Results for ' judgments, of sensually ‘agreeable’ and aesthetic judgment of taste'

984 found
Order:
  1.  58
    Mistaking Judgments of the Agreeable and Judgments of Taste.Francis Raven - 2008 - Kritike 2 (2):112-130.
    In the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant develops a rigorous formulation of aesthetic judgments, in which he makes a sharp distinction between judgments of taste and judgments of the agreeable if only to dismiss judgments of the agreeable as worthy objects of study. Kant is primarily concerned with judgments of taste, the main example of which is judging something to be beautiful. He asserts that such judgments are subjective, universal, necessary, disinterested, and do not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  6
    Aesthetic Attributes in Wine.Douglas Burnham & Ole Martin Skilleås - 2012-07-16 - In Dominic McIver Lopes & Berys Gaut (eds.), The Aesthetics of Wine. Wiley. pp. 97–139.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Canary Wine and Beyond Wine, the Analogy with Art, and Expression Dewey Seeing As and Seeing In Critical Rhetoric The Institutional Theories Attention, Attitude and Appreciation Aesthetic Attributes and Experiences Aesthetic Experience: What Is It? Functionalist Theories The Necessity of Aesthetic Competency Aesthetic Emergence Aesthetic Competency Notes.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  62
    The intentionality of judgments of taste in Kant's critique of judgment.Joseph Cannon - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (1):53–65.
  4.  9
    The Intentionality of Judgments of Taste in Kant's Critique of Judgment.Joseph Cannon - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66 (1):53-65.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  66
    The Subjective Basis of Kant's Judgment of Taste.Brian Watkins - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (4):315-336.
    Abstract Kant claims that the basis of a judgment of taste is a merely subjective representation and that the only merely subjective representations are feelings of pleasure or displeasure. Commentators disagree over how to interpret this claim. Some take it to mean that judgments about the beauty of an object depend only on the state of the judging subject. Others argue instead that, for Kant, the pleasure we take in a beautiful object is best understood as a response (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  6
    Kant’s Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment[REVIEW]Allen W. Wood - 2003 - Review of Metaphysics 56 (3):633-634.
    Allison begins this book by observing that although the eighteenth century is often called the “age of reason,” it has also been called the “century of taste.” There is a clear enough connection, however, between the two names, for anyone with eyes open enough to see it. For the phenomenon of taste—of likings and dislikings conforming to sharable standards, and invited or sought from others precisely for the sake of sharing them universally—was recognized by eighteenth-century rationalists, and certainly (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Kant’s Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment.Henry Allison - 2001 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This book constitutes one of the most important contributions to recent Kant scholarship. In it, one of the pre-eminent interpreters of Kant, Henry Allison, offers a comprehensive, systematic, and philosophically astute account of all aspects of Kant's views on aesthetics. The first part of the book analyses Kant's conception of reflective judgment and its connections with both empirical knowledge and judgments of taste. The second and third parts treat two questions that Allison insists must be kept distinct: the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  8. The significance of taste: Kant, aesthetic and reflective judgment.Robert B. Pippin - 1996 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (4):549-569.
    The Significance of Taste: Kant, Aesthetic and Reflective Judgment ROBERT B. PIPPIN 1? THE FUNDAMENTAL QUESTION of the "Analytic of the Beautiful" in the "Critique of Aesthetic Judgment" is easy enough to identify. On what basis, if any, could one claim some sort of universal a priori validity for judgments of the form, "This is beautiful"? In Kant's well-known analysis of this question, the issue is reformulated as: By what right could one claim that another (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9.  90
    The conclusion of the deduction of taste in the dialectic of the power of judgment aesthetic in Kant.Manuel Sánchez - 2013 - Trans/Form/Ação 36 (2):45-62.
    In this paper, it is argued that only in the section on dialectic in the Critique of Judgment does Kant reach a definitive and conclusive version of deduction, after discovering the concept of the supersensible. In the section on the deduction of pure aesthetic judgments, Kant does not satisfactorily explain the critical distinction between the sensible nature of humanity and the supersensible nature of human reason presupposed in the concept of universal communicability. While the concept of the supersensible (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The Conclusion of the Deduction of Taste in the Dialectic of Aesthetic Power of Judgment in Kant.Manuel Sánchez Rodríguez - 2013 - Trans/Form/Ação 36 (2):45-62.
