Results for 'Fred Sherwin'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Italian sonnet.Fred Sherwin - 1922 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 3 (4):243.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Conscious experience.Fred Dretske - 1993 - Mind 102 (406):263-283.
  3. The logic of natural language.Fred Sommers - 1982 - New York: Oxford University Press.
  4. Intentional action in ordinary language: Core concept or pragmatic understanding?Fred Adams & Annie Steadman - 2004 - Analysis 64 (2):173–181.
    Among philosophers, there are at least two prevalent views about the core concept of intentional action. View I (Adams 1986, 1997; McCann 1986) holds that an agent S intentionally does an action A only if S intends to do A. View II (Bratman 1987; Harman 1976; and Mele 1992) holds that there are cases where S intentionally does A without intending to do A, as long as doing A is foreseen and S is willing to accept A as a consequence (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  5. Perception without awareness.Fred Dretske - 2006 - In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 147--180.
  6.  45
    Emergence and its place in nature: a case study of biochemical networks.Fred C. Boogerd, Frank J. Bruggeman, Robert C. Richardson, Achim Stephan & Hans V. Westerhoff - 2005 - Synthese 145 (1):131-164.
    We will show that there is a strong form of emergence in cell biology. Beginning with C.D. Broad’s classic discussion of emergence, we distinguish two conditions sufficient for emergence. Emergence in biology must be compatible with the thought that all explanations of systemic properties are mechanistic explanations and with their sufficiency. Explanations of systemic properties are always in terms of the properties of the parts within the system. Nonetheless, systemic properties can still be emergent. If the properties of the components (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  7. The good life: A defense of attitudinal hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):604-628.
    The students and colleagues of Roderick Chisholm admired and respected Chisholm. Many were filled not only with admiration, but with affection and gratitude for Chisholm throughout the time we knew him. Even now that he is dead, we continue to wish him well. Under the circumstances, many of us probably think that that wish amounts to no more than this: we hope that things went well for him when he lived; we hope that he had a good life.
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  8. Functional specialization in the lower and upper visual fields in humans: Its ecological origins and neurophysiological implications.Fred H. Previc - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):519-542.
  9. Adjusting utility for justice: A consequentialist reply to the objection from justice.Fred Feldman - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (3):567-585.
    1. Introduction. In a famous passage near the beginning of A Theory of Justice, John Rawls discusses utilitarianism’s notorious difficulties with justice. According to classic forms of utilitarianism, a certain course of action is morally right if it produces the greatest sum of satisfactions. And, as Rawls points out, the perplexing implication is “…that it does not matter, except indirectly, how this sum of satisfactions is distributed among individuals any more than it matters, except indirectly, how one man distributes his (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  10. Mental events as structuring causes of behavior.Fred Dretske - 1993 - In John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford University Press.
    1. Causal explanations depend on our interests, our purposes, and our prior knowledge. ⇒ No uniquely real causal explanation.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  11.  67
    The Good Life: A Defense of Attitudinal Hedonism.Fred Feldman - 2002 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (3):604-628.
    What makes a life go well for the one who lives it? Hedonists hold that pleasure enhances the value of a life; pain diminishes it. Hedonism has been subjected to a number of objections. Some are (a) based on the claim that hedonism is a form of “mental statism”. Others are (b) based on the claim that some pleasures are base or degrading. Yet others are (c) based on the claim that when a bad person enjoys a pleasure, his receipt (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  12.  81
    Adjusting Utility for Justice.Fred Feldman - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (3):567-585.
    1. Introduction. In a famous passage near the beginning of A Theory of Justice, John Rawls discusses utilitarianism’s notorious difficulties with justice. According to classic forms of utilitarianism, a certain course of action is morally right if it produces the greatest sum of satisfactions. And, as Rawls points out, the perplexing implication is “…that it does not matter, except indirectly, how this sum of satisfactions is distributed among individuals any more than it matters, except indirectly, how one man distributes his (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  13. Types and ontology.Fred Sommers - 1963 - Philosophical Review 72 (3):327-363.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  14. The Logic of Natural Language.Fred Sommers - 1983 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 173 (3):367-368.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  15.  9
    From theory, to practice, to policy.Franfoise Baylis, Jocelyn Downie & Susan Sherwin - 2002 - In Ruth F. Chadwick & Doris Schroeder (eds.), Applied Ethics: Critical Concepts in Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 1--140.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  17
    Psychological Analysis and the Philosophy of John Stuart Mill.Fred Wilson - 1990
    John Stuart Mill underwent a mental crisis in the 1820s. He emerged from it, argues Fred Wilson, with a new understanding of the notion of introspective analysis more dequare as an empirical method than the sort of analysis that had been used by earlier utilitarian thinkiers such as Bentham and James Mill. Wilson's study places Mill's innovations in the context of earlier work in ethics and perception and of subsequent developments in the history of psychology. He shows the significance (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17. Mental events as structuring causes of behavior.Fred Dretske - 1993 - In John Heil & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), Mental Causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 121--135.
