Results for 'reductive psychological hedonism'

995 found
Order:
  1. Butler’s Stone and Ultimate Psychological Hedonism.Peter Nilsson - 2013 - Philosophia 41 (2):545-553.
    This paper discusses psychological hedonism with a special reference to the writings of Bishop Butler, and Elliot Sober and David Sloan Wilson. Contrary to philosophical orthodoxy, Sober and Wilson have claimed that Butler failed to refute psychological hedonism. In this paper it is argued: (1) that there is a difference between reductive and ultimate psychological hedonism; (2) that Butler failed to refute ultimate psychological hedonism, but that he succeeded in refuting (...) psychological hedonism; and, finally and more importantly, (3) that Butler’s criticism of reductive hedonism can be used as a stepping-stone in another argument showing the implausibility of ultimate psychological hedonism as well. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  37
    Non-Drive-Reductive Hedonism and the Physiological Psychology of Inspiration.Bill Faw - 2008 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 15 (2):114-128.
    Major strands of the history of scientific psychology proposed less mechanistic explanations of behavior than the “series of billiard ball reactions” that Ellis ascribes to them. I tease apart psychological systems based on hedonism and those based on stimulus-response mechanisms-and then tease apart basic hedonism and drive-reduction hedonism, to layout psychological and neuroscientific foundations for the active, dynamic, cognitive, emotive, and "spiritual" dynamics of human nature which Ellis calls us to affirm. I trace these distinctions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  17
    Future and Present Hedonistic Time Perspectives and the Propensity to Take Investment Risks: The Interplay Between Induced and Chronic Time Perspectives.Katarzyna Sekścińska, Joanna Rudzinska-Wojciechowska & Dominika Agnieszka Maison - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9:362092.
    Willingness to take risk is one of the most important aspects of personal financial decisions, especially those regarding investments. Recent studies show that one’s perception of time, specifically the individual level of Present Hedonistic and Future Time Perspectives (TPs), influence risky financial choices. This was demonstrated for both, Time Perspective treated as an individual trait and for experimentally induced Time Perspectives. However, on occasion, people might find themselves under the joint influence of both, chronic and situational Time Perspectives and little (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  83
    Psychological hedonism and the nature of motivation: Bertrand Russell's anhedonic desires.Geir Overskeid - 2002 - Philosophical Psychology 15 (1):77 – 93.
    Understanding the causes of behavior is one of philosophy's oldest challenges. In analyzing human desires, Bertrand Russell's position was clearly related to that of psychological hedonism. Still, though he seems to have held quite consistently that desires and emotions govern human behavior, he claimed that they do not necessarily do so by making us want to maximize pleasure. This claim is related to several being made in today's psychology and philosophy. I point out a string of facts and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Psychological hedonism, evolutionary biology, and the experience machine.John Lemos - 2004 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34 (4):506-526.
    In the second half of their recent, critically acclaimed book Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior , Elliott Sober and David Sloan Wilson discuss psychological hedonism. This is the view that avoiding our own pain and increasing our own pleasure are the only ultimate motives people have. They argue that none of the traditional philosophical arguments against this view are good, and they go on to present theirownevolutionary biological argument against it. Interestingly, the first half (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6. Two types of psychological hedonism.Justin Garson - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 56:7-14.
    I develop a distinction between two types of psychological hedonism. Inferential hedonism (or “I-hedonism”) holds that each person only has ultimate desires regarding his or her own hedonic states (pleasure and pain). Reinforcement hedonism (or “R–hedonism”) holds that each person's ultimate desires, whatever their contents are, are differentially reinforced in that person’s cognitive system only by virtue of their association with hedonic states. I’ll argue that accepting R-hedonism and rejecting I-hedonism provides a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  7.  43
    Peirce's Critique of Psychological Hedonism.Richard Kenneth Atkins - 2015 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (2):349-367.
    Psychological hedonism is the theory that all of our actions are ultimately motivated by a desire for our own pleasure or an aversion to our own pain. Peirce offers a unique critique of PH based on a descriptive analysis of self-controlled action. This essay examines Peirce's critique and his accounts of self-controlled action and of desire.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Butler's Stone.John J. Tilley - 2018 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (4): 891–909.
    Early in the eleventh of his Fifteen Sermons, Joseph Butler advances his best-known argument against psychological hedonism. Elliott Sober calls that argument Butler’s stone, and famously objects to it. I consider whether Butler’s stone has philosophical value. In doing so I examine, and reject, two possible ways of overcoming Sober’s objection, each of which has proponents. In examining the first way I discuss Lord Kames’s version of the stone argument, which has hitherto escaped scholarly attention. Finally, I show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  62
    Kant's Psychological Hedonism.A. Phillips Griffiths - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (256):207 - 216.
    As far as consideration of man as phenomenon, as appearance, as an empirical self, is concerned, Kant appears to be a thoroughgoing psychological hedonist.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10.  93
    Psychological Hedonism.Wladyslaw Tatarkiewicz - 1949 - Synthese 8 (1):409-425.
  11.  27
    Psychological hedonism.Ralph Piddington - 1931 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 9 (4):274 – 283.
  12.  16
    Psychological hedonism.Ralph Piddington - 1931 - Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy 9 (4):274-283.
  13. Schlick, Altruism and Psychological Hedonism.F. Ablondi - 1996 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 23 (3-4):417-428.
  14. Butler’s Argument Against Psychological Hedonism.Robert M. Stewart - 1992 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (2):211-221.
    It is widely thought among philosophers that Joseph Butler's criticism of psychological egoism in his Sermons is, in the words of A.E. Duncan-Jones, 'the classic refutation of it.' Indeed, no less a philosopher than David Hume restated and put forth Butler's central argument against hedonistic egoism - without due credit - as part of his own critique. Yet recent commentators have begun to question Butler's arguments, albeit usually with sympathy and in the hope of saving what they take to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  15
    Neurophysiological reduction, psychological explanation and neuropsychology.Laurence F. Mucciolo - 1975 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 5 (3):451-462.
  16.  46
    A Dialectical Dissolution of Psychological Hedonism.Laurence J. Lafleur - 1954 - Review of Metaphysics 7 (3):368 - 378.
    What does a Utilitarian mean by happiness when he says that it is the good? Specifically, pleasure. But how many different kinds of experiences are included under this term? It appears that as the word was used by Bentham, and indeed by almost all other hedonists, it had so wide an extension that it included all experiences not properly termed "unhappiness." Partly, however, because of the identification of happiness with pleasure and the absence of pain, and partly because of a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  73
    Goals of action and emotional reasons for action. A modern version of the theory of ultimate psychological hedonism.Ulrich Mees & Annette Schmitt - 2008 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 38 (2):157–178.
    In this paper we present a modern version of the classic theory of “ultimate psychological hedonism” . As does the UPH, our two-dimensional model of metatelic orientations also postulates a fundamentally hedonistic motivation for any human action. However, it makes a distinction between “telic” or content-based goals of actions and “metatelic” or emotional reasons for actions. In our view, only the emotional reasons for action, but not the goals of action, conform to the UPH. After outlining our model, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  18
    An examination of psychological hedonism.W. A. Merrylees - 1932 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 10 (2):92 – 108.
  19.  17
    An examination of Psychological Hedonism.W. A. Merrylees - 1932 - Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy 10 (2):92-108.
  20. Troubles for Psychological Hedonism.John J. Tilley - 1999 - Skepsis: A Journal for Philosophy and Interdisciplinary Research 10.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  28
    Can evolutionary theory provide evidence against psychological hedonism?G. Harman - 2000 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 7 (1-2):1-2.
    Sober and Wilson argue that neither psychological evidence nor philosophical arguments provide grounds for rejecting psychological hedonism, but evolution by natural selection is unlikely to have led to such a single source of motivation. In order to turn their piecemeal discussion of into a serious argument, Sober and Wilson need a general procedure for mapping alternative accounts of motivation into egoistic hedonistic accounts. That is the only way to demonstrate that there will always be an available hedonistic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22.  63
    Bishop Butler's Refutation of Psychological Hedonism.Reginald Jackson - 1943 - Philosophy 18 (70):114 - 139.
    To the question ‘Why do you try to realize this?’ your answer may be ‘Because I desire that and I think that the realization of this would involve the realization of that.’ Or your answer may be ‘Because I desire this.’ If ‘Why?’ is interpreted as ‘Desiring what?’ the question ‘Why do you desire this?’ is improper. The word ‘desire’ is, however, frequently used in such a way as to countenance the impropriety. It is so used not only when what (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23.  53
    Toward a re-examination of psychological hedonism.W. K. McAllister - 1952 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 13 (4):499-505.
  24. Normative theory and psychological research: Hedonism, eudaimonism and why it matters.Valerie Tiberius & Alicia Hall - 2010 - Journal of Positive Psychology 5 (3):212-225..