    In this paper, it is argued that only in the section on dialectic in the Critique of Judgment does Kant reach a definitive and conclusive version of deduction, after discovering the concept of the supersensible. In the section on the deduction of pure aesthetic judgments, Kant does not satisfactorily explain the critical distinction between the sensible nature of humanity and the supersensible nature of human reason presupposed in the concept of universal communicability. While the concept of the supersensible (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  94
    Kant on Informed Pure Judgments of Taste.Emine Hande Tuna - 2018 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76 (2):163-174.
    Two dominant interpretations of Kant's notion of adherent beauty, the conjunctive view and the incorporation view, provide an account of how to form informed aesthetic assessments concerning artworks. According to both accounts, judgments of perfection play a crucial role in making informed, although impure, judgments of taste. These accounts only examine aesthetic responses to objects that meet or fail to meet the expectations we have regarding what they ought to be. I demonstrate that Kant's works of genius (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12. Kant's theory of the relation of imagination and understanding in aesthetic judgements of taste.Harry Blocker - 1965 - British Journal of Aesthetics 5 (1):37-45.
  13.  12
    Latin Poetry and the Judgment of Taste. An Essay in Aesthetics.S. Stern-Gillet - 2006 - British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (3):319-322.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Logical purposiveness and the principle of taste.Luigi Caranti - 2005 - Kant Studien 96 (3):364-374.
    In both Introductions to the Critique of Judgment Kant seems to identify the a priori principle at the basis of aesthetic judgments with the principle that guides reflective judgment in its cognitive inquiry of nature, i.e. the purposiveness of nature or systematicity. For instance Kant writes.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15.  26
    Kant and the Claims of Taste[REVIEW]R. H. - 1979 - Review of Metaphysics 33 (2):430-432.
    According to Guyer, Kant’s entire aesthetic theory rests on the imputation of intersubjectivity to judgments of taste. Empiricist theories could not establish intersubjectivity; rationalist ones could do so only by construing aesthetic judgment as confused cognitive or moral judgment. But even in the pre-Critical aesthetics, which Guyer teases out of Reflexionen, letters, and student notes, anticipations of a duality in intersubjectivity’s aesthetic function can be found. The first version and the printed version of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  76
    Expression and Objectivity in the Case of Wine: Defending the Aesthetic Terroir of Tastes and Smells.Cain Todd - 2012 - Rivista di Estetica 51:95-115.
    This paper provides an account of the nature of our appreciation of wine, and a defence of the aesthetic value of tastes and smells. Focusing primarily on Roger Scruton’s recent claims, I argue against him that our appreciation of wine meets his own constraints on aesthetic interest and, moreover, that the cultural significance he grants to wine is in large part grounded in its aesthetic value. I show that Scruton’s claims are thus in tension with each other, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  22
    Living Freedom: The Heautonomy of the Judgement of Taste.Zhengmi Zhouhuang - 2024 - Kantian Review 29 (1):81-102.
    Different from the autonomy of understanding in cognition and the autonomy of practical reason in praxis, the heautonomy in the judgement of taste is reflexive. The reflexivity consists not only in the fact that the power of judgement legislates to its own usage but also, and more importantly, it legislates to itself through its own operative process. This normativity, based on the self-referential structure of pure aesthetic judgement and the a priori principle of subjective, internal purposiveness, can be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  77
    Does Wine Have a Place in Kant’s Theory of Taste?Rachel Cristy - 2016 - Journal of the American Philosophical Association 2 (1):36--54.
