Results for ' ‘slave boy’, recalling geometrical theorem'

988 found
Order:
  1.  5
    Pythagoras Counts up to Ten (ca. 570–495 BCE).Martin Cohen - 2008 - In Martin Cohen & Raul Gonzalez (eds.), Philosophical Tales: Being an Alternative History Revealing the Characters, the Plots, and the Hidden Scenes That Make Up the True Story of Philosophy. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 33–40.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  46
    Inquiry.Nicholas P. White - 1974 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (2):289 - 310.
    AS SOME PHILOSOPHERS KNOW, the paradox about inquiry at 80d-e of Plato’s Meno is more than a tedious sophism. Plato is one such philosopher. The puzzle is an obstacle to his project of discovering definitions, and is introduced as such. And it is met with an elaborate response: the theory of recollection, explicitly presented as an answer to the obstacle. But then what of the famous conversation in which Socrates coaxes a geometrical theorem from a slave boy Is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  3.  9
    On Geometric Implications.Amirhossein Akbar Tabatabai - forthcoming - Studia Logica:1-30.
    It is a well-known fact that although the poset of open sets of a topological space is a Heyting algebra, its Heyting implication is not necessarily stable under the inverse image of continuous functions and hence is not a geometric concept. This leaves us wondering if there is any stable family of implications that can be safely called geometric. In this paper, we will first recall the abstract notion of implication as a binary modality introduced in Akbar Tabatabai (Implication via (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  13
    Neurophysiological correlates of memory change in children with fetal alcohol spectrum disorders treated with choline.Anita J. Fuglestad, Neely C. Miller, Birgit A. Fink, Christopher J. Boys, Judith K. Eckerle, Michael K. Georgieff & Jeffrey R. Wozniak - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    BackgroundPrenatal and early postnatal choline supplementation reduces cognitive and behavioral deficits in animal models of Fetal Alcohol Spectrum Disorder. In a previously published 9-month clinical trial of choline supplementation in children with FASD, we reported that postnatal choline was associated with improved performance on a hippocampal-dependent recognition memory task. The current paper describes the neurophysiological correlates of that memory performance for trial completers.MethodsChildren with FASD who were enrolled in a clinical trial of choline supplementation were followed for 9 months. Delayed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  37
    Two Geometrical Examples From Aristotle's Metaphysics.Henry Mendell - 1984 - Classical Quarterly 34 (02):359-.
    The discussion of mathematical knowledge and its relation to the construction of an appropriate diagram in Aristotle's Metaphysics Θ 9. 1051 a21—33 is an important, if compressed, account of Aristotle's most mature thoughts on mathematical knowledge. The discussion of what sort of previous knowledge one must have for understanding a theorem recalls the discussion at An. Post. A 1. 71 a 17–21, where the epistemological point is similar and the examples the same. The first example, that the interior angles (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  16
    Laue's Theorem Revisited: Energy-Momentum Tensors, Symmetries, and the Habitat of Globally Conserved Quantities.Domenico Giulini - 2018 - International Journal of Geometric Methods in Modern Physics 15 (10).
    The energy-momentum tensor for a particular matter component summarises its local energy-momentum distribution in terms of densities and current densities. We re-investigate under what conditions these local distributions can be integrated to meaningful global quantities. This leads us directly to a classic theorem by Max von Laue concerning integrals of components of the energy-momentum tensor, whose statement and proof we recall. In the first half of this paper we do this within the realm of Special Relativity and in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  58
    Plato Disapproves of the Slave-Boy's Answer.Malcolm S. Brown - 1967 - Review of Metaphysics 21 (1):57 - 93.
    As with the dialogue, so with the slave-boy episode within it, two questions are handled, one of them substantive, the other a question of method. The substantive question is how to double the square of a side of 2 units; the procedural question is how, if at all, can an answer be found by one who does not know it. It develops that the answer must be sought exclusively among opinions which the boy already holds, by means of questioning. What (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  9
    Geometric theorem proving by integrated logical and algebraic reasoning.Takashi Matsuyama & Tomoaki Nitta - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 75 (1):93-113.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Meno's Paradox, the Slave‐Boy Interrogation, and the Unity of Platonic Recollection.Lee Franklin - 2009 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 47 (4):349-377.
    Plato invokes the Theory of Recollection to explain both ordinary and philosophical learning. In a new reading of Meno's Paradox and the Slave‐Boy Interrogation, I explain why these two levels are linked in a single theory of learning. Since, for Plato, philosophical inquiry starts in ordinary discourse, the possibility of success in inquiry is tied to the character of the ordinary comprehension we bring to it. Through the claim that all learning is recollection, Plato traces the knowledge achievable through inquiry (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Freeing Meno's Slave Boy: Scaffolded Learning in the Philosophy Classroom.Robert Colter & Joseph Ulatowski - 2015 - Teaching Philosophy 38 (1):25-49.
    This paper argues that a well known passage from Plato’s Meno exemplifies how to employ scaffolded learning in the philosophy classroom. It explores scaffolded learning by fully defining it, explaining it, and gesturing at some ways in which scaffolding has been implemented. We then offer our own model of scaffolded learning in terms of four phases and eight stages, and explicate our model using a well known example from Plato’s Meno as an exemplar. We believe that any practical concerns one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  98
    Meno, the Slave Boy and the Elenchos.Hugh H. Benson - 1990 - Phronesis 35 (1):128-158.
  12.  70
    Hume and Derrida on Language and Meaning.Fred Wilson - 1986 - Hume Studies 12 (2):99-121.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:99 HUME AND DERRIDA ON LANGUAGE AND MEANING "...Language itself is menaced in its very life, helpless, adrift in the threat of limitlessness, brought back to its own finitude at the very moment when its limits seem to disappear, when it ceases to be self-assured, contained, and guaranteed by the infinite signified which seemed to exceed it." Is this true? What does it mean? Derrida is making a contrast (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  10
    A Re-examination of the Slave-boy Interview.John E. Thomas - 1970 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 26 (1):17.
  14.  2
    Inquiry in plato's meno what are we supposed to learn from the experiment with the slave boy?Larry J. Waggle - 2004 - Auslegung 27 (1):31-46.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  25
    Roles of diagrammatic information for the discovery of geometrical theorems.Tsuyoshi Murata - 2004 - In A. Blackwell, K. Marriott & A. Shimojima (eds.), Diagrammatic Representation and Inference. Springer. pp. 235--238.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Aporia and Philosophy: A Commentary on Plato's "Meno".Joe Mccoy - 2001 - Dissertation, Boston University
    This dissertation concerns the central role of aporia in philosophical thought and Platonic philosophy. In contrast with the standard sense of aporia as a perplexity that clears away an interlocutor's ignorance and pretension, I argue that aporia is a necessary step in the movement from ignorance to knowledge. Aporia thus involves a kind of understanding that in principle leads one out of perplexity to knowledge. This conception of aporia also reveals, I argue a connection between Platonic metaphysical doctrines, such as (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Can a proof compel us?Cesare Cozzo - 2005 - In C. Cellucci D. Gillies (ed.), Mathematical Reasoning and Heuristics. King's College Publications. pp. 191-212.
    The compulsion of proofs is an ancient idea, which plays an important role in Plato’s dialogues. The reader perhaps recalls Socrates’ question to the slave boy in the Meno: “If the side of a square A is 2 feet, and the corresponding area is 4, how long is the side of a square whose area is double, i.e. 8?”. The slave answers: “Obviously, Socrates, it will be twice the length” (cf. Me 82-85). A straightforward analogy: if the area is double, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. NeutroGeometry & AntiGeometry are alternatives and generalizations of the Non-Euclidean Geometries (revisited).Florentin Smarandache - 2021 - Neutrosophic Sets and Systems 46 (1):456-477.
    In this paper we extend the NeutroAlgebra & AntiAlgebra to the geometric spaces, by founding the NeutroGeometry & AntiGeometry. While the Non-Euclidean Geometries resulted from the total negation of one specific axiom (Euclid’s Fifth Postulate), the AntiGeometry results from the total negation of any axiom or even of more axioms from any geometric axiomatic system (Euclid’s, Hilbert’s, etc.) and from any type of geometry such as (Euclidean, Projective, Finite, Affine, Differential, Algebraic, Complex, Discrete, Computational, Molecular, Convex, etc.) Geometry, and the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  18
    Socratic Perplexity and the Nature of Philosophy, and: The Philosophy of Socrates (review).Roslyn Weiss - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (1):137-139.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.1 (2001) 137-139 [Access article in PDF] Gareth B. Matthews. Socratic Perplexity and the Nature of Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 1999. Pp. 137. Cloth, $29.95 Thomas C. Brickhouse and Nicholas D. Smith. The Philosophy of Socrates. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 2000. Pp. x + 290. Paper $22.00. Matthews' little book tracks the course of Socrates' perplexity, which, Matthews contends, starts out (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. La Neutro-Geometría y la Anti-Geometría como Alternativas y Generalizaciones de las Geometrías no Euclidianas.Florentin Smarandache - 2022 - Neutrosophic Computing and Machine Learning 20 (1):91-104.
    In this paper we extend Neutro-Algebra and Anti-Algebra to geometric spaces, founding Neutro/Geometry and AntiGeometry. While Non-Euclidean Geometries resulted from the total negation of a specific axiom (Euclid's Fifth Postulate), AntiGeometry results from the total negation of any axiom or even more axioms of any geometric axiomatic system (Euclidean, Hilbert, etc. ) and of any type of geometry such as Geometry (Euclidean, Projective, Finite, Differential, Algebraic, Complex, Discrete, Computational, Molecular, Convex, etc.), and Neutro-Geometry results from the partial negation of one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  58
    A Weyl-Type Theorem for Geometrized Newtonian Gravity.Erik Curiel - unknown
    I state and prove, in the context of a space having only the metrical structure imposed by the geometrized version of Newtonian gravitational theory, a theorem analagous to that of Weyl's in a Lorentzian space. The theorem, loosely speaking, says that a projective structure and a suitably defined compatible conformal structure on such a space jointly suffice for fixing the metrical structure of a Newtonian spacetime model up to constant factors. It allows one to give a natural, physically (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. Towards a geometrical understanding of the cpt theorem.Hilary Greaves - 2010 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 61 (1):27-50.
    The CPT theorem of quantum field theory states that any relativistic (Lorentz-invariant) quantum field theory must also be invariant under CPT, the composition of charge conjugation, parity reversal and time reversal. This paper sketches a puzzle that seems to arise when one puts the existence of this sort of theorem alongside a standard way of thinking about symmetries, according to which spacetime symmetries (at any rate) are associated with features of the spacetime structure. The puzzle is, roughly, that (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  51
    A characterization theorem for geometric logic.Olivia Caramello - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (4):318-321.
    We establish a criterion for deciding whether a class of structures is the class of models of a geometric theory inside Grothendieck toposes; then we specialize this result to obtain a characterization of the infinitary first-order theories which are geometric in terms of their models in Grothendieck toposes, solving a problem posed by Ieke Moerdijk in 1989.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  14
    Can We Identify the Theorem in Metaphysics 9, 1051a24-27 with Euclid’s Proposition 32? Geometric Deductions for the Discovery of Mathematical Knowledge.Francisco Miguel Ortiz Delgado - 2023 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 33 (66):41-65.
    This paper has two specific goals. The first is to demonstrate that the theorem in MetaphysicsΘ 9, 1051a24-27 is not equiva-lent to Euclid’s Proposition 32 of book I (which contradicts some Aristotelian commentators, such as W. D. Ross, J. L. Heiberg, and T. L. Heith). Agreeing with Henry Mendell’s analysis, I ar-gue that the two theorems are not equivalent, but I offer different reasons for such divergence: I propose a pedagogical-philosoph-ical reason for the Aristotelian theorem being shorter than (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  17
    Sen's theorem: Geometric proof, new interpretations.Lingfang Li & Donald G. Saari - manuscript
    Sen's classic social choice result supposedly demonstrates a conflict between Pareto and even minimal forms of liberalism. By providing the first direct mathematical proof of this seminal result, we underscore a significantly different interpretation: rather than conflicts among rights, Sen's result occurs because the liberalism assumption negates the assumption that voters have transitive preferences. This explanation enriches interpretations of Sen's conclusion by including radically new kinds of societal conflicts, it suggests ways to sidestep these difficulties, and it explains earlier approaches (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  26
    Barrow, Leibniz and the Geometrical Proof of the Fundamental Theorem of the Calculus.Michael Nauenberg - 2014 - Annals of Science 71 (3):335-354.