    This paper is a contribution to the debate about eudaimonism started by Kashdan, Biswas-Diener, King, and Waterman in a previous issue of The Journal of Positive Psychology. We point out that one thing that is missing from this debate is an understanding of the problems with subjective theories of well-being that motivate a turn to objective theories. A better understanding of the rationale for objective theories helps us to see what is needed from a theory of well-being. We then argue (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25. Reduction: Models of cross-scientific relations and their implications for the psychology-neuroscience interface.Robert McCauley - manuscript
    University Abstract Philosophers have sought to improve upon the logical empiricists’ model of scientific reduction. While opportunities for integration between the cognitive and the neural sciences have increased, most philosophers, appealing to the multiple realizability of mental states and the irreducibility of consciousness, object to psychoneural reduction. New Wave reductionists offer a continuum of comparative goodness of intertheoretic mapping for assessing reductions. Their insistence on a unified view of intertheoretic relations obscures epistemically significant crossscientific relations and engenders dismissive conclusions about (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  26.  17
    Psychology and hedonism.W. B. Mahan - 1929 - International Journal of Ethics 39 (4):408-423.
  27.  7
    Psychology and Hedonism.W. B. Mahan - 1929 - International Journal of Ethics 39 (4):408-423.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Epicurus: psychological or ethical hedonist?Larry J. Waggle - 2007 - Revista de Filosofía (Venezuela) 57 (3):73-88.
    Este artículo sostiene que el tipo de hedonismo que se encuentra en la ética de Epicuro no es de tipo psicológico sino ético. Asimismo, este ensayo se opone a la utilización de reportes doxográficos como una base para desarrollar una interpretación de la filosofía de Epicuro si existen materiales de referencia primaria disponibles, y afirma que la doxografía debe ser utilizada para clarificar esos materiales de referencia primarios, y no al revés.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Realization, Reduction And Psychological Autonomy.Schweizer Paul - 2001 - Synthese 126 (3):383-405.
    It is often thought that the computational paradigm provides a supporting case for the theoretical autonomy of the science of mind. However, I argue that computation is in fact incompatible with this alleged aspect of intentional explanation, and hence the foundational assumptions of orthodox cognitive science are mutually unstable. The most plausible way to relieve these foundational tensions is to relinquish the idea that the psychological level enjoys some special form of theoretical sovereignty. So, in contrast to well known (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  13
    From Psychology to Neuroscience: A New Reductive Account.Patrice Soom - 2011 - De Gruyter.
    This book explores the mind-body issue from both the perspectives of philosophy of mind and philosophy of science. Starting from the problem of mental causation, it provides an overview of the contemporary metaphysical discussion and argues in favour of the token-identity thesis, as the only position that can account for the causal efficacy of the mental. Showing furthermore that this ontological reductionism is not dissociable from epistemological reductionism, the author applies a new strategy of inter-theoretic reduction, which is compatible with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  60
    Reduction and autonomy in psychology and neuroscience: A call for pragmatism.Paul B. Sharp & Gregory A. Miller - 2019 - Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 39 (1):18-31.
    Psychologists and neuroscientists often struggle to integrate findings in their respective domains, a problem due partly to implicitly and explicitly held philosophical positions on issues of reduction and autonomy across these domains. The present article reviews how reduction and autonomy have been used in philosophical arguments regarding how macro-scale findings relate to micro-scale findings across various scientific disciplines. The present article demonstrates how macro findings are indispensable to explanations of phenomena of interest by (a) providing information regarding higher levels of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  37
    A reductive physicalist account of the autonomy of psychology.Orly R. Shenker - unknown
    The appearance of multiple realization of the special sciences kinds by physical kinds can be fully explained within a type-identity reductive physicalist framework, based on recent findings in the foundations of statistical mechanics. This has been shown in Hemmo and Shenker. However, while this account is available for special sciences like biology and thermodynamics, it is unavailable for psychology. Therefore the only coherent physicalist account of psychology is a type-type identity account. The so-called “non reductive” physicalism turns out (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Hedonism.John J. Tilley - 2012 - In Ruth Chadwick (ed.), Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics, 2nd ed., vol. 2. Academic Press. pp. 566-73.
    This article covers four types of hedonism: ancient hedonism; ethical hedonism; axiological hedonism; and psychological hedonism. It concentrates on the latter two types, both by clarifying them and by discussing arguments in their behalf. It closes with a few words about the relevance of those positions to applied ethics.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. A Dance Between the Reduction and Reflexivity: Explicating the "Phenomenological Psychological Attitude".Linda Finlay - 2008 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 39 (1):1-32.
