability maneuver: Because we are warranted in asserting that S doesn’t know that p, it can seem that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  32
    Absolutes and Particulars.Tim Chappell - 2004 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 54:95-117.
    [About the book] Although this collection of articles is not formally a commentary on Elizabeth Anscombe's famous article of the same title, in which she criticised the moral philosophy prevalent in 1958, a number of the contributors do take Anscombe's work as a starting point. Taken together the collection could be seen as a demonstration of the extent to which moral philosophers have since attempted to answer Anscombe's challenge, and to develop an approach to their subject which, while psychologically plausible, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32.  10
    Ethical imperialism or ethical mindfulness? Rethinking ethical review for social sciences.Tim Bond - 2012 - Research Ethics 8 (2):97-112.
    This article is a response to the challenge with which Zachary Schrag concluded his article, ‘The case against ethics review in social sciences’ − that ‘the burden of proof for its continuation rests on its defenders’ (Schrag, 2011). This article acknowledges that there is substance in the charges he lays against some reviews of social sciences and that these are of sufficient quantity and seriousness to justify his challenge. Instead of favouring abandonment of ethical review of social sciences, the author (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  2
    al-ʻAlmānīyah fī al-falsafah al-muʻāṣirah.Ḥātim Amzīl - 2017 - [Rabat?]: Mukhtabar al-Dirāsāt al-Rushdīyah.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  13
    The distinction between coherence and constancy in Hume's Treatise I.iv.2.Tim Black - 2007 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 15 (1):1-25.
    In the Treatise, Book I, Part iv, Section 2, Hume seeks to explain what causes us to believe that objects continue to exist even when they are not perceived. He argues that we won't be able to prov...
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35. In Defence of Speciesism.Tim Chappell - 1997 - In David S. Oderberg & Jacqueline A. Laing (eds.), Human lives: critical essays on consequentialist bioethics. New York, N.Y.: St. Martin's Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  5
    The Speciation of Modern Homo Sapiens.Tim Crow (ed.) - 2004 - Oxford University Press.
    This is the first volume to address directly the question of the speciation of modern Homo sapiens. The subject raises profound questions about the nature of the species, our defining characteristic (it is suggested it is language), and the brain changes and their genetic basis that make us distinct. The British Academy and the Academy of Medical Sciences have brought together experts from palaeontology, archaeology, linguistics, psychology, genetics and evolutionary theory to present evidence and theories at the cutting edge of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  6
    An Ethics Role-Playing Case.Tim Manuel - 2010 - Journal of Business Ethics Education 7:141-154.
    This paper discusses a role playing ethics case suitable for business students in which participants must balance shareholder and stakeholder concerns. Students take on the role of operations manager and are challenged to consider the effects of their choices on the local society as they balance the demands of stockholders, employees, and family when the concerns of the groups come into conflict. The exercise helps students understand the need to consider the ethicalcomponents of business decisions and the difficulties of handling (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  25
    Natural Separateness: Why Parfit's Reductionist Account of Persons Fails to Support Consequentialism.Tim Christie - 2009 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 6 (2):178-195.
    My goal in this essay will be to show, contra Parfit, that the separateness of human persons—although metaphysically shallow—has a moral significance that should not be overlooked. Parfit holds that his reductionist view of personal identity lends support to consequentialism; I reject this claim because it rests on the assumption that the separateness of human persons has an arbitrariness that renders it morally insignificant. This assumption is flawed because this separateness is grounded in our 'person practices', which reflect some of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39.  4
    Het nadeel van de zekerheid: uitgedaagd door het scepticisme.Tim de Mey (ed.) - 2015 - Rotterdam: Lemniscaat.
    Historische en systematische artikelen van Nederlandstalige filosofen over diverse aspecten van scepticisme, toen en nu, in filosofie, religie en wetenschap.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  9
    The integrity of exacerbated ambiguity.Tim De Mey - 2016 - Algemeen Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Wijsbegeerte 108 (3):469-482.
    Although Thomas More is an exemplary figure of both personal and moral integrity, his Utopia is not straightforwardly ‘integer’ in another meaning of the term, i.e., it does not unequivocally describe a ‘whole, intact or pure’ conception of the ideal society. Rather, Utopia is patently ambiguous and challenges the reader to disambiguate the narrative and to make up his own mind on how to construct the ideal society. In this paper, I analyze utopias and dystopias in general as evaluative thought (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  1
    The Relativity Principle and the Isotropy of Boosts.Tim Budden - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:528 - 541.
