Results for 'Voluntary act requirement'

984 found
Order:
  1.  81
    The Voluntary Act Requirement.Gideon Yaffe - 2012 - In Marmor Andrei (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Law. Routledge. pp. 174.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  2.  58
    Action, the Act Requirement and Criminal Liability.Antony Duff - 2004 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55:69-103.
    The slogan that criminal liability requires an ‘act’, or a ‘voluntary act’, is still something of a commonplace in textbooks of criminal law. There are, it is usually added, certain exceptions to this requirement— cases in which liability is in fact, and perhaps even properly, imposed in the absence of such an act: but the ‘act requirement’ is taken to represent a normally minimal necessary condition of criminal liability. Even offences of strict liability, for which no mens (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  98
    Intoxication and the Act/Control/Agency Requirement.Susan Dimock - 2012 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 6 (3):341-362.
    Doug Husak has argued, persuasively I think, that there is no literal ‘act requirement’ in Anglo-American law. I begin by reviewing Husak’s reasons for rejecting the act requirement, and provide additional reasons to think he is right to do so. But Husak’s alternative, the ‘control condition’, I argue, is inadequate. The control requirement is falsified by the widespread practice of holding extremely intoxicated offenders liable for criminal conduct they engage in even if they lack control over their (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  32
    Conditions required for a law on active voluntary euthanasia: a survey of nurses' opinions in the Australian Capital Territory.B. Kitchener & A. F. Jorm - 1999 - Journal of Medical Ethics 25 (1):25-30.
    OBJECTIVES: To ascertain which conditions nurses believe should be in a law allowing active voluntary euthanasia (AVE). DESIGN: Survey questionnaire posted to registered nurses (RNs). SETTING: Australian Capital Territory (ACT) at the end of 1996, when active voluntary euthanasia was legal in the Northern Territory. SURVEY SAMPLE: A random sample of 2,000 RNs, representing 54 per cent of the RN population in the ACT. MAIN MEASURES: Two methods were used to look at nurses' opinions. The first involved four (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  5. Act and Crime: The Philosophy of Action and its Implications for Criminal Law.Michael S. Moore - 1993 - Oxford University Press.
    This work provides, for the first time, a unified account of the theory of action presupposed by both British and American criminal law and its underlying morality. It defends the view that human actions are volitionally caused body movements. This theory illuminates three major problems in drafting and implementing criminal law--what the voluntary act requirement does and should require, what complex descriptions of actions prohibited by criminal codes both do and should require, and when the two actions are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  6.  10
    Act and Crime: The Philosophy of Action and its Implications for Criminal Law.Michael S. Moore - 2010 - Oxford University Press UK.
    In print for the first time in over ten years, Act and Crime provides a unified account of the theory of action presupposed by both Anglo-American criminal law and the morality that underlies it. The book defends the view that human actions are always volitionally caused bodily movements and nothing else. The theory is used to illuminate three major problems in the drafting and the interpretation of criminal codes: 1) what the voluntary act requirement both does and should (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  7.  53
    Sculpting Character: Aristotle's Voluntary as Affectability.Audrey L. Anton - 2016 - Labyrinth: An International Journal for Philosophy, Value Theory and Sociocultural Hermeneutics 18 (2):75-103.
    I argue that the two criteria traditionally identified as jointly sufficient for voluntary behavior according to Aristotle require qualification. Without such qualification, they admit troubling exceptions. Through minding these difficult examples, I conclude that a third condition mentioned by Aristotle – the eph' hēmin – is key to qualifying the original two criteria. What is eph' hēmin is that which is efficiently caused by appetite and teleologically caused by reason such that the agent could have, in theory, acted differently. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Acts, Attitudes, and Rational Control.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    I argue that when determining whether an agent ought to perform an act, we should not hold fixed the fact that she’s going to form certain attitudes (and, here, I’m concerned with only reasons-responsive attitudes such as beliefs, desires, and intentions). For, as I argue, agents have, in the relevant sense, just as much control over which attitudes they form as which acts they perform. This is important because what effect an act will have on the world depends not only (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9. Acts, Attitudes, and Rational Choice.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    In this paper, I argue that we have obligations not only to perform certain actions, but also to have certain attitudes (such as desires, beliefs, and intentions), and this despite the fact that we rarely, if ever, have direct voluntary control over our attitudes. Moreover, I argue that whatever obligations we have with respect to actions derive from our obligations with respect to attitudes. More specifically, I argue that an agent is obligated to perform an action if and only (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  35
    Buddhist Virtue, Voluntary Poverty, and Extensive Benevolence.Donald K. Swearer - 1998 - Journal of Religious Ethics 26 (1):71-103.
    Complementing recent studies by Keown, Whitehill, and Hallisey that associate Buddhist ethics with the virtue tradition, the author proposes that Buddhist virtue requires both overcoming attachment to self and compassionate regard for others. Within a broader framework of comparative religious ethics, such a claim is not extraordinary; overcoming prudentialist self-interest, cultivating sympathy, and acting on others' behalf are ethical values highly praised by most religious traditions, including Buddhism. Nevertheless, this proposal runs counter to those who hold Theravāda Buddhism to be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  31
    In Defense of Criminal Possession.Gideon Yaffe - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (3):441-471.
    Criminal law casebooks and treatises frequently mention the possibility that criminal liability for possession is inconsistent with the Voluntary Act Requirement, which limits criminal liability to that which includes an act or an omission. This paper explains why criminal liability for possession is compatible with the Voluntary Act Requirement despite the fact that possession is a status. To make good on this claim, the paper defends the Voluntary Act Requirement, offers an account of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  86
    “Minding Our Business”: What the United States Government has done and can do to Ensure that U.S. Multinationals Act Responsibly in Foreign Markets. [REVIEW]Susan Ariel Aaronson - 2005 - Journal of Business Ethics 59 (1-2):175 - 198.
    The United States Government does not mandate that US based firms follow US social and environmental law in foreign markets. However, because many developing countries do not have strong human rights, labor, and environmental laws, many multinationals have adopted voluntary corporate responsibility initiatives to self-regulate their overseas social and environmental practices. This article argues that voluntary actions, while important, are insufficient to address the magnitude of problems companies confront as they operate in developing countries where governance is often (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  13.  21
    Exploring and Expanding Supererogatory Acts: Beyond Duty for a Sustainable Future.Gareth R. T. White, Anthony Samuel & Robert J. Thomas - 2023 - Journal of Business Ethics 185 (3):665-688.
    Supererogation has gained attention as a means of explaining the voluntary behaviours of individuals and organizations that are done for the benefit of others and which go above what is required of legislation and what may be expected by society. Whilst the emerging literature has made some significant headway in exploring supererogation as an ethical lens for the study of business there remain several important issues that require attention. These comprise, the lack of primary evidence upon which such examinations (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. The Enemy of the Good: Supererogation and Requiring Perfection.Claire Benn - 2018 - Utilitas 30 (3):333-354.
    Moral theories that demand that we do what is morally best leave no room for the supererogatory. One argument against such theories is that they fail to realize the value of autonomy: supererogatory acts allow for the exercise of autonomy because their omissions are not accompanied by any threats of sanctions, unlike obligatory ones. While this argument fails, I use the distinction it draws – between omissions of obligatory and supererogatory acts in terms of appropriate sanctions – to draw a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Understanding the Voluntary Act principle.Andrew Botterell - 2012 - In François Tanguay-Renaud & James Stribopoulos (eds.), Rethinking Criminal Law Theory: New Canadian Perspectives in the Philosophy of Domestic, Transnational, and International Criminal Law. Hart Publishing.