    This article explores the nature of "the phenomenological attitude," which is understood as the process of retaining a wonder and openness to the world while reflexively restraining pre-understandings, as it applies to psychological research. A brief history identifies key philosphical ideas outlining Husserl's formulation of the reductions and subsequent existential-hermeneutic elaborations, and how these have been applied in empirical psychological research. Then three concrete descriptions of engaging the phenomenological attitude are offered, highlighting the way the epoché of the (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  35. Phenomenologico-Psychological and Transcendental Reductions in Husserl's 'Crisis'.Joseph J. Kockelmans - 1972 - Analecta Husserliana 2:78.
  36.  13
    Logical reduction and social psychology.J. K. Chadwick-Jones - 1973 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 3 (1):3–21.
  37.  38
    Genetics, reduction and functional psychology.Patricia Kitcher - 1982 - Philosophy of Science 49 (4):633-636.
  38.  40
    Psychological type-type reduction via disjunction.Cynthia Macdonald - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (1):65-69.
  39.  4
    Psychological Type‐Type Reduction Via Disjunction.Cynthia Macdonald - 1992 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (1):65-69.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  9
    Neurophysiological reduction and psychological explanation.Michael Martin - 1971 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 1 (1):161-170.
  41.  22
    Reduction of Psychology to Neurophysiology?Herbert Feigl - 1969 - Kagaku Tetsugaku 2:163-184.
  42.  17
    Scientific reduction and the possibility of parapsychology: Parallels from cognitive psychology.Timothy L. Hubbard - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):384-385.
  43.  2
    On the Reduction of Semantics to Psychology.Anita Avramides - 1985
  44.  20
    Neurophilosophy meets psychology: Reduction, autonomy, and empirical constraints.Gary Hatfield - 1988 - Cognitive Neuropsychology 5:723-46.
    A commentary on Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain, by Patricia Smith Churchland. Cambridge, Mass.: The M.I.T. Press/Bradford, 1986, pp. xi + 546, $27.50, ISBN 0-262-03116-7.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45. James Sully's Psychological Reduction of Philosophical Pessimism.Patrick Hassan - forthcoming - British Journal for the History of Philosophy:1-24.
    One of the greatest philosophical disputes in Germany in the latter half of the 19th century concerned the value of life. Following Arthur Schopenhauer, numerous philosophers sought to defend the provocative view that life is not worth living. A persistent objection to pessimism is that it is not really a philosophical theory at all, but rather a psychological state; a mood or disposition which is the product of socio-economic circumstance. A developed and influential version of this view was advanced (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Hedonism as the Explanation of Value.David Brax - 2009 - Dissertation, Lund University
    This thesis defends a hedonistic theory of value consisting of two main components. Part 1 offers a theory of pleasure. Pleasures are experiences distinguished by a distinct phenomenological quality. This quality is attitudinal in nature: it is the feeling of liking. The pleasure experience is also an object of this attitude: when feeling pleasure, we like what we feel, and part of how it feels is how this liking feels: Pleasures are Internally Liked Experiences. Pleasure plays a central role in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47. Quantification, Conceptual Reduction and Theoretical Under-determination in Psychological Science.Stan Klein - 2021 - Psychology of Consciousness: Theory, Research, and Practice 8 (1):95-103.
    I argue that academic psychology’s quest to achieve scientific respectability by reliance on quantification and objectification is deeply flawed. Specifically, psychological theory typically cannot support prognostication beyond the binary opposition of “effect present/effect absent”. Accordingly, the “numbers” assigned to experimental results amount to little more than affixing names (e.g., more than, less than) to the members of an ordered sequence of outcomes. This, in conjunction with the conceptual under-specification characterizing the targets of experimental inquiry, is, I contend, a primary (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Psychoneural Reduction: The New Wave.John W. Bickle - 1998 - Bradford.
    One of the central problems in the philosophy of psychology is an updated version of the old mind-body problem: how levels of theories in the behavioral and brain sciences relate to one another. Many contemporary philosophers of mind believe that cognitive-psychological theories are not reducible to neurological theories. However, this antireductionism has not spawned a revival of dualism. Instead, most nonreductive physicalists prefer the idea of a one-way dependence of the mental on the physical.In Psychoneural Reduction, John Bickle presents (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  49. Disjunctive predicates and the reduction of psychology.John W. Godbey Jr - 1978 - Mind 87 (347):433-435.
  50.  57
    Intentionality and modern philosophical psychology I: The modern reduction of intentionality.William E. Lyons - 1990 - Philosophical Psychology 3 (2 & 3):247-69.
    In rounded terms and modem dress a theory of intentionality is a theory about how humans take in information via the senses and in the very process of taking it in understand it and, most often, make subsequent use of it in guiding human behaviour. The problem of intentionality in this century has been the problem of providing an adequate explanation of how a purely physical causal system, the brain, can both receive information and at the same time understand it, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 995