    Kant claims in the third Critique that one can make about wine the merely subjective judgment that it is agreeable but never the universally valid judgment that it is beautiful. This follows from his views that judgments of beauty can be made only about the formal (spatiotemporal) features of a representation and that aromas and flavors consist of formless sensory matter. However, I argue that Kant's theory permits judgments of beauty about wine because the experience displays a temporal (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  77
    Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment (review). [REVIEW]Paul Guyer - 2002 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (3):406-408.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 40.3 (2002) 406-408 [Access article in PDF] Book Review Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment Henry E. Allison. Kant's Theory of Taste: A Reading of the Critique of Aesthetic Judgment. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2001. Pp. xvi + 424. Cloth, $69.95. Paper, $24.95. In his new book, Henry Allison provides (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Kann aus dem Urteil über das Angenehme ein Geschmacksurteil ähnlich wie aus dem Wahrnehmungsurteil ein Erfahrungsurteil werden? (Can a Judgment About the Agreeable Become a Judgment of Taste, As a Judgment of Perception Can Become a Judgment of Experience?).Christian Helmut Wenzel - 2001 - In Volker Gerhardt, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Ralph Schumacher (eds.), Kant und die Berliner Aufklärung. Akten des IX. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, vol. 3. Walter de Gruyter. pp. 468-476.
  21.  69
    Reflection: Its Structure and Meaning in Kant’s Judgments of Taste.Kristi Sweet - 2009 - Kantian Review 14 (1):53-80.
    When Kant announces in a letter to Reinhold that he has discovered a new domain of a priori principles, he situates these principles in a ‘faculty of feeling pleasure and displeasure ’. And it is indeed in his Critique of Aesthetic Judgement, named in this letter the Critique of Taste, that we find his elucidation of the relation of the principle of purposiveness to the feeling of pleasure. The kinds of judgements in which our feelings are evaluated in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Maggots are delicious, sunsets hideous: false, or do you just disagree? Data on truth relativism about judgments of personal taste and aesthetics.Dylan Murray - 2020 - In Tania Lombrozo, Shaun Nichols & Joshua Knobe (eds.), Oxford Studies in Experimental Philosophy Volume 3. Oxford University Press. pp. 64-96.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. The Hope of Agreement: Against Vibing Accounts of Aesthetic Judgment.Nat Hansen & Zed Adams - 2023 - Mind.
    Stanley Cavell’s account of aesthetic judgment has two components. The first is a feeling: the judge has to see, hear, ‘dig’ something in the object being judged, there has to be an ‘emotion’ that the judge feels and expresses. The second is the ‘discipline of accounting for [the judgment]’, a readiness to argue for one’s aesthetic judgment in the face of disagreement. The discipline of accounting for one’s aesthetic judgments involves what Nick Riggle has (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Can kants deduction of judgments of taste be saved?Miles Rind - 2002 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 84 (1):20-45.
    Kant’s argument in § 38 of the *Critique of Judgment* is subject to a dilemma: if the subjective condition of cognition is the sufficient condition of the pleasure of taste, then every object of experience must produce that pleasure; if not, then the universal communicability of cognition does not entail the universal communicability of the pleasure. Kant’s use of an additional premise in § 21 may get him out of this difficulty, but the premises themselves hang in the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25. The Role of Transcendental Idealism in Kant's Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgment.Andrew Ward - unknown
    A defence of the view that the introduction of transendental idealism, in the Dialectic of Aesthetic Judgment, plays a central role in resolving the antinomy which, as Kant contends, exists in our pure judgments of taste. It is further argued that the link that he holds to exist between the realms of nature and morality (or freedom) can only be successfully made out if transcendental idealism is accepted as underpinning our judgments concerning the beauties of nature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  31
    The Salonnieres and the Philosophes in Old Regime France: The Authority of Aesthetic Judgment.Jolanta T. Pekacz - 1999 - Journal of the History of Ideas 60 (2):277.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Salonnières and the Philosophes in Old Regime France: The Authority of Aesthetic Judgment*Jolanta T. PekaczDuring the eighteenth century a significant shift occurred in the perception of the authority of aesthetic judgment in France, from a group usually referred to as “polite society” and widely considered the exclusive source of taste (goût) to various competing groups arrogating to themselves the right to judge artistic (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Autonomy and Community in Kant's Theory of Taste.Jessica J. Williams - forthcoming - The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.