    SummaryIn 1693, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz published in the Acta Eruditorum a geometrical proof of the fundamental theorem of the calculus. It is shown that this proof closely resembles Isaac Barrow's proof in Proposition 11, Lecture 10, of his Lectiones Geometricae, published in 1670. This comparison provides evidence that Leibniz gained substantial help from Barrow's book in formulating and presenting his geometrical formulation of this theorem. The analysis herein also supports the work of J. M. Child, who (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  9
    Remarks on Barr’s Theorem: Proofs in Geometric Theories.Michael Rathjen - 2016 - In Peter Schuster & Dieter Probst (eds.), Concepts of Proof in Mathematics, Philosophy, and Computer Science. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 347-374.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  71
    Contraction-free sequent calculi for geometric theories with an application to Barr's theorem.Sara Negri - 2003 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 42 (4):389-401.
    Geometric theories are presented as contraction- and cut-free systems of sequent calculi with mathematical rules following a prescribed rule-scheme that extends the scheme given in Negri and von Plato. Examples include cut-free calculi for Robinson arithmetic and real closed fields. As an immediate consequence of cut elimination, it is shown that if a geometric implication is classically derivable from a geometric theory then it is intuitionistically derivable.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  29.  70
    Piron's and Bell's Geometric Lemmas and Gleason's Theorem.Georges Chevalier, Anatolij Dvurečenskij & Karl Svozil - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (10):1737-1755.
    We study the idea of implantation of Piron's and Bell's geometrical lemmas for proving some results concerning measures on finite as well as infinite-dimensional Hilbert spaces, including also measures with infinite values. In addition, we present parabola based proofs of weak Piron's geometrical and Bell's lemmas. These approaches will not used directly Gleason's theorem, which is a highly non-trivial result.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  10
    Geometric Rules in Infinitary Logic.Sara Negri - 2021 - In Ofer Arieli & Anna Zamansky (eds.), Arnon Avron on Semantics and Proof Theory of Non-Classical Logics. Springer Verlag. pp. 265-293.
    Large portions of mathematics such as algebra and geometry can be formalized using first-order axiomatizations. In many cases it is even possible to use a very well-behaved class of first-order axioms, namely, what are called coherent or geometric implications. Such class of axioms can be translated to inference rules that can be added to a sequent calculus while preserving its structural properties. In this work, this fundamental result is extended to their infinitary generalizations as extensions of sequent calculi for both (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31. A Geometrical Characterization of the Twin Paradox and its Variants.Gergely Székely - 2010 - Studia Logica 95 (1-2):161 - 182.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a logic-based conceptual analysis of the twin paradox (TwP) theorem within a first-order logic framework. A geometrical characterization of TwP and its variants is given. It is shown that TwP is not logically equivalent to the assumption of the slowing down of moving clocks, and the lack of TwP is not logically equivalent to the Newtonian assumption of absolute time. The logical connection between TwP and a symmetry axiom of special (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  68
    Boy! What Boy?Rick Benitez - 2016 - Ancient Philosophy 36 (1):107-114.
    This paper corrects the common misconception that Meno's slave (in Plato's dialogue of that name) is a boy. The first part of the paper shows how long-standing and widespread that misconception is. The description of Meno's slave as a "slave-boy" goes back at least to Benjamin Jowett, and the phrase is still commonly seen today in books and journal articles in philosophy and classics generally, even in presses and journals with the highest reputation. The paper then shows that the Greek (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  17
    Ehrenfest’s Theorem revisited.Henryk Stanisław Arodź - 2019 - Philosophical Problems in Science 66:73-94.
    Historically, Ehrenfest’s theorem is the first one which shows that classical physics can emerge from quantum physics as a kind of approximation. We recall the theorem in its original form, and we highlight its generalizations to the relativistic Dirac particle and to a particle with spin and izospin. We argue that apparent classicality of the macroscopic world can probably be explained within the framework of standard quantum mechanics.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  62
    A geometric proof of the completeness of the łukasiewicz calculus.Giovanni Panti - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):563-578.
    We give a self-contained geometric proof of the completeness theorem for the infinite-valued sentential calculus of Łukasiewicz.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  35.  26
    Geometric Objects and Perspectivalism.James Read - 2022 - In James Read & Nicholas J. Teh (eds.), The Philosophy and Physics of Noether's Theorems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 257-273.
  36. A geometric form of the axiom of choice.J. L. Bell - unknown
    Consider the following well-known result from the theory of normed linear spaces ([2], p. 80, 4(b)): (g) the unit ball of the (continuous) dual of a normed linear space over the reals has an extreme point. The standard proof of (~) uses the axiom of choice (AG); thus the implication AC~(w) can be proved in set theory. In this paper we show that this implication can be reversed, so that (*) is actually eq7I2valent to the axiom of choice. From this (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  18
    The theorem of the means for cardinal and ordinal numbers.George Rousseau - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):279-286.
    The theorem that the arithmetic mean is greater than or equal to the geometric mean is investigated for cardinal and ordinal numbers. It is shown that whereas the theorem of the means can be proved for n pairwise comparable cardinal numbers without the axiom of choice, the inequality a2 + b2 ≥ 2ab is equivalent to the axiom of choice. For ordinal numbers, the inequality α2 + β2 ≥ 2αβ is established and the conditions for equality are derived; (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. A Geometric Look at Manipulation.Jan van Eijck - unknown
    We take a fresh look at voting theory, in particular at the notion of manipulation, by employing the geometry of the Saari triangle. This yields a geometric proof of the Gibbard/Satterthwaite theorem, and new insight into what it means to manipulate the vote. Next, we propose two possible strengthenings of the notion of manipulability (or weakenings of the notion of non-manipulability), and analyze how these affect the impossibility proof for non-manipulable voting rules.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  50
    Partition theorems and computability theory.Joseph R. Mileti - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):411-427.
    The connections between mathematical logic and combinatorics have a rich history. This paper focuses on one aspect of this relationship: understanding the strength, measured using the tools of computability theory and reverse mathematics, of various partition theorems. To set the stage, recall two of the most fundamental combinatorial principles, König's Lemma and Ramsey's Theorem. We denote the set of natural numbers by ω and the set of finite sequences of natural numbers by ω<ω. We also identify each n ∈ (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  40.  46
    Theorems as meaningful cultural artifacts: Making the world additive.Martin H. Krieger - 1991 - Synthese 88 (2):135 - 154.
    Mathematical theorems are cultural artifacts and may be interpreted much as works of art, literature, and tool-and-craft are interpreted. The Fundamental Theorem of the Calculus, the Central Limit Theorem of Statistics, and the Statistical Continuum Limit of field theories, all show how the world may be put together through the arithmetic addition of suitably prescribed parts (velocities, variances, and renormalizations and scaled blocks, respectively). In the limit — of smoothness, statistical independence, and large N — higher-order parts, such (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41.  41
    Topological representation of geometric theories.Henrik Forssell - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (6):380-393.
    Using Butz and Moerdijk's topological groupoid representation of a topos with enough points, a ‘syntax-semantics’ duality for geometric theories is constructed. The emphasis is on a logical presentation, starting with a description of the semantic topological groupoid of models and isomorphisms of a theory. It is then shown how to extract a theory from equivariant sheaves on a topological groupoid in such a way that the result is a contravariant adjunction between theories and groupoids, the restriction of which is a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  33
    Geometric significance of the spinor Lie derivative. II.V. Jhangiani - 1978 - Foundations of Physics 8 (7-8):593-601.
    The formulas for the Lie covariant differentiation of spinors are deduced from an algebraic viewpoint. The Lie covariant derivative of the spinor connection is calculated, and is given a geometric meaning. A theorem about the Lie covariant derivative of an operator in spin space that was stated in Part I of this work is discussed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  29
    Stability in geometric theories.Jerry Gagelman - 2005 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 132 (2-3):313-326.
    The class of geometric surgical theories is examined. The main theorem is that every stable theory that is interpretable in a geometric surgical theory is superstable of finite U-rank.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  44. Range theorems for quantum probability and entanglement.Itamar Pitowsky - unknown
    We consider the set of all matrices of the form pij = tr[W (Ei ⊗ Fj)] where Ei, Fj are projections on a Hilbert space H, and W is some state on H ⊗ H. We derive the basic properties of this set, compare it with the classical range of probability, and note how its properties may be related to a geometric measures of entanglement.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  52
    On lovely pairs of geometric structures.Alexander Berenstein & Evgueni Vassiliev - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (7):866-878.
    We study the theory of lovely pairs of geometric structures, in particular o-minimal structures. We use the pairs to isolate a class of geometric structures called weakly locally modular which generalizes the class of linear structures in the settings of SU-rank one theories and o-minimal theories. For o-minimal theories, we use the Peterzil–Starchenko trichotomy theorem to characterize for a sufficiently general point, the local geometry around it in terms of the thorn U-rank of its type inside a lovely pair.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  46.  11
    Logiḳah be-peʻulah =.Doron Avital - 2012 - Or Yehudah: Zemorah-Bitan, motsiʼim le-or.
    Logic in Action/Doron Avital Nothing is more difficult, and therefore more precious, than to be able to decide (Napoleon Bonaparte) Introduction -/- This book was born on the battlefield and in nights of secretive special operations all around the Middle East, as well as in the corridors and lecture halls of Western Academia best schools. As a young boy, I was always mesmerized by stories of great men and women of action at fateful cross-roads of decision-making. Then, like as today, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  94
    The geometrical aspects of the bell inequalities.Alexei A. Tyapkin & Milan Vindushka - 1991 - Foundations of Physics 21 (2):185-195.
    The Bell inequalities of the metric form are introduced. The quantum-mechanical correlations of the particles with s=1/2 and photons are described using the relative measure of probability on the concave surfaces. The relation of the proposed scheme with the Bayes theorem about conditional information entropy and J. von Neumann's postulates is discussed.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  16
    An algebraic theory of normal forms.Silvio Ghilardi - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 71 (3):189-245.
    In this paper we present a general theory of normal forms, based on a categorial result for the free monoid construction. We shall use the theory mainly for proposictional modal logic, although it seems to have a wider range of applications. We shall formally represent normal forms as combinatorial objects, basically labelled trees and forests. This geometric conceptualization is implicit in and our approach will extend it to other cases and make it more direct: operations of a purely geometric and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  49.  25
    Euclid's Optics and Geometrical Astronomy.Colin Webster - 2014 - Apeiron 47 (4):526-551.
    This paper seeks to demonstrate that propositions 23–27 of the Euclidian Optics originated in the context of geometrical astronomy. These entries, which deal with the geometry of spheres and rays, present material that overlaps considerably with propositions 1–3 of Aristarchus of Samos’ On the Sizes and Distances of the Sun and the Moon. While all these theorems deal with material that could conceivably be native to celestial illumination, the proofs do not work for binocular vision. It therefore seems probable (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  17
    Situating the Debate on “Geometrical Algebra” within the Framework of Premodern Algebra.Michalis Sialaros & Jean Christianidis - 2016 - Science in Context 29 (2):129-150.
    ArgumentThe aim of this paper is to employ the newly contextualized historiographical category of “premodern algebra” in order to revisit the arguably most controversial topic of the last decades in the field of Greek mathematics, namely the debate on “geometrical algebra.” Within this framework, we shift focus from the discrepancy among the views expressed in the debate to some of the historiographical assumptions and methodological approaches that the opposing sides shared. Moreover, by using a series of propositions related toElem.II.5 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 988