  18.  41
    Reply to Reviewers.Fred Dretske - 1990 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (4):819 - 839.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  19. Empty names and pragmatic implicatures.Fred Adams & Gary Fuller - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):449-461.
    What are the meanings of empty names such as ‘Vulcan,’ ‘Pegasus,’ and ‘Santa Claus’ in such sentences as ‘Vulcan is the tenth planet,’ ‘Pegasus flies,’ and especially ‘Santa Claus does not exist’?Our view, developed in Adams et al., consists of a direct-reference account of the meaning of empty names in combination with a pragmatic-implicature account of why we have certain intuitions that seem to conflict with a direct-reference account.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  30
    Community-equipoise and the ethics of randomized clinical trials.Fred Gifford - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (2):127–148.
    This paper critically examines a particular strategy for resolving the central ethical dilemma associated with randomized clinical trials — the “community equipoise” strategy . The dilemma is that RCTs appear to violate a physician's duty to choose that therapy which there is most reason to believe is in the patient's best interest, randomizing patients even once evidence begins to favor one treatment. The community equipoise strategy involves the suggestion that our judgment that neither treatment is to be preferred is to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  21. Hyperventilating about intrinsic value.Fred Feldman - 1998 - The Journal of Ethics 2 (4):339-354.
    Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Brentano, Moore, and Chisholm have suggested marks or criteria of intrinsic goodness. I distinguish among eight of these. I focus in this paper on four: (a) unimprovability, (b) unqualifiedness, (c) dependence upon intrinsic natures, and (d) incorruptibility. I try to show that each of these is problematic in some way. I also try to show that they are not equivalent – they point toward distinct conceptions of intrinsic goodness. In the end it appears that none of them (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  22.  75
    The calculus of terms.Fred Sommers - 1970 - Mind 79 (313):1-39.
  23. What good is consciousness?Fred Dretske - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):1-15.
    If consciousness is good for something, conscious things must differ in some causally relevant way from unconscious things. If they do not, then, as Davies and Humphreys conclude, too bad for consciousness: ‘psychological theory need not be concerned with this topic.’Davies and Humphreys are applying a respectable metaphysical idea — the idea, namely, that if an object's having a property does not make a difference to what that object does, if the object's causal powers are in no way enhanced by (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  24. The ordinary language tree.Fred Sommers - 1959 - Mind 68 (270):160-185.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  25.  29
    Empty Names and Pragmatic Implicatures.Fred Adams & Gary Fuller - 2007 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (3):449-461.
    What are the meanings of empty names such as ‘Vulcan,’ ‘Pegasus,’ and ‘Santa Claus’ in such sentences as ‘Vulcan is the tenth planet,’ ‘Pegasus flies,’ and especially ‘Santa Claus does not exist’?Our view, developed in Adams et al., consists of a direct-reference account of the meaning of empty names in combination with a pragmatic-implicature account of why we have certain intuitions that seem to conflict with a direct-reference account.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  26.  25
    What Good is Consciousness?Fred Dretske - 1997 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):1-15.
    If consciousness is good for something, conscious things must differ in some causally relevant way from unconscious things. If they do not, then, as Davies and Humphreys conclude, too bad for consciousness: ‘psychological theory need not be concerned with this topic.’Davies and Humphreys are applying a respectable metaphysical idea — the idea, namely, that if an object's having a property does not make a difference to what that object does, if the object's causal powers are in no way enhanced by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  27.  15
    Community‐Equipoise and the Ethics of Randomized Clinical Trials.Fred Gifford - 1995 - Bioethics 9 (2):127-148.
    This paper critically examines a particular strategy for resolving the central ethical dilemma associated with randomized clinical trials (RCTs) — the “community equipoise” strategy (CE). The dilemma is that RCTs appear to violate a physician's duty to choose that therapy which there is most reason to believe is in the patient's best interest, randomizing patients even once evidence begins to favor one treatment. The community equipoise strategy involves the suggestion that our judgment that neither treatment is to be preferred (that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  28.  49
    Hyperventilating about Intrinsic Value.Fred Feldman - 1998 - The Journal of Ethics 2 (4):339-354.
    Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Brentano, Moore, and Chisholm have suggested ’’marks‘‘ or criteria of intrinsic goodness. I distinguish among eight of these. I focus in this paper on four: (a) unimprovability, (b) unqualifiedness, (c) dependence upon intrinsic natures, and (d) incorruptibility. I try to show that each of these is problematic in some way. I also try to show that they are not equivalent – they point toward distinct conceptions of intrinsic goodness. In the end it appears that none of them (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  29.  71
    Differences that make no difference.Fred Dretske - 1994 - Philosophical Topics 22 (1/2):41-57.
  30. Structural ontology.Fred Sommers - 1971 - Philosophia 1 (1-2):21-42.
  31. Predicability.Fred Sommers - 1964 - In Max Black (ed.), Philosophy in America. Ithaca: Routledge. pp. 262--281.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  32.  12
    Differences that Make No Difference.Fred Dretske - 1994 - Philosophical Topics 22 (1-2):41-57.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33.  19
    Visual processing in three-dimensional space: Perceptions and misperceptions.Fred H. Previc - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):559-575.
  34. Absent qualia.Fred Dretske - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (1):78-85.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35.  67
    Church's thesis without tears.Fred Richman - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (3):797-803.
    The modern theory of computability is based on the works of Church, Markov and Turing who, starting from quite different models of computation, arrived at the same class of computable functions. The purpose of this paper is the show how the main results of the Church-Markov-Turing theory of computable functions may quickly be derived and understood without recourse to the largely irrelevant theories of recursive functions, Markov algorithms, or Turing machines. We do this by ignoring the problem of what constitutes (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  44
    Gleason's theorem has a constructive proof.Fred Richman - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (4):425-431.
    Gleason's theorem for ������³ says that if f is a nonnegative function on the unit sphere with the property that f(x) + f(y) + f(z) is a fixed constant for each triple x, y, z of mutually orthogonal unit vectors, then f is a quadratic form. We examine the issues raised by discussions in this journal regarding the possibility of a constructive proof of Gleason's theorem in light of the recent publication of such a proof.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  37.  10
    Absent Qualia.Fred Dretske - 1996 - Mind and Language 11 (1):78-85.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  38.  74
    The Metaphysics of Freedom.Fred Dretske - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):1-13.
    I offer Jimmy a dollar to wiggle his ears. He wiggles them because he wants the dollar and, as a result of my offer, thinks he will earn it by wiggling his ears. So I cause him to believe something that explains, or helps to explain, why he wiggles his ears. If I push a button, and a bell, wired to the button, rings because the button is depressed, I cause the bell to ring. I make it ring. Indeed, I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  39. Perception without awareness.Fred Dretske - 2006 - In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press.
  40.  29
    Acquaintance, Ontology, and Knowledge.Fred Wilson - 1970 - New Scholasticism 44 (1):1-48.
  41.  17
    The Origins of Hume's Sceptical Argument against Reason.Fred Wilson - 1985 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (3):323 - 335.
  42.  24
    Weinberg's Refutation of Nominalism.Fred Wilson - 1969 - Dialogue 8 (3):460-474.
    Professor Weinberg, in his recention, Relation, and Induction, has critically discussed the nominalistic tradition stemming from Ockham and continuing in the work of Berkeley and Hume. In this tradition there is one fundamental principle, which however divides into two parts. The first is Whatever is distinguishable is distinct, and conversely. The second is Whatever is distinct is separable, and conversely. Weinberg argues that both and are mistaken.In this paper I propose to explore the case against nominalism. I shall suggest that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. Embodied cognition and the extended mind.Fred Adams & Ken Aizawa - 2009 - In Sarah Robins, John Symons & Paco Calvo (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 193--213.
    Summary: A review of the cognitivist/extended cognition and extended mind landscape.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  42
    The Role of a Principle of Acquaintance in Ontology.Fred Wilson - 1969 - Modern Schoolman 47 (1):37-56.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  29
    Omniscience Principles and Functions of Bounded Variation.Fred Richman - 2002 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 48 (1):111-116.
    A very weak omniscience principle is formulated, related omniscience principlesare considered, and the theorem that a function of bounded variation is the difference of two increasing functions is shown to be equivalent to the omniscience principle WLPO. It is a so shown that an arbitrary function with located variation on an interval is the difference of two increasing functions.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  35
    Kung-sun lung, designated things, and logic.Fred Rieman - 1980 - Philosophy East and West 30 (3):305-319.
  47.  6
    The Metaphysics of Freedom.Fred Dretske - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (1):1-13.
    I offer Jimmy a dollar to wiggle his ears. He wiggles them because he wants the dollar and, as a result of my offer, thinks he will earn it by wiggling his ears. So I cause him to believe something that explains, or helps to explain, why he wiggles his ears. If I push a button, and a bell, wired to the button, rings because the button is depressed, I cause the bell to ring. I make it ring. Indeed, I (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  11
    Enjeu éthique d’une ontologie de la différence. La situation de handicap comme question sociale et politique.Fred Poché - 2017 - Franciscanum 59 (167):151.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  10
    Predication in the Logic of Terms.Fred Sommers - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 31 (1):106-126.
  50.  59
    Habermas and rationality.Fred Dallmayr - 1988 - Political Theory 16 (4):553-579.
1 — 50 / 1000