    A class of theories which satisfy the Relativity Principle has been overlooked. The kinematics for these theories is derived by relaxing the 'boost isotropy' symmetry normally invoked, and the role the dynamical fields play in determining the inertial coordinate systems is emphasised, leading to a criticism of Friedman's (1983) practice of identifying them via the absolute objects of a spacetime theory alone. Some theories complete with 'boost anisotropic' dynamics are given.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  34
    Forallx Adelaide.Antony Eagle, Tim Button & P. D. Magnus - manuscript
  43.  11
    Mere Molinism: A Defense of Two Essential Pillars.Jacobus Erasmus & Tim Stratton - 2018 - Perichoresis 16 (2):17-29.
    Molinism is founded on two ‘pillars’, namely, the view that human beings possess libertarian free will and the view that God has middle knowledge. Both these pillars stand in contrast to naturalistic determinism and divine determinism. In this article, however, the authors offer philosophical and theological grounds in favor of libertarian free will and middle knowledge.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  18
    Lawyers, Ethics, and To Kill a Mockingbird.Tim Dare - 2001 - Philosophy and Literature 25 (1):127-141.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 25.1 (2001) 127-141 [Access article in PDF] Lawyers, Ethics, and To Kill a Mockingbird Tim Dare I Lawyers are widely thought to be callous, self-serving, devious, and indifferent to justice, truth, and the public good. The law profession could do with a hero, and some think Atticus Finch of Harper Lee's To Kill a Mockingbird fits the bill. 1 Claudia Carver, for instance, urging lawyers to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Das Kind im Manne. Platons Bewertung der Leiblichkeit im Hinblick auf die Entwicklung der Seele.Tim Gollasch - 2013 - Perspektiven der Philosophie 39 (1):131-154.
    Das Motiv der Gegenüberstellung von Kind und Erwachsenem ist formal wie inhaltlich wesentlich für Platons Schriften. Mit dem Kind ist auch ein Seelenzustand des Erwachsenen gemeint, der die eigentliche Entwicklung seiner Seele zur personalen und souveränen Identität noch anfangen muss. Auf diesen Anfangs- und Entwicklungsgedanken hin sind Platons Dialoge konzipiert: Die Verschränkung von Logos und Mythos ist Darstellung und Anleitung einer Identitätsfindung, d. h. einer Auffindung des Ichs, das sich selbst formt, anstatt, getrieben von seinem Werdegang, dem Vorgegebenen zu folgen. (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  33
    The New Vanguard.Tim Crane - 2002 - The Philosophers' Magazine 18:41-42.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  18
    The legitimacy of ESG standards as an analytical framework for responsible investment.Tim Cadman - 2011 - In Wim Vandekerckhove, Jos Leys, Kristian Alm, Bert Scholtens, Silvana Signori & Henry Schäfer (eds.), Responsible Investment in Times of Turmoil. Springer. pp. 35--53.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Spotty Scope and Our Relation to Fictions.Tim Button - 2012 - Noûs 46 (2):243-58.
    Whatever the attractions of Tolkein's world, irrealists about fictions do not believe literally that Bilbo Baggins is a hobbit. Instead, irrealists believe that, according to The Lord of the Rings {Bilbo is a hobbit}. But when irrealists want to say something like “I am taller than Bilbo”, there is nowhere good for them to insert the operator “according to The Lord of the Rings”. This is an instance of the operator problem. In this paper, I outline and criticise Sainsbury's (2006) (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  4
    Reductionism about persons; and what matters.Tim Chappell - 1998 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 98 (1):41-58.
    This paper's ?I examines Derek Parfit's main, metaphysical, argument for reductionism about personal identity. ?II considers three possible ethical arguments for reductionism, and suggests a new approach to the question of what matters about personal identity which has to do with the notion of an ethical narrative.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  91
    Avoiding the dogmatic commitments of contextualism.Tim Black & Peter Murphy - 2005 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (1):165-182.
    Epistemological contextualists maintain that the truth-conditions of sentences of the form 'S knows that P' vary according to the context in which they're uttered, where this variation is due to the semantics of 'knows'. Among the linguistic data that have been offered in support of contextualism are several everyday cases. We argue that these cases fail to support contextualism and that they instead support epistemological invariantism—the thesis that the truth-conditions of 'S knows that P' do not vary according to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 995