    In this paper, I argue that Kant has a far more communitarian theory of aesthetic life than is usually acknowledged. I focus on two aspects of Kant’s theory that might otherwise be taken to support an individualist reading, namely, Kant’s emphasis on aesthetic autonomy and his characterization of judgments of taste as involving demands for agreement. I argue that the full expression of autonomy in fact requires being a member of an aesthetic community and that within (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  22
    Martindale (C.) Latin Poetry and the Judgement of Taste. An Essay in Aesthetics . Pp. x + 265. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. Cased, £50. ISBN: 0-19-924040-X. [REVIEW]Richard Jenkyns - 2006 - The Classical Review 56 (01):102-.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  6
    Martindale Latin Poetry and the Judgement of Taste. An Essay in Aesthetics. Pp. x + 265. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. Cased, £50. ISBN: 0-19-924040-X. [REVIEW]Richard Jenkyns - 2006 - The Classical Review 56 (1):102-104.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  14
    Critical Aesthetics. Baumgarten and the Logic of Taste.Alessandro Nannini - 2021 - Aesthetic Investigations 4 (2):201-218.
    In this essay, I discuss Baumgarten’s neglected doctrine of taste. In particular I investigate his definition of taste as the judgment of the senses against the backdrop of the philosophical debate of his day, pointing out the biblical and classical sources of the idea of a judging aisthesis. In addition, I analyse the radical change that the definition of taste as the judgment of the senses brings about in the idea of both taste and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Aesthetic judgment.Nick Zangwill - 2003 - The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Beauty is an important part of our lives. Ugliness too. It is no surprise then that philosophers since antiquity have been interested in our experiences of and judgments about beauty and ugliness. They have tried to understand the nature of these experiences and judgments, and they have also wanted to know whether these experiences and judgments were legitimate. Both these projects took a sharpened form in the twentieth century, when this part of our lives came under a sustained attack in (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  32. On Standard and Taste. Wittgenstein and Aesthetic Judgment.Jean-Pierre Cometti - 2013 - Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 6 (1):5-15.
    The question of aesthetic judgment is related to a lot of paradoxes that have marked sustainably the reflection on arts, and even arts as such during their modern history. These paradoxes have found a first formulation, apparently clear, in the very famous Hume's essay: "On the standard of taste", but without to lead to a real resolution. In this paper, I would like to approach the question of Hume by starting from what Wittgenstein suggested about aesthetic (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Aesthetic representation of purposiveness and the concept of beauty in Kant’s aesthetics. The solution of the ‘everything is beautiful’ problem.Mojca Küplen - 2016 - Philosophical Inquiries 4 (2):69-88.
    In the Critique of the Power of Judgment, Kant introduces the notion of the reflective judgment and the a priori principle of purposiveness or systematicity of nature. He claims that the ability to judge objects by means of this principle underlies empirical concept acquisition and it is therefore necessary for cognition in general. In addition, he suggests that there is a connection between this principle and judgments of taste. Kant’s account of this connection has been criticized by (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  27
    Beauty and the Behest: Distinguishing Legal Judgment and Aesthetic Judgment in the Context of 21st Century Street Art and Graffiti.Andrea Baldini - 2017 - Rivista di Estetica 65:91-106.
    Street art and graffiti are on the rise and their problematic relationship with the law is becoming an increasingly pressing issue. This paper considers a series of high profile street art controversies involving famous street artists Banksy and Alice Pasquini as cases studies for illuminating such a relationship. First, by discussing the “Banksy’s Law” – a “law” protecting street artworks in the style of Banksy while condemning graffiti – and its perceived arbitrariness, I investigate what I call the structural differences (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  65
    Aesthetic solidarity "after" Kant and Lyotard.Bart Vandenabeele - 2008 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 42 (4):pp. 17-30.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Aesthetic Solidarity "after" Kant and LyotardBart Vandenabeele (bio)Whatever view we hold, it must be shown / Why every lover has a wish to make / Some other kind of otherness his own: / Perhaps in fact we never are alone.—W. H. AudenIntroductionUndoubtedly one of the most fascinating aspects of Kant's aesthetics is the link that the Königsberg philosopher establishes between aesthetic judging and the idea of being-together (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Kant and the Claims of Taste.Paul Guyer - 1979 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Kant and the Claims of Taste, published here for the first time in paperback in a revised version, has become, since its initial publication in 1979, the standard commentary on Kant's aesthetic theory. The book offers a detailed account of Kant's views on judgments of taste, aesthetic pleasure, imagination and many other topics. For this new edition, Paul Guyer has provided a new foreword and has added a chapter on Kant's conception of fine art. This re-issue (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  37. Ethical dimensions of the pure judgement of taste in Kant's aesthetics.O. Bakos - 2003 - Filozofia 58 (3):147-154.
    The paper deals with pure judgments of taste in Kant's aesthetics regarding the meaning they achieve due to the presence of the other subject. In his Critique of Judgment Kant defines the subject as a physical individual endowed with feelings, related not only to objects, but rather expanding this relation on the community of others. Therefore, the aesthetic relation to an object, which is the precondition of the pure judgment of taste, involves implicitly a recquirement (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. The objectivity of aesthetic judgements.M. W. Rowe - 1999 - British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (1):40-52.
    The first half of this article argues that, like judgments as to whether something smells or tastes good, judgments about works of art ultimately depend on an element of subjective response. However, it shows that, unlike gustatory or olfactory judgments, we can argue meaningfully about our experience of works of art because they have _parts<D>. Because works of art have parts these can be patterned by the imagination, and this patterning can be influenced by what is said to us. The (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  33
    Communicative Implications of Kant’s Aesthetic Theory.Thomas Hove - 2009 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 42 (2):pp. 103-114.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Communicative Implications of Kant’s Aesthetic TheoryThomas HoveIn recent discussions of aesthetic theory, critics who raise social, cultural, and political concerns have issued important challenges to the Kantian legacy. Kant’s Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790) continues to be widely regarded as one of the founding documents of modern aesthetic theory. But the arguments he laid out in that notoriously enigmatic work remain controversial on (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40. The Interpersonal Variability of Gustatory Sensation and the Prospects for an Alimentary Aesthetics.Vaughn Bryan Baltzly - 2020 - Intervalla 7 (1):6-16.
    We all have different “tastes” for different tastes: some of us have a sweet tooth, while others prefer more subtle flavors; some crave spicy foods, while others cannot stand them. As Bourdieu and others have pointed out, these varying judgments seem to be more than mere preferences; often they reflect (and partially constitute) differences of class and culture. But I want to suggest that we’ve possibly overlooked another important source of these divergent gastronomic evaluations, other than hierarchy and caste: mere (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Criticism, imagination, and the subjectivation of aesthetics.Roger W. H. Savage - 2005 - Philosophy and Literature 29 (1):164-179.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Criticism, Imagination, and the Subjectivization of AestheticsRoger W. H. SavageThe growing discontent with reductivist practices signals a new current in contemporary criticism's understanding of music, literature and art. George Levine's unease with critics who are unable or unwilling to account for their continuing preoccupation with literary texts they expose as "imperialist, sexist, homophobic and racist" illumines the contradiction fueling the reduction of aesthetics to ideology.1 Cultural studies that deploy (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  23
    Fitness, Fatness, and Aesthetic Judgments of the Female Body: What the AMA Decision to Medicalize Obesity means for other Non–Normal Female Bodies.Sara R. Jordan - 2014 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 4 (2):101-104.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Fitness, Fatness, and Aesthetic Judgments of the Female Body:What the AMA Decision to Medicalize Obesity means for other Non–Normal Female BodiesSara R. Jordan“I’ll be happy to refer you to our dietician to get you on a program to help you get your weight under control before it becomes a problem”.As my new physician spun around out of the examination room door, my head spun faster. I had heard (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  51
    Kant on the Science of Aesthetics and the Critique of Taste.J. Colin McQuillan - 2017 - Kant Yearbook 9 (1):113-132.
    This article considers the reasons Kant rejects the possibility of a science of aesthetics throughout his career. It begins by surveying the background of Kant’s denial, focusing first on the introduction of aesthetics as a new science in the works of Alexander Baumgarten and Georg Friedrich Meier. After showing that there are numerous ambiguities in the way Baumgarten and Meier present their new science, the article considers Kant’s account of the differences between aesthetics and logic in the transcripts of his (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. Kant's theory of judgment, and judgments of taste: On Henry Allison's "Kant's theory of taste".Béatrice Longuenesse - 2003 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 46 (2):143 – 163.
    Kant's use of the leading thread of his table of logical forms of judgment to analyze judgments of taste yields more results than Allison's account allows. It reveals in judgments of taste the combination of two judgments: a descriptive judgment about the object, and a normative judgment about the judging subjects. Core arguments of Kant's critique of taste receive new light from this analysis.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45. Judgments of Taste and Analysis of the Problem of Ugliness in Kant’s Aesthetics.Mojca Küplen - 2015 - In Mojca Küplen (ed.), Beauty, Ugliness and the Free Play of Imagination: an approach to Kant's Aesthetics. Cham: Springer Verlag.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  13
    Taste and the claims of war: the Kantian sublime and the function of war in public aesthetic judgement.Lucian Staiano-Daniels - 2023 - History of European Ideas 49 (5):822-835.
    Although Kant disapproved of war, he asserted it was sublime. His views of war are disconnected and in places surprisingly positive, but he avoids grappling with their implications. This article analyses these heterogeneous discussions through Kant’s notion of the sublime to argue that some of his statements imply war’s sublimity can provoke an educated public into forming an international federation: the power to keep all in awe in Kant’s interpretation of international foundation is not the Hobbesean sovereign or a coercive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  89
    Hume and the Standard of Taste.Christopher MacLachlan - 1986 - Hume Studies 12 (1):18-38.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:18 HUME AND THE STANDARD OF TASTE David Hume's critical theories, although fragmentary, have drawn increasingly serious attention in the twentieth century, yet even in 1976 Peter Jones, in reassessing Hume's aesthetics, can describe one of the most substantial of his critical essays, "Of the Standard of Taste," as underrated. Jones praises it as "subtle and highly complex," but while I agree with that judgment I (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  75
    On the Notion of "Disinterestedness": Kant, Lyotard, and Schopenhauer.Bart Vandenabeele - 2001 - Journal of the History of Ideas 62 (4):705-720.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Ideas 62.4 (2001) 705-720 [Access article in PDF] On the Notion of "Disinterestedness": Kant, Lyotard, and Schopenhauer Bart Vandenabeele The strange thing, on looking back, was the purity, the integrity, of her feeling for Sally. It was not like one's feeling for a man. It was completely disinterested, and besides, it had a quality which could only exist between women, between women just grown (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  73
    On Nietzsche's Judgment of Style and Hume's Quixotic Taste: On the Science of Aesthetics and "Playing" the Satyr.Babette Babich - 2012 - Journal of Nietzsche Studies 43 (2):240-259.
    "Homer and Classical Philology," Nietzsche's 1869 inaugural lecture at the University of Basel, addresses not only the history of the Homer question as a problem but also raises the question of the discipline of classical philology as science . Thematically, Nietzsche's first lecture as a professor of classical philology focuses on the significance of style as such. In this meta-scholarly context, the issue of scholarly discernment is explored in terms of aesthetic judgment, as a judgment of (...), a focus Nietzsche subsequently resumes in the second of his Untimely Meditations, "On the Utility and Liability of History for Life."1 To be . (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  53
    Reading David Hume’s » Of the Standard of Taste «.Babette E. Babich (ed.) - 2019 - Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.
    This collection dedicated to and including David Hume's "Of the Standard of Taste," offers a much needed resource for students and scholars of philosophical aesthetics, political reflection, value and judgments, economics, and art. The authors include experts in the philosophy of art, aesthetics, history of philosophy as well as the history of science. Contributors include Babette Babich, Howard Caygill, Timothy M.Costelloe, Andrej Démuth / Slávka Démuthová, Bernard Freydberg, Peter Kivy, Carolyn Korsmeyer, Christopher MacLachlan, Emilio Mazza, Roger Schiner, Roger Scruton, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 984