Results for 'Refusal to treat '

982 found
Order:
  1.  51
    Refusing to Treat Sexual Dysfunction in Sex Offenders.Thomas Douglas - 2017 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (1):143-158.
    This article examines one kind of conscientious refusal: the refusal of healthcare professionals to treat sexual dysfunction in individuals with a history of sexual offending. According to what I call the orthodoxy, such refusal is invariably impermissible, whereas at least one other kind of conscientious refusalrefusal to offer abortion services—is not. I seek to put pressure on the orthodoxy by (1) motivating the view that either both kinds of conscientious refusal are permissible or (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  45
    Conscience Clauses, the Refusal to Treat, and Civil Disobedience—Practicing Medicine as a Christian in a Hostile Secular Moral Space.Mark J. Cherry - 2012 - Christian Bioethics 18 (1):1-14.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  3.  26
    The Morality of Refusing to Treat HIV‐positive Patients.Mitchell Silver - 2008 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 6 (2):149-158.
    ABSTRACT Do physicians and nurses have an obligation to treat patients who are HIV‐positive? Although an initial review of the possible sources of such an obligation yields equivocal results, a closer examination reveals a clear obligation to treat. The current risk of job‐caused HIV‐infection is not sufficient to warrant a refusal to treat. This is so because there exist rationally justified, general social, as well as specific peer expectations, that health care professionals treat HIV‐positive patients. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  54
    Duty to Treat or Right to Refuse?Norman Daniels - 1991 - Hastings Center Report 21 (2):36-46.
    By entering the medical profession, physicians have consented to accept a standard level of risk of infection. In most instances, the risk of contracting HIV does not exceed this level.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  5.  32
    Pubertal Suppression and Professional Obligations: May a Pediatric Endocrinologist Refuse to Treat an Adolescent With Gender Dysphoria?Armand H. Matheny Antommaria - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (1):43-46.
    Of the different features of this case, I focus on the pediatric endocrinologist's refusal to treat the patient. Providers generally have wide latitude in accepting or refusing patients. Appropriat...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  8
    Pubertal Suppression and Professional Obligations: May a Pediatric Endocrinologist Refuse to Treat an Adolescent With Gender Dysphoria?Armand Matheny Antommaria - 2014 - American Journal of Bioethics 14 (1):43-46.
    Of the different features of this case, I focus on the pediatric endocrinologist's refusal to treat the patient. Providers generally have wide latitude in accepting or refusing patients. Appropriat...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7.  23
    May a dentist refuse to treat an HIV-positive patient?Jos V. M. Welie - 1998 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 1 (2):163-169.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  14
    Ethical position of medical practitioners who refuse to treat unvaccinated children.Melanie Forster - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (8):552-555.
    Recent reports in Australia have suggested that some medical practitioners are refusing to treat children who have not been vaccinated, a practice that has been observed in the USA and parts of Europe for some years. This behaviour, if it is indeed occurring in Australia, has not been supported by the Australian Medical Association, although there is broad support for medical practitioners in general having the right to conscientious objection. This paper examines the ethical underpinnings of conscientious objection and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  14
    Health Professions, Codes, and the Right to Refuse to Treat HIV‐Infectious Patients.Benjamin Freedman - 1988 - Hastings Center Report 18 (2):20-25.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  49
    Do Health Care Providers Have a Right to Refuse to Treat Some Patients?E. C. Brugger - 2012 - Christian Bioethics 18 (1):15-29.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  77
    To treat or not to treat: the legal, ethical and therapeutic implications of treatment refusal.A. N. Wear & D. Brahams - 1991 - Journal of Medical Ethics 17 (3):131-135.
    Health professionals faced with refusal of life-saving treatment may wish to override a person's wishes, especially if that person suffers from a mental disorder. Mental illness does not automatically mean a patient is incapable of making decisions of this nature. It is not always clear whether an individual is legally competent to decide whether to undergo treatment or not. This article discusses a clinical example and analyses some of the moral implications.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  8
    COVID-19: What should employers do if employed health professionals such as doctors and nurses refuse to treat COVID-19 patients despite being provided with the required personal protective equipment? [REVIEW]D. J. McQuoid-Mason - 2020 - South African Journal of Bioethics and Law 13 (2):87.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  24
    Announced refusal to answer: a study of norms and accountability in broadcast political interviews.Mats Ekström - 2009 - Discourse Studies 11 (6):681-702.
    This article investigates the announced refusal to answer as a form of dispreferred and challenging response in broadcast political interviews. The aim is to study how the rightness and wrongness of conduct is dealt with in situations of announced refusal. More specifically, the paper focuses on: announced refusal as a particular type of conduct; the orientation to norms and accountability in situations of announced refusal; how the legitimacy of politics and journalism is negotiated in broadcast interviews. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  14.  12
    The ethics of refusing to care for patients during the coronavirus pandemic: A Chinese perspective.Junhong Zhu, Teresa Stone & Marcia Petrini - 2021 - Nursing Inquiry 28 (1):e12380.
    As a result of the coronavirus (COVID‐19) pandemic, health professionals are faced with situations they have not previously encountered and are being forced to make difficult ethical decisions. As the first group to experience challenges of caring for patients with coronavirus, Chinese nurses endure heartbreak and face stressful moral dilemmas. In this opinion piece, we examine three related critical questions: Whether society has the right to require health professionals to risk their lives caring for patients; whether health professionals have the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  10
    Prisoner's right to refuse treatment outweighs physician's duty to treat.G. P. Drescher - 1992 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 21 (3-4):400-401.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  47
    Balancing the duty to treat with the duty to family in the context of the COVID-19 pandemic.Doug McConnell - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (6):360-363.
    Healthcare systems around the world are struggling to maintain a sufficient workforce to provide adequate care during the COVID-19 pandemic. Staffing problems have been exacerbated by healthcare workers refusing to work out of concern for their families. I sketch a deontological framework for assessing when it is morally permissible for HCWs to abstain from work to protect their families from infection and when it is a dereliction of duty to patients. I argue that it is morally permissible for HCWs to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  17.  48
    What healthcare professionals owe us: why their duty to treat during a pandemic is contingent on personal protective equipment (PPE).Udo Schuklenk - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (7):432-435.
    Healthcare professionals’ capacity to protect themselves, while caring for infected patients during an infectious disease pandemic, depends on their ability to practise universal precautions. In turn, universal precautions rely on the availability of personal protective equipment (PPE). During the SARS-CoV2 outbreak many healthcare workers across the globe have been reluctant to provide patient care because crucial PPE components are in short supply. The lack of such equipment during the pandemic was not a result of careful resource allocation decisions in the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  18.  21
    HIV Infection, Risk Taking, and the Duty to Treat.D. Smolkin - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (1):55-74.
    The paper advances a consequence-based argument in support of the American Medical Association's policy that a physician may not ethically refuse to treat a person with HIV solely because the patient is seropositive. A limited number of alternative arguments, both in support of and in opposition to this policy are also considered, but are found wanting. The paper then concludes with a discussion of some of the other obstacles to quality health care that persons with HIV must often confront.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  11
    “Fake it till You Make it”! Contaminating Rubber Hands (“Multisensory Stimulation Therapy”) to Treat Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder.Baland Jalal, Richard J. McNally, Jason A. Elias, Sriramya Potluri & Vilayanur S. Ramachandran - 2020 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13:476545.
    Obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD) is a deeply enigmatic psychiatric condition associated with immense suffering worldwide. Efficacious therapies for OCD, like exposure and response prevention (ERP) are sometimes poorly tolerated by patients. As many as 25 percent of patients refuse to initiate ERP mainly because they are too anxious to follow exposure procedures. Accordingly, we proposed a simple and tolerable (immersive yet indirect) low-cost technique for treating OCD that we call “multisensory stimulation therapy.” This method involves contaminating a rubber hand during the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  41
    Doctors as fiduciaries: do medical professionals have the right not to treat?Edwin C. Hui - 2005 - Poiesis and Praxis 3 (4):256-276.
    In the first part of the paper, the author discusses the origin and obligation of the medical profession and argues that the duty of fidelity in the context of a patient–professional relationship (PPR) is the central obligation of medical professionals. The duty of fidelity entails seeking the patient’s best interests even at the expense of the professional’s own, and refusing to treat a risk-patient infected by SARS is a breach of fidelity because the medical professional is involved in a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  7
    The duty of care and the right to be cared for: is there a duty to treat the unvaccinated?Zohar Lederman & Shalom Corcos - 2024 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 27 (1):81-91.
    Vaccine hesitancy or refusal has been one of the major obstacles to herd immunity against Covid-19 in high-income countries and one of the causes for the emergence of variants. The refusal of people who are eligible for vaccination to receive vaccination creates an ethical dilemma between the duty of healthcare professionals (HCPs) to care for patients and their right to be taken care of. This paper argues for an extended social contract between patients and society wherein vaccination against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  4
    Needs to address clinicians’ moral distress in treating unvaccinated COVID-19 patients.Robert Klitzman - 2022 - BMC Medical Ethics 23 (1):1-9.
    BackgroundMoral dilemmas have arisen concerning whether physicians and other providers should treat patients who have declined COVID vaccination and are now sick with this disease. Several ethicists have argued that clinicians have obligations to treat such patients, yet providing care to these patients has distressed clinicians, who have at times declined to do so. Critical questions thus emerge regarding how best to proceed.Main bodyProviders face moral tensions: whether to place the benefits to an unvaccinated patient over their duties (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  13
    Responding to the Refusal of Care in the Emergency Department.Jennifer Nelson, Arvind Venkat & Moira Davenport - 2014 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 4 (1):75-80.
    The emergency department (ED) serves as the primary gateway for acute care and the source of health care of last resort. Emergency physicians are commonly expected to rapidly assess and treat patients with a variety of life–threatening conditions. However, patients do refuse recommended therapy, even when the consequences are significant morbidity and even mortality. This raises the ethical dilemma of how emergency physicians and ED staff can rapidly determine whether patient refusal of treatment recommendations is based on intact (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Are patients' decisions to refuse treatment binding on health care professionals?Peter Murphy - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (3):189–201.
    ABSTRACT When patients refuse to receive medical treatment, the consequences of honouring their decisions can be tragic. This is no less true of patients who autonomously decide to refuse treatment. I distinguish three possible implications of these autonomous decisions. According to the Permissibility Claim, such a decision implies that it is permissible for the patient who has made the autonomous decision to forego medical treatment. According to the Anti‐Paternalism Claim, it follows that health‐care professionals are not morally permitted to (...) that patient. According to the Binding Claim it follows that these decisions are binding on health‐care professionals. My focus is the last claim. After arguing that it is importantly different from each of the first two claims, I give two arguments to show that it is false. One argument against the Binding Claim draws a comparison with cases in which patients autonomously choose perilous positive treatments. The other argument appeals to considered judgments about cases in which disincentives are used to deter patients from refusing sound treatments. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  11
    Effects of induced and naturalistic mood on the temporal allocation of attention to emotional information.Frank J. Farach, Teresa A. Treat & Justin A. Jungé - 2014 - Cognition and Emotion 28 (6):993-1011.
  26.  33
    Physicians Should Treat Mentally Ill Death Row Inmates, Even If Treatment Is Refused.Melissa McDonnell & Robert T. M. Phillips - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):774-788.
    Competency to be executed evaluations are conducted with a clear understanding that no physician-patient relationship exists. Treatment however, is not so neatly re-categorized in large measure because it involves the physician's active provision of the healing arts. A natural tension exists between what practices may be legally permissible and what are ethically acceptable. We present an overview of the existing positions on this matter in the process of framing our argument.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  11
    Physicians Should Treat Mentally Ill Death Row Inmates, Even if Treatment is Refused.Melissa McDonnell & Robert T. M. Phillips - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (4):774-788.
    The history of physician involvement in capital proceedings is longstanding and ripe with controversy and conflicts of ethical concerns. Previously one of us has written that the controversy is more appropriately characterized as a conflict of moral position rather than one of ethical dilemma.In hindsight, we believe that analysis, while true, does not capture the depth or complexity of the issue.Forensic psychiatric evaluations, including competency to be executed evaluations, are done with a clear understanding that no physician-patient relationship exists. Treatment, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  36
    Personality disorder and competence to refuse treatment.E. Winburn & R. Mullen - 2008 - Journal of Medical Ethics 34 (10):715-716.
    The traditional view that having a personality disorder, unlike other mental disorders, is not usually reason enough to consider a person incompetent to make healthcare decisions is challenged. The example of a case in which a woman was treated for a physical disorder without her consent illustrates that personality disorder can render a person incompetent to refuse essential treatment, particularly because it can affect the doctor–patient relationship within which consent is given.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  29.  11
    Visual attention to emotion in depression: Facilitation and withdrawal processes.Blair E. Wisco, Teresa A. Treat & Andrew Hollingworth - 2012 - Cognition and Emotion 26 (4):602-614.
  30. Conscientious Refusal of Abortion in Emergency Life-Threatening Circumstances and Contested Judgments of Conscience.Wojciech Ciszewski & Tomasz Żuradzki - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (7):62-64.
    Lawrence Nelson (2018) criticizes conscientious objection (CO) to abortion statutes as far as they permit health care providers to escape criminal liability for what would otherwise be the legally wrongful taking of a pregnant woman’s life by refusing treatment (i.e. abortion). His key argument refers to the U.S. Supreme Court judgment (Roe v. Wade 1973) that does not treat the unborn as constitutional persons under the Fourteenth Amendment. Therefore, Nelson claims that within the U.S. legal system any vital interests (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  8
    Sedation accompanying treatment refusals, or refusals of eating and drinking, with a wish to die: an ethical statement.Bettina Schöne-Seifert, Dieter Birnbacher, Annette Dufner & Oliver Rauprich - 2024 - Ethik in der Medizin 36 (1):31-53.
