Switch to: References

Citations of:

The ordinary language tree

Mind 68 (270):160-185 (1959)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Semantic kinds.John Woods - 1973 - Philosophia 3 (2-3):117-151.
  • What Kind of Ontological Categories for Geo-ontologies?Timothy Tambassi - 2019 - Acta Analytica 34 (2):135-144.
    Despite their recent development, geo-ontologies represent a complicated conundrum for the different experts involved in their design. Computer scientists use ontologies for describing the meaning of data and their semantics in order to make information resources built for humans understandable also for artificial agents. Geographers pursue conceptualizations that describe the domain of interest in a way that should be accessible, informative, and complete for their final recipients. In this context, philosophers are not required to sketch the historical background of ontology. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cognisance and cognitive science. Part two: Towards an empirical psychology of cognisance.James Russell - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (2):165-201.
    Abstract In the first part of this essay (Russell, 1988a) I argued that ?cognisance? (roughly: a subject's knowledge of his relation to the physical world as an experiencer of it) cannot be explained in terms of a syntactic theory of mind, due to the ?referential? and ?holistic? nature of this knowledge. The syntactic account of the higher mental functions is immediately intelligible to us due to its derivation from computer technology, so this would not appear to be a happy result (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Category mistakes and classification.Robert Sharpe - 1967 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 10 (1-4):204-207.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Twardowski's theory of modification againts the background of traditional logic.Roberto Poli - 1993 - Axiomathes 4 (1):41-57.
  • Three conditions on conceptual naturalness.Daniel N. Osherson - 1978 - Cognition 6 (4):263-289.
  • The more things change…: Metamorphoses and conceptual structure.Michael H. Kelly & Frank C. Keil - 1985 - Cognitive Science 9 (4):403-416.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Parsons and possible objects.Stephen Cade Hetherington - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):246 – 254.
  • Aristotelian categories and cognitive domains.Ian Hacking - 2001 - Synthese 126 (3):473 - 515.
    This paper puts together an ancientand a recent approach to classificatory language, thought, and ontology.It includes on the one hand an interpretation of Aristotle's ten categories,with remarks on his first category, called (or translated as) substancein the Categories or What a thing is in the Topics. On the other hand is the ideaof domain-specific cognitive abilities urged in contemporary developmentalpsychology. Each family of ideas can be used to understand the other. Neitherthe metaphysical nor the psychological approach is intrinsically morefundamental; they (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Revealing ontological commitments by magic.Thomas L. Griffiths - 2015 - Cognition 136 (C):43-48.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Predicates, relations and categories.L. Goddard - 1966 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 44 (2):139 – 171.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Sommers' theory and the paradox of confirmation.George Englebretsen - 1971 - Philosophy of Science 38 (3):438-441.
    In order to confirm any statement of the form A are B we consider a sufficiently large number of A in order to check them for having or failing to have property B. But logic leads us to believe that A are B is equivalent to non-B are non-A. If this is so then it seems reasonable to suppose that we confirm and in the same way. Whatever set of things we consider for confirming one must be the same set (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • La théorie des catégories de Sommers: une nouvelle introduction.George Englebretsen - 1988 - Dialogue 27 (3):451-473.
    Les travaux de Fred Sommers dans le domaine de l'ontologie ont été l'objet, jusqu'à présent, de beaucoup moins d'attention critique qu'ils ne sont aptes à en susciter. C'est au cours des années soixante que Sommers a élaboré sa théorie et qu'il l'a rendue publique par le moyen d'une série d'articles et de conférences. Bien que ses travaux aient alors fait l'objet de quelques critiques ou commentaires, ils ont, depuis, généralement été passés sous silence. Récemment, la revue Monist a fait paraître (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fred Sommers’ Contributions to Formal Logic.George Englebretsen - 2016 - History and Philosophy of Logic 37 (3):269-291.
    Fred Sommers passed away in October of 2014 in his 92nd year. Having begun his teaching at Columbia University, he eventually became the Harry A. Wolfson Chair in Philosophy at Brandeis University, where he taught from 1963 to 1993. During his long and productive career, Sommers authored or co-authored over 50 books, articles, reviews, etc., presenting his ideas on numerous occasions throughout North America and Europe. His work was characterized by a commitment to the preservation and application of historical insights (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The object bias and the study of scientific revolutions: Lessons from developmental psychology.Xiang Chen - 2007 - Philosophical Psychology 20 (4):479 – 503.
    I propose a new perspective on the study of scientific revolutions. This is a transformation from an object-only perspective to an ontological perspective that properly treats objects and processes as distinct kinds. I begin my analysis by identifying an object bias in the study of scientific revolutions, where it takes the form of representing scientific revolutions as changes in classification of physical objects. I further explore the origins of this object bias. Findings from developmental psychology indicate that children cannot distinguish (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Pre-Theoretical Aspects of Aristotelian Definition and Classification of Animals: The Case for Common Sense.Scott Atran - 1985 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 16 (2):113.
  • Categories.Amie Thomasson - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    A system of categories is a complete list of highest kinds or genera. Traditionally, following Aristotle, these have been thought of as highest genera of entities (in the widest sense of the term), so that a system of categories undertaken in this realist spirit would ideally provide an inventory of everything there is, thus answering the most basic of metaphysical questions: “What is there?”. Skepticism about the possibilities for discerning the different categories of ‘reality itself’ has led others to approach (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations