Results for 'James Owings'

983 found
Order:
  1.  16
    Recursion, metarecursion, and inclusion.James C. Owings - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):173-179.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2.  16
    Corrigendum to: ``Diagonalization and the recursion theorem''.James C. Owings - 1988 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 30 (1):153-153.
  3.  13
    Max and min limiters.James Owings, William Gasarch & Georgia Martin - 2002 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 41 (5):483-495.
    If and the function is partial recursive, it is easily seen that A is recursive. In this paper, we weaken this hypothesis in various ways (and similarly for ``min'' in place of ``max'') and investigate what effect this has on the complexity of A. We discover a sharp contrast between retraceable and co-retraceable sets, and we characterize sets which are the union of a recursive set and a co-r.e., retraceable set. Most of our proofs are noneffective. Several open questions are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  12
    [Omnibus Review].James C. Owings - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (1):155-156.
  5.  7
    $pi^1_1$ Sets, $omega$-Sets, and Metacompleteness.James C. Owings - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2):194-204.
    An ω-set is a subset of the recursive ordinals whose complement with respect to the recursive ordinals is unbounded and has order type ω. This concept has proved fruitful in the study of sets in relation to metarecursion theory. We prove that the metadegrees of the sets coincide with those of the meta-r.e. ω-sets. We then show that, given any set, a metacomplete set can be found which is weakly metarecursive in it. It then follows that weak relative metarecursiveness is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  7
    Robinson Robert W.. Simplicity of recursively enumerable sets.James C. Owings - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):153-155.
  7.  36
    Diagonalization and the recursion theorem.James C. Owings - 1973 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 14 (1):95-99.
  8. A splitting theorem for simple π11 sets.James C. Owings - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (3):433 - 438.
  9.  32
    A cardinality version of biegel's nonspeedup theorem.James C. Owings - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):761-767.
    If S is a finite set, let |S| be the cardinality of S. We show that if $m \in \omega, A \subseteq \omega, B \subseteq \omega$ , and |{i: 1 ≤ i ≤ 2 m & x i ∈ A}| can be computed by an algorithm which, for all x 1 ,...,x 2 m , makes at most m queries to B, then A is recursive in the halting set K. If m = 1, we show that A is recursive.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  47
    The meta-r.E. Sets, but not the π11 sets, can be enumerated without repetition.James C. Owings - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):223 - 229.
  11.  19
    Π 1 1 Sets, ω-Sets, and metacompleteness.James C. Owings - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2):194-204.
    An ω-set is a subset of the recursive ordinals whose complement with respect to the recursive ordinals is unbounded and has order type ω. This concept has proved fruitful in the study of sets in relation to metarecursion theory. We prove that the metadegrees of the sets coincide with those of the meta-r.e. ω-sets. We then show that, given any set, a metacomplete set can be found which is weakly metarecursive in it. It then follows that weak relative metarecursiveness is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  48
    Weakly semirecursive sets.Carl G. Jockusch & James C. Owings - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):637-644.
    We introduce the notion of "semi-r.e." for subsets of ω, a generalization of "semirecursive" and of "r.e.", and the notion of "weakly semirecursive", a generalization of "semi-r.e.". We show that A is weakly semirecursive iff, for any n numbers x 1 ,...,x n , knowing how many of these numbers belong to A is equivalent to knowing which of these numbers belong to A. It is shown that there exist weakly semirecursive sets that are neither semi-r.e. nor co-semi-r.e. On the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  35
    Marian Boykan Pour-El and Hilary Putnam. Recursively enumerable classes and their application to recursive sequences of formal theories. Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung, vol. 8 no. 3–4 , pp. 104–121. - Marian Boykan Pour-El and William A. Howard. A structural criterion for recursive enumeration without repetition. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 10 , pp. 105–114. - A. H. Lachlan. On recursive enumeration without repetition. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 11 , pp. 209–220. - A. H. Lachlan. On recursive enumeration without repetition: a correction. Zeitschrift für mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, vol. 13 , pp. 99–100. [REVIEW]James C. Owings - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (1):155-156.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  25
    Robert W. Robinson. Simplicity of recursively enumerable sets.The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 32 , pp. 162–172. - Robert W. Robinson. Two theorems on hyperhypersimple sets. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 128 , pp. 531–538. - A. H. Lachlan. On the lattice of recursively enumerable sets.Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 130 , pp. 1–37. - A. H. Lachlan. The elementary theory of recursively enumerable sets. Duke mathematical journal, vol. 35 , pp. 123–146. [REVIEW]James C. Owings - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):153-155.
  15.  28
    The Inequivalence of Two Well-Known Notions of Randomness for Binary Sequences.Thomas Herzog & James C. Owings - 1976 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 22 (1):385-389.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  4
    The Inequivalence of Two Well‐Known Notions of Randomness for Binary Sequences.Thomas Herzog & James C. Owings - 1976 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 22 (1):385-389.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  7
    Philosophical perspectives on technology and psychiatry.James Phillips (ed.) - 2009 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Our lives are dominated by technology. We live with and through the achievements of technology. What is true of the rest of life is of course true of medicine. Many of us owe our existence and our continued vigour to some achievement of medical technology. And what is true in a major way of general medicine is to a significant degree true of psychiatry. Prozac has long since arrived, and in its wake an ever-growing armamentarium of new psychotropics; beyond that, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18. Epicurus and Democritean ethics: an archaeology of ataraxia.James Warren - 2002 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    The Epicurean philosophical system has enjoyed much recent scrutiny, but the question of its philosophical ancestry remains largely neglected. It has often been thought that Epicurus owed only his physical theory of atomism to the fifth-century BC philosopher Democritus, but this study finds that there is much in his ethical thought which can be traced to Democritus. It also finds important influences on Epicurus in Democritus' fourth-century followers such as Anaxarchus and Pyrrho, and in Epicurus' disagreements with his own Democritean (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  19.  7
    Docilitas: on teaching and being taught.James V. Schall - 2016 - South Bend, Indiana: St. Augustine's Press.
    The Latin word "Docilitas" in the title of this book means the willingness and capacity we have of being able to learn something we did not know. It has not the same connotation as "learning," which is what happens to us when we are taught something. Docility also means our recognition that we do not know many things, that we need the help of others, wiser than we are, to learn most of what we know, though we can discover a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  27
    Rethinking the subject: an anthology of contemporary European social thought.James D. Faubion (ed.) - 1995 - Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press.
    Since the early 1970s, European thinkers have departed notably from their predecessors in order to pursue analytical programs more thoroughly their own. Rethinking the Subject brings together in one volume some of the most influential writings of Foucault, Habermas, Bourdieu, Pizzorno, Macfarlane, and other authors whose ideas have had a worldwide influence in recent social history.The anthology is testament to the central importance of three contemporary themes, each familiar to earlier thinkers but never definitively formulated or resolved. The first two (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  9
    Covenons! We Owe Our Store to the Company's Soul.James R. Barker & Charles J. Yoos ii - 2008 - Journal of Human Values 14 (2):141-155.
    We argue that in contemporary business organizations, in which fundamental purpose is construed to be increased value—especially in ‘participative’ organizations, in which non–hierarchal interaction (for example, work teams) is the norm; and in ‘adaptive’ organizations, in which unpredictable change is the rule—a process of values covenanting will be much more valueable than just espoused values or even values covenants. We propose such a process model for organizational values covenanting and argue that such covenanting reflects an anthropomorphism of the human character (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  44
    Amor mundi: explorations in the faith and thought of Hannah Arendt.James William Bernauer (ed.) - 1987 - Hingham, MA: distributors for the U.S. and Canada Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    The title of our collection is owed to Hannah Arendt herself. Writing to Karl Jaspers on August 6, 1955, she spoke of how she had only just begun to really love the world and expressed her desire to testify to that love in the title of what came to be published as The Human Condition: "Out of gratitude, I want to call my book about political theories Arnor Mundi. "t In retrospect, it was fitting that amor mundi, love of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23. Transforming expressivism.James Dreier - 1999 - Noûs 33 (4):558-572.
    In chapter five of Wise Choices, Apt Feelings Allan Gibbard develops what he calls a ‘normative logic’ intended to solve some problems that face an expressivist theory of norms like his. The first is “the problem of embedding: The analysis applies to simple contexts, in which it is simply asserted or denied that such-and-such is rational. It says nothing about more complex normative assertions.”1 That is the problem with which I will be concerned. Though he doesn’t list it as one (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  24.  10
    Bhaṭṭanāyaka and the Vedānta Influence on Sanskrit Literary Theory.James D. Reich - 2022 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 138 (3):533.
    In the history of Sanskrit literary theory Bhaṭṭanāyaka occupies an influential yet mysterious position. Abhinavagupta clearly owes a great debt to him, but since Bhaṭṭanāyaka’s works themselves have been lost, it has proven difficult to understand exactly what that debt is. The common understanding is that Bhaṭṭanāyaka was a Mīmāṃsaka and that he applied the principles of Vedic hermeneutics to literature. But this actually doesn’t fit well with much of what Abhinavagupta tells us about Bhaṭṭanāyaka, and upon closer inspection it (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  21
    What Do We Owe Texts? Respect, Irreverence, or Nothing at All?James R. Kincaid & James Phelan - 1999 - Critical Inquiry 25 (4):758-783.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  34
    Poststructuralism and Transcendental Philosophy: Derrida’s Différance.James Cartlidge - 2022 - Kritikos 1 (Spring).
    This paper examines how Jacques Derrida appropriates and deepens Immanuel Kant’s transcendental philosophy. In Derrida’s early essay on différance, Kant is conspicuous in his absence. One of the essay’s key aims is to re-think space and time, drawing on the work of Heidegger, Hegel, Nietzsche, and several others to do so. It is therefore curious that Kant is never mentioned, especially because the method and conceptual framework Derrida ends up adopting owes a huge debt to transcendental arguments. Derrida posits a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. T.H. Green’s Theory of Positive Freedom: From Metaphysics to Political Theory.James W. Allard - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (4):538-539.
    Although T. H. Green is primarily remembered today as a moral and political philosopher, many of his philosophical concerns owe their origins to the Victorian crisis of faith in which a widespread belief in the literal truth of Scripture confronted seemingly incompatible scientific theories. Green attributed this crisis to the inability of science and religion to find accommodation in the popular version of empiricism widely accepted by educated men and women of his day. In his 371-page introduction to Hume’s Treatise, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  58
    The principle of agency.James Rachels - 1998 - Bioethics 12 (2):150–161.
    The Principle of Agency says that if it would be good for a state of affairs to occur “naturally”, then it is permissible to take action to bring it about. This contradicts the views of some bioethicists, who object to euthanasia, in vitro fertilization, and cloning, even though they acknowledge that the states of affairs produced are good. But the principle, or some form of it, seems inescapable. The opposite view — that we may not, by our action, reproduce “natural” (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  39
    The Grace We Are Owed.James B. Gould - 2008 - Faith and Philosophy 25 (3):261-275.
    Traditional views of grace assert that God owes us nothing. Grace is undeserved, supererogatory and free. In this paper I argue that while this is an accurate characterization of creating grace, it is not true of saving grace. We have no right to be created as spiritual beings whose true good is found in relationship with God. But once we exist as spiritual beings, God does owe us a genuine offer of the salvation that constitutes our highest fulfillment. Creating grace (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  34
    The Limits of Creditors' Rights: The Case of Third World Debt: JAMES W. CHILD.James W. Child - 1992 - Social Philosophy and Policy 9 (1):114-140.
    At present, Third World countries owe over one trillion dollars to the developed Western nations; much of the debt is held by the leading international commercial banks. The debt of six Latin American countries alone — Argentina, Brazil, Chile, Mexico, Peru, and Venezuela — is over $330 billion, of which $240 billion is owed to commercial banks. Let us immediately narrow our focus to loans made by the major international commercial banks to Third World governments. We shall not be concerned (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  45
    Extending the extended consciousness debate: perception, imagination, and the common kind assumption.James Deery - 2023 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 22 (4):955-973.
    For some, the states and processes involved in the realisation of phenomenal consciousness are not confined to within the organismic boundaries of the experiencing subject. Instead, the sub-personal basis of perceptual experience can, and does, extend beyond the brain and body to implicate environmental elements through one’s interaction with the world. These claims are met by proponents of predictive processing, who propose that perception and imagination should be understood as a product of the same internal mechanisms. On this view, as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  76
    Darwin’s Methodological Evolution.James G. Lennox - 2005 - Journal of the History of Biology 38 (1):85-99.
    A necessary condition for having a revolution named after you is that you are an innovator in your field. I argue that if Charles Darwin meets this condition, it is as a philosopher and methodologist. In 1991, I made the case for Darwin's innovative use of "thought experiment" in the "Origin." Here I place this innovative practice in the context of Darwin's methodological commitments, trace its origins back into Darwin's notebooks, and pursue Darwin's suggestion that it owes its inspiration to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  33.  23
    History in the Service of Metaphysics.James Collins - 1949 - Review of Metaphysics 2 (8):105 - 125.
    Undoubtedly, American Thomists owe a major share of their confident historical outlook to the writings of Professor Gilson whose latest work is formally concerned with the relative merits of Thomism and other important systems. This is not a new preoccupation with him, since a whole series of earlier books testify to his abiding interest in this problem. But he has now made a fresh exploration of the entire territory in the light of his revised view of the mind of St. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  12
    History In the Service of Metaphysics.James Collins - 1949 - Review of Metaphysics 2 (8):105-125.
    Undoubtedly, American Thomists owe a major share of their confident historical outlook to the writings of Professor Gilson whose latest work is formally concerned with the relative merits of Thomism and other important systems. This is not a new preoccupation with him, since a whole series of earlier books testify to his abiding interest in this problem. But he has now made a fresh exploration of the entire territory in the light of his revised view of the mind of St. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  9
    Never Solo: Gratitude for My Academic Journey.James F. Childress - 2020 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 45 (4-5):410-416.
    Tom Beauchamp and I were asked by the editors of The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy to prepare “intellectual autobiographies,” with particular attention to sources and influences on our work, including but not limited to Principles of Biomedical Ethics. Of course, it is artificial and even impossible to try fully to separate the “intellectual” from other aspects of our lives. So, while emphasizing the “intellectual” aspects of my autobiography, I have attended to other aspects, too. The huge debts of gratitude (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  65
    Autonomy, duress, and coercion.James Stacey Taylor - 2003 - Social Philosophy and Policy 20 (2):127-155.
    For the past three decades philosophical discussions of both personal autonomy and what it is for a person to “identify” with her desires have been dominated by the “hierarchical” analyses of these concepts developed by Gerald Dworkin and Harry Frankfurt. The longevity of these analyses is owed, in part, to the intuitive appeal of their shared claim that the concepts of autonomy and identification are to be analyzed in terms of hierarchies of desires, such that it is a necessary condition (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  37.  26
    Freedom from poverty as a human right: Who owes what to the very poor? - Edited by Thomas Pogge.James P. Sterba - 2008 - Ethics and International Affairs 22 (2):227–229.
  38. Epistemic Injustice in Healthcare: A Philosophical Analysis.Ian James Kidd & Havi Carel - 2014 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 17 (4):529-540.
    In this paper we argue that ill persons are particularly vulnerable to epistemic injustice in the sense articulated by Fricker. Ill persons are vulnerable to testimonial injustice through the presumptive attribution of characteristics like cognitive unreliability and emotional instability that downgrade the credibility of their testimonies. Ill persons are also vulnerable to hermeneutical injustice because many aspects of the experience of illness are difficult to understand and communicate and this often owes to gaps in collective hermeneutical resources. We then argue (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   153 citations  
  39.  8
    Virtue politics: soulcraft and statecraft in Renaissance Italy.James Hankins - 2019 - Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
    Convulsed by a civilizational crisis, the great thinkers of the Renaissance set out to reconceive the nature of society. Everywhere they saw problems. Corrupt and reckless tyrants sowing discord and ruling through fear; elites who prized wealth and status over the common good; military leaders waging endless wars. Their solution was at once simple and radical. "Men, not walls, make a city," as Thucydides so memorably said. They would rebuild their city, and their civilization, by transforming the moral character of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  63
    Evolution and sudden infant death syndrome (SIDS).James J. McKenna - 1990 - Human Nature 1 (2):145-177.
    This paper and its subsequent parts (Part II and Part III) build on an earlier publication (McKenna 1986). They suggest that important clinical data on the relationship between infantile constitutional deficits and microenvironmental factors relevant to SIDS can be acquired by examining the physiological regulatory effects (well documented among nonhuman primates) that parents assert on their infants when they sleep together.I attempt to show why access to parental sensory cues (movement, touch, smell, sound) that induce arousals in infants while they (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  41.  98
    Oriental enlightenment: the encounter between Asian and Western thought.John James Clarke - 1997 - New York: Routledge.
    The West has long had an ambivalent attitude toward the philosophical traditions of the East. Voltaire claimed that the East is the civilization "to which the West owes everything", yet C.S. Peirce was contemptuous of the "monstrous mysticism of the East". And despite the current trend toward globalizations, there is still a reluctance to take seriously the intellectual inheritance of South and East Asia. Oriental Enlightenment challenges this Eurocentric prejudice. J. J. Clarke examines the role played by the ideas of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  42. Robinson Jeffers, 'The Double Axe'.James Lesher - manuscript
    Robinson Jeffers’ dark view of humankind is thought to owe much to Friedrich Nietzsche while his admiration for the beauty of nature has been compared to sentiments expressed by Lucretius in de rerum natura. In many respects, however, the philosopher who stands closest to Jeffers in both thought and personality is the ancient Greek thinker Heraclitus of Ephesus. Jeffers’ extended poem ‘The Double Axe’ makes no fewer than five clear references to Heraclitean ideas: (1) ‘Heraclitus’ Sibyl whose voice reached over (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  33
    Understanding the Worldly and Human Significance of At Through Arendt and Gadamer.James Couch - 2008 - Southwest Philosophy Review 24 (1):133-140.
    This essay explores Hannah Arendt’s thought concerning mass society’s tendency to constrict the appearances of the world. The role that art plays for her is brought into further relief in conjunction with the larger theme of the value of disclosure. Because Arendt’s thought concerning appearance runs on a parallel course to the philosophical hermeneutics of Hans-Georg Gadamer, further insight into the experience of art is discovered. The significance of Gadamer’s hermeneutic understanding, as it is exemplified in the experience of art, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Hegel on Mind, Action and Social Life: The Theory of Geist as a Theory of Explanation.James Kreines - 2001 - Dissertation, The University of Chicago
    This dissertation develops an interpretation of Hegel's answer to the question of who or what we ourselves are, or his theory of Geist . The theory of Geist is perhaps most familiar when read as an appeal to a romantic metaphysical or theological view on which we are all part of "cosmic spirit", a self-creating collective agent identical to reality itself. I argue that the theory of Geist cannot be understood apart from Hegel's core concerns, but that these are not (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  58
    The Philosophical Significance of Hope.James Dodd - 2004 - Review of Metaphysics 58 (1):117-146.
    ANYONE WHO DECIDES TO VENTURE FORTH AN ARGUMENT for the philosophical importance of hope owes a debt to Ernst Bloch. His seminal The Principle of Hope is a remarkable attempt to situate the theme of hope at the very center of the philosophical enterprise. Yet, The Principle of Hope is cited here only in order to mark the distance that separates the inquiry presented below from the strategy and, to some extent, the purpose of Bloch’s work. A basic conviction of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  24
    The emergence and development of psychopathy.James Horley - 2014 - History of the Human Sciences 27 (5):91-110.
    Currently, psychopathy and related terms such as antisocial personality disorder are popular yet problematic constructs within forensic psychology and other disciplines. Psychopathy is traced typically to the works of Pinel and Prichard in the early 19th century, and it has even been linked to biblical passages, although there appears to be little or no support for the latter claim. The first use of the term psychopathy in German psychiatry of the mid-19th century referred only to psychological disturbance in general, or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  67
    Reid’s Conception of Common Sense.James Somerville - 1987 - The Monist 70 (4):418-429.
    When Reid wrote An Inquiry Into The Human Mind, On The Principles Of Common Sense the term ‘common sense’ had long been in use in something like its ordinary sense today. Prompted no doubt by Priestley’s criticism that he had “made an innovation in the received use” of the term he devoted a chapter of his Essays On The Intellectual Powers Of Man to the use of the term: “All that is intended in this chapter is to explain the meaning (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  24
    Persuading Philosophy to Government and People.James F. Perry - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 52:61-67.
    Philosophy studies the relation between random, routine, and reflective thought and action. It is in essence the reflective study of routine. No one can survive a random world, but a routine world will generate the same randomness it is intended to avoid owing to the inevitable errors associated with routines. The prime function of reflective inquiry is to identify and explain the logical foundation of these errors. While governments depend on strict routine to prevent anarchy, it is only with the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  27
    To Shape a Global Human Consciousness, De‐Mystify Philosophy First.James F. Perry - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 52:49-59.
    Philosophy studies the relation between random, routine, and reflective thought and action. It is in essence the reflective study of routine. No one can survive a random world, but a routine world will generate the same randomness it is intended to avoid owing to the inevitable errors associated with routines. The prime function of reflective inquiry is to identify and explain the logical foundation of these errors. While governments depend on strict routine to prevent anarchy, it is only with the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  90
    A New Instrumental Theory of Rights.James Sherman - 2010 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (2):215-228.
    My goal in this paper is to advance a long-standing debate about the nature of moral rights. The debate focuses on the questions: In virtue of what do persons possess moral rights? What could explain the fact that they possess moral rights? The predominant sides in this debate are the status theory and the instrumental theory. I aim to develop and defend a new instrumental theory. I take as my point of departure the influential view of Joseph Raz, which for (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 983