    In broad outline, the chapter proceeds as follows. As indicated above, the Voluntary Act Principle has two components. The first part, the act component, claims that criminal liability can be imposed on an accused only for the performance of an act. The second part, the voluntariness component, claims that criminal liability can be imposed on an accused only for the voluntary performance of an act. I will argue that both components of the Voluntary Act Principle are in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  14
    Voluntary acts: The child/Davidson Trilemma.Larry Alexander - 1992 - Criminal Justice Ethics 11 (2):98-99.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  97
    Reconsidering the Relationship among Voluntary Acts, Strict Liability, and Negligence in Criminal Law.Larry Alexander - 1990 - Social Philosophy and Policy 7 (2):84.
    This essay, as will become obvious, owes a huge debt to Mark Kelman, particularly to his article “Interpretative Construction in the Substantive Criminal Law.” That debt is one of both concept and content. There is rich irony in my aping Kelman's deconstructionist enterprise, for I do not share his enthusiasm for either the “insights” or the political agenda of the Critical Legal Studies movement. I do not believe that either the law in general or the criminal law in particular is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  18
    Approaches to Implementing the Olmstead ADA (Americans with Disabilities Act) Ruling.Shelley R. Jackson, Gayle Hafner, Daniel O’Brien & Georges Benjamin - 2003 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 31 (S4):47-48.
    The Department of Health and Human Services, Office for Civil Rights enforces Section 504 of the 1973 Rehabilitation Act and Title II of the Americans with Disabilities Act. OCR works through complaint investigations and compliance reviews, as well as outreach, technical assistance, and public education to promote voluntary compliance. In the Olmstead decision of June 1999, the Supreme Court held that the ADA’s “integration regulation” requires state and local government to administer services, programs, and activities in the most integrated (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  67
    Aquinas on Non-voluntary Acts.Jeffrey Hause - 2006 - International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (4):459-475.
    Aquinas argues that an agent’s act may be voluntary, involuntary, or even nonvoluntary. An agent performs a non-voluntary act on these conditions: (a) the agent does not know the act falls under a certain description D, (b) the act under D is not contrary to the agent’s will, and (c) if the agent had known that the act fell under D, the agent would still have performed it. Aquinas’s full account of non-voluntary acts is terse and ambiguous (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  5
    Action and Criminal Responsibility.R. A. Duff - 2010 - In Timothy O'Connor & Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action. Oxford, UK: Wiley‐Blackwell. pp. 331–337.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Actions and the Criminal Law Objects or Conditions of Criminal Responsibility? Actions and (Voluntary) Acts Abandoning the Act Requirement? An Action Presumption? References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  48
    Time-frames, voluntary acts, and strict liability.Douglas Husak & Brian P. McLaughlin - 1993 - Law and Philosophy 12 (1):95 - 120.
  22. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness-potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act.Benjamin Libet, Curtis A. Gleason, Elwood W. Wright & Dennis K. Pearl - 1983 - Brain 106 (3):623--664.
  23.  28
    Canadian Scholars on Criminal Responsibility.Stephen P. Garvey - 2015 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 9 (2):351-364.
    This short review examines the work of four Canadian scholars addressing a variety of questions about criminal responsibility. The essays under review are a small part of a recent collection of essays entitled “Rethinking Criminal Law Theory: New Canadian Perspectives in the Philosophy of Domestic, Transnational, and International Criminal Law.”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Consciousness, Intentionality, and Causality.Walter J. Freeman - 1999 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 6 (11-12):11-12.
    According to behavioural theories deriving from pragmatism, gestalt psychology, existentialism, and ecopsychology, knowledge about the world is gained by intentional action followed by learning. In terms of the neurodynamics described here, if the intending of an act comes to awareness through reafference, it is perceived as a cause. If the consequences of an act come to awareness through proprioception and exteroception, they are perceived as an effect. A sequence of such states of awareness comprises consciousness, which can grow in complexity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  25.  96
    Readiness Potentials Preceding Unrestricted Spontaneous Pre-Planned Voluntary Acts.B. Libet, E. Wright & C. Gleason - 1982 - Electroencephalography and Clinical Neurophysiology 54:322-325.
  26.  37
    Are the mental experiences of will and self-control significant for the performance of a voluntary act?Benjamin Libet - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):783.
  27. An alleged act requirement in the criminal law.Douglas Husak - 2011 - In John Deigh & David Dolinko (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of the Criminal Law. Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  11
    Fundamentals of criminal law: responsibility, culpability, and wrongdoing.Andrew Simester - 2021 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Written by a noted expert in criminal law, this book explores the philosophical underpinnings of the law's major doctrines concerning actus reus, mens rea, and defences, showing that they are not always driven by culpability. They are grounded also in principles of moral responsibility, ascriptive responsibility, and wrongdoing. As such, they engage wider debates about wrongdoing, and about the boundaries between liability and freedom. This multi-textured analysis allows this book to take more nuanced positions about many important controversies in criminal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  80
    Beyond voluntary consent: Hans Jonas on the moral requirements of human experimentation.C. Fethe - 1993 - Journal of Medical Ethics 19 (2):99-103.
    In his essay, Philosophical Reflections on Experimenting with Human Subjects, Hans Jonas contends that except in cases of widespread medical emergencies, people do not have a moral or social obligation to volunteer to be subjects in medical experiments. He further argues that any appeal for volunteer subjects in medical experiments should whenever possible give priority to those who can identify with the project and offer a strong sense of commitment to its goals. The first of these claims is given support (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30. Exorcising Grice’s ghost: an empirical approach to studying intentional communication in animals.Simon W. Townsend, Sonja E. Koski, Richard W. Byrne, Katie E. Slocombe, Balthasar Bickel, Markus Boeckle, Ines Braga Goncalves, Judith M. Burkart, Tom Flower, Florence Gaunet, Hans Johann Https://Orcidorg909X Glock, Thibaud Gruber, David A. W. A. M. Jansen, Katja Liebal, Angelika Linke, Ádám Miklósi, Richard Moore, Carel P. van Schaik, Sabine Stoll, Alex Vail, Bridget M. Waller, Markus Wild, Klaus Zuberbühler & Marta B. Manser - 2016 - Biological Reviews 3.
    Language’s intentional nature has been highlighted as a crucial feature distinguishing it from other communication systems. Specifically, language is often thought to depend on highly structured intentional action and mutual mindreading by a communicator and recipient. Whilst similar abilities in animals can shed light on the evolution of intentionality, they remain challenging to detect unambiguously. We revisit animal intentional communication and suggest that progress in identifying analogous capacities has been complicated by (i) the assumption that intentional (that is, voluntary) (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  8
    The Theory of Tawlīd in Kal'm in terms of the Limits of Freedom and Responsibility.Mücteba Altindas - 2020 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 24 (3):1113-1134.
    The problem of human freedom have been addressed by al-Mutakallimūn (Islamic theologians) in the context of human acts and discussed from the point of view its relation with the will and other elements. At this point, whether the human has will and power in his own act, the limits of his will and power, the role of human in the act and his responsibilities have prompted to different debates. The theory of tawlīd put forward by Mu‘tazila is very crucial in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  41
    Are We Moving Beyond Voluntary CSR? Exploring Theoretical and Managerial Implications of Mandatory CSR Resulting from the New Indian Companies Act.Lucia Gatti, Babitha Vishwanath, Peter Seele & Bertil Cottier - 2018 - Journal of Business Ethics 160 (4):961-972.
    Although the literature on corporate social responsibility has discussed the scope and meaning of CSR extensively, confusion still exists regarding how to define the concept. One controversial issue deals with the changing legal status of CSR. Based on a review of CSR definitions and meta-studies on CSR definitions, we find that the majority of definitions leans toward voluntary CSR. However, some recent regulatory amendments toward mandatory CSR have called into question the established idea of CSR as merely a managerial (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  33.  20
    Enduring Values for Contemporary Issues: Integrating Buddhist and Jewish Morality Into Contemporary Management Models.Lois Hecht Oppenheim - 2017 - Philosophy of Management 16 (1):55-68.
    In today’s multi-cultural world and global economy, attention is often focused on the diversity of cultural values and practices and the need for management approaches to take these differing cultural environments into account. While there is much to be valued in this approach, the focus is often on how to navigate through distinct cultural practices in order to achieve a singular business aim, which falls within the current neoliberal paradigm of global trade. In addition, by focusing on differences in cultural (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. Voluntary Groups, Noncompliance, and Conflicts of Reason: Tuomela on Acting as a Group-Member.David Schweikard - 2016 - In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Social Ontology and Collective Intentionality: Critical Essays on the Philosophy of Raimo Tuomela with his Responses. Cham: Springer.
  35.  42
    Action and agency in the criminal law: Vincent chiao.Vincent Chiao - 2009 - Legal Theory 15 (1):1-23.
    This paper offers a critical reconsideration of the traditional doctrine that responsibility for a crime requires a voluntary act. I defend three general propositions: first, that orthodox Anglo-American criminal theory fails to explain adequately why criminal responsibility requires an act. Second, when it comes to the just definition of crimes, the act requirement is at best a rough generalization rather than a substantive limiting principle. Third, that the intuition underlying the so-called “act requirement” is better explained by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  91
    Commentary on free will in the light of neuropsychiatry.Benjamin Libet - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (2):95-96.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Free Will in the Light of Neuropsychiatry”Benjamin Libet (bio)Is Free Will Incompatible with Neuroscience?Sean Spence sets forth some interesting approaches to the issue of free will. His concepts are provocative and his marshalling of related quotations is informative.However, I shall argue with some of his crucial assumptions, in a way that affects the validity of some of Spence’s major conclusions. The latter are that “conscious experience is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  41
    Duty Without Obligation.S. A. Lloyd - 2017 - Hobbes Studies 30 (2):202-221.
    _ Source: _Volume 30, Issue 2, pp 202 - 221 There is ongoing scholarly debate over the role that Hobbes’s laws of nature play in grounding the moral requirement that subjects obey the government under which they live. This essay demonstrates how the laws of nature, when understood as natural duties, may directly ground a moral duty to obey one’s sovereign without positing that subjects have undertaken any covenant of subjection. Such a grounding avoids the problems that attend accounts (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  15
    Voluntariness and the Orthodox Actus Reus Requirement.Stephen Mathis - 1998 - Southwest Philosophy Review 14 (1):55-61.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  17
    L. Polo: la libertà come essere personale e la sua manifestazione nella volontà.Juan José Sanguineti - 2018 - Acta Philosophica 27 (1):45-62.
    Freedom in L. Polo’s transcendental anthropology is seen as equivalent to the human person, conceived as a peculiar act of existence different from the act of being attributed to the material universe. More precisely, freedom constitutes, together with co-existence, intellect and self-donating love, the four personal transcendentals of the being-person. The structure of self-donating love is the dynamics of giving and accepting. At the level of essence as a manifestation of the person, freedom appears as the self which is capable (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  16
    Response to the Commentaries.Sean Spence - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (2):99-100.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Response to the CommentariesSean A. SpenceIn “Free Will in the Light of Neuropsychiatry,” I have attempted to present an argument from the perspective of materialist neuroscience, pushing the latter to its logical conclusion: that if the human nervous system is consistent in its properties, then the only place for “free will” is in the non-conscious processes which underpin conscious awareness. This argument I have based on two supports: the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  40
    The requirements of the Data Protection Act 1998 for the processing of medical data.P. Boyd - 2003 - Journal of Medical Ethics 29 (1):34-35.
    The Data Protection Act 1998 presents a number of significant challenges to data controllers in the health sector. To assist data controllers in understanding their obligations under the act, the Information Commissioner has published guidance, The Use and Disclosure of Health Data, which is reproduced here. The guidance deals, among other things, with the steps that must be taken to obtain patient data fairly, the implied requirements of the act to use anonymised or psuedonymised data where possible, an exemption applicable (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  55
    Acting more generously than the law requires: The issue of employee layoffs in halakhah.Harry J. Van Buren - 1999 - Journal of Business Ethics 19 (4):335-343.
    In this paper, the issue of plant closings is analyzed from the perspective of halakhah (the Written Law of Judaism). Two levels of analysis in halakhah must be differentiated: the legal (enforced by courts) and the moral (not enforced by law, but rather framed in terms of duty to God). There is no legal mandate to keep an unprofitable plant open, but there are a number of moral imprecations (particularly "acting more generously than the law requires") that might influence an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  14
    Acting More Generously than the Law Requires: The Issue of Employee Layoffs in halakhah.Harry J. van Buren Iii - 1999 - Journal of Business Ethics 19 (4):335-343.
    In this paper, the issue of plant closings is analyzed from the perspective of halakhah (the Written Law of Judaism). Two levels of analysis in halakhah must be differentiated: the legal (enforced by courts) and the moral (not enforced by law, but rather framed in terms of duty to God). There is no legal mandate to keep an unprofitable plant open, but there are a number of moral imprecations (particularly "acting more generously than the law requires") that might influence an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44. Believing and Acting: Voluntary Control and the Pragmatic Theory of Belief.Brian Hedden - 2015 - Logos and Episteme 6 (4):495-513.
    I argue that a attractive theory about the metaphysics of belief—the prag- matic, interpretationist theory endorsed by Stalnaker, Lewis, and Dennett, among others—implies that agents have a novel form of voluntary control over their beliefs. According to the pragmatic picture, what it is to have a given belief is in part for that belief to be part of an optimal rationalization of your actions. Since you have voluntary control over your actions, and what actions you perform in part (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. Reclaiming volition: An alternative interpretation of Libet's experiment.Jing Zhu - 2003 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 10 (11):61-77.
    Based on his experimental studies, Libet claims that voluntary actions are initiated by unconscious brain activities well before intentions or decisions to act are consciously experienced by people. This account conflicts with our common-sense conception of human agency, in which people consciously and intentionally exert volitions or acts of will to initiate voluntary actions. This paper offers an alternative interpretation of Libet's experiment. The cause of the intentional acts performed by the subjects in Libet's experiment should not be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  46.  18
    Requirement and rationality: two problems concerning supererogatory acts.Elizabeth Drummond Young - 2005 - Dissertation, University of Edinburgh
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  14
    Require an Act?Douglas Husak - 1998 - In Antony Duff (ed.), Philosophy and the Criminal Law: Principle and Critique. Cambridge University Press. pp. 60.
  48.  20
    Acting irrationally versus acting contrary to what is required by reason.Bernard Gert - 1999 - Journal of Social Philosophy 30 (3):379–386.
  49. Can Right Acts Be Voluntary?James K. Mish'alani - 1959 - Analysis 20 (3):67 - 72.
  50. Voluntary Rehabilitation? On Neurotechnological Behavioural Treatment, Valid Consent and (In)appropriate Offers.Lene Bomann-Larsen - 2011 - Neuroethics 6 (1):65-77.
    Criminal offenders may be offered to participate in voluntary rehabilitation programs aiming at correcting undesirable behaviour, as a condition of early release. Behavioural treatment may include direct intervention into the central nervous system (CNS). This article discusses under which circumstances voluntary rehabilitation by CNS intervention is justified. It is argued that although the context of voluntary rehabilitation is a coercive circumstance, consent may still be effective, in the sense that it can meet formal criteria for informed consent. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
1 — 50 / 984