    Background This paper addresses sedation at the end of life. The use of sedation is often seen as a last resort for patients whose death is imminent and whose symptoms cannot be treated in any other way. This paper asks how to assess constellations, where patients want to hasten their death by refusing (further) life-sustaining treatment, or by voluntarily stopping eating and drinking (VSED), and wish this to be accompanied by sedation. Argument We argue that sedation is ethically and legally (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  44
    Ethics of refusing parental requests to withhold or withdraw treatment from their premature baby.R. J. Boyle - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (4):402-405.
    In the United Kingdom women have access to termination of pregnancy for maternal reasons until 24 weeks’ completed gestation, but it is accepted practice for children born at or beyond 25 weeks’ gestation to be treated according to the child’s perceived best interests even if this is not in accordance with parental wishes. The authors present a case drawn from clinical practice which highlights the discomfort that parents may feel about such an abrupt change in their rights over their child, (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  18
    Advance refusals: does the law help?Gwen M. Sayers, Moses S. Kapembwa & Mary C. Green - 2006 - Clinical Ethics 1 (3):139-145.
    Advance refusals of life-sustaining treatment involve three potentially conflicting interests: those of the patient; those of the doctor; and those of the law. The state's interest in protecting life can clash with the patient's right to self determination which, in turn, can conflict with the doctor's desire to act in the patient's best interests. Against this background, we present the case of a patient who was treated (arguably) contrary to his advance refusal but in accordance with English law.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  29
    Treating competent patients by force: the limits and lessons of Israel's Patient's Rights Act.M. L. Gross - 2005 - Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (1):29-34.
    Competent patients who refuse life saving medical treatment present a dilemma for healthcare professionals. On one hand, respect for autonomy and liberty demand that physicians respect a patient’s decision to refuse treatment. However, it is often apparent that such patients are not fully competent. They may not adequately comprehend the benefits of medical care, be overly anxious about pain, or discount the value of their future state of health. Although most bioethicists are convinced that partial autonomy or marginal competence of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Overriding Adolescent Refusals of Treatment.Anthony Skelton, Lisa Forsberg & Isra Black - 2021 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 20 (3):221-247.
    Adolescents are routinely treated differently to adults, even when they possess similar capacities. In this article, we explore the justification for one case of differential treatment of adolescents. We attempt to make philosophical sense of the concurrent consents doctrine in law: adolescents found to have decision-making capacity have the power to consent to—and thereby, all else being equal, permit—their own medical treatment, but they lack the power always to refuse treatment and so render it impermissible. Other parties, that is, individuals (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  13
    Assessing Public Reason Approaches to Conscientious Objection in Healthcare.Doug McConnell - forthcoming - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics:1-11.
    Sometimes healthcare professionals conscientiously refuse to treat patients despite the patient requesting legal, medically indicated treatments within the professionals’ remit. Recently, there has been a proliferation of views using the concept of public reason to specify which conscientious refusals of treatment should be accommodated. Four such views are critically assessed, namely, those of Robert Card, Massimo Reichlin, David Scott, and Doug McConnell. This paper argues that McConnell’s view has advantages over the other approaches because it combines the requirement that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  20
    Refusing Technology, Accepting Death: My Father’s Story.Milly Ryan-Harshman - 2016 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 59 (2):198-205.
    In December 2004, at the age of 91, my father was told that his congestive heart failure had worsened and that his kidneys were functioning poorly. At best, the prognosis was that he had perhaps another year; at 86, my father had had a succession of three heart attacks before having surgery to place a stent in his coronary artery. The cardiologist who treated him then said he would get five or six good years from the stent, for which my (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  17
    Punishing Health Care Providers for Treating Terrorists.Leonard S. Rubenstein - 2015 - Hastings Center Report 45 (4):13-16.
    Imagine that an American physician volunteered to treat wounded children through the Ministry of Health in Gaza, controlled by Hamas. Or that a Palestinian nurse attending to injured fighters in Gaza spoke out against the firing of rockets into Israel, was threatened with arrest, and sought asylum in the United States. Under U.S. law, the doctor could be subject to prosecution, and the nurse could be denied asylum—in the first case, because she provided medical care under the direction or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  70
    False belief and the refusal of medical treatment.R. Faden & A. Faden - 1977 - Journal of Medical Ethics 3 (3):133-136.
    May a doctor treat a patient, despite that patient's refusal, when in his professional opinion treatment is necessary? This is the dilemma which must from time to time confront most physicians. An examination of the validity of such a refusal is provided by the present authors who use the case history of a patient refusing treatment, for cancer as well as for a fractured hip, to evaluate the grounds for intervention in such circumstances. In such a situation (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  17
    Why careproviders may conclude that treating a patient is futile.Edmund G. Howe - 2013 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 24 (2):83-90.
    I shall examine one way that careproviders may come to judgments of “futility” in cases that are less than clear-cut, in the hope that, if such judgment is unwarranted, it may be avoided.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  16
    The Ethics of Refusing Lifesaving Treatment Following a Failed Suicide Attempt.Wayne Shelton, Jacob Mago & Megan K. Applewhite - 2023 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 34 (3):273-277.
    Injuries from failed suicide attempts account for a large number of patients cared for in the emergency and trauma setting. While a fundamental underpinning of clinical ethics is that patients have a right to refuse treatment, individuals presenting with life-threating injuries resulting from suicide attempts are almost universally treated in this acute care setting. Here we discuss the limitations on physician ability to determine capacity in this setting and the challenges these pose in carrying out patient wishes.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  10
    QUOTATION3 By Israel Scheffler FOLLOWING Goodman4 in treating inscriptions framed by quotes as concrete general rather than abstract. [REVIEW]an Inscriptional Approach To Indirect - 1997 - In Catherine Z. Elgin (ed.), Nelson Goodman's Theory of Symbols and its Applications. Garland. pp. 237.
  43.  8
    At the Intersection of Faith, Culture, and Family Dynamics: A Complex Case of Refusal of Treatment for Childhood Cancer.Amy E. Caruso Brown - 2017 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 28 (3):228-235.
    Refusing treatment for potentially curable childhood cancers engenders much discussion and debate. I present a case in which the competent parents of a young Amish child with acute myeloid leukemia deferred authority for decision making to the child’s maternal grandfather, who was vocal in his opposition to treatment. I analyze three related concerns that distinguish this case from other accounts of refused treatment.First, I place deference to grandparents as decision makers in the context of surrogate decision making more generally.Second, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  9
    Time to treat the climate and nature crisis as one indivisible global health emergency.Kamran Abbasi, Parveen Ali, Virginia Barbour, Thomas Benfield, Kirsten Bibbins-Domingo, Stephen Stephen, Richard Horton, Laurie Laybourn-Langton, Robert Mash, Peush Sahni, Wadeia Mohammad Sharief, Paul Yonga & Chris Zielinski - 2024 - Nursing Inquiry 31 (1):e12612.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  3
    Time to Treat the Climate and Nature Crisis as One Indivisible Global Health Emergency.Kamran Abbasi, Parveen Ali, Virginia Barbour, Thomas Benfield, Kirsten Bibbins-Domingo, Gregory E. Erhabor, Stephen Hancocks, Richard Horton, Laurie Laybourn-Langton, Robert Mash, Peush Sahni, Wadeia Mohammad Sharief, Paul Yonga & Chris Zielinski - forthcoming - The New Bioethics:1-6.
    Over 200 health journals call on the United Nations, political leaders, and health professionals to recognize that climate change and biodiversity loss are one indivisible crisis and must be tackle...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Anorexia Nervosa and Respecting a refusal of life‐prolonging Therapy: A Limited Justification.Heather Draper - 2000 - Bioethics 14 (2):120–133.
    People who suffer from eating disorders often have to be treated against their will, perhaps by being detained, perhaps by being forced to eat. In this paper it is argued that whilst forcing compliance is generally acceptable, there may be circumstances under which a sufferer's refusal of consent to treatment should be respected. This argument will hinge upon whether someone in the grip of an eating disorder can actually make competent decisions about their quality of life. If so, then (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  47.  73
    Autonomy, Wellbeing, and the Case of the Refusing Patient.Jukka Varelius - 2005 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 9 (1):117-125.
    A moral problem arises when a patient refuses a treatment that would save her life. Should the patient be treated against her will? According to an influential approach to questions of biomedical ethics, certain considerations pertaining to individual autonomy provide a solution to this problem. According to this approach, we should respect the patient’s autonomy and, since she has made an autonomous decision against accepting the treatment, she should not be treated. This article argues against the view that our answer (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  7
    Time to Treat the Climate and Nature Crisis as One Indivisible Global Health Emergency†.Kamran Abbasi, Parveen Ali, Virginia Barbour, Thomas Benfield, Kirsten Bibbins-Domingo, Stephen Hancocks, Richard Horton, Laurie Laybourn-Langton, Robert Mash, Peush Sahni, Wadeia Mohammad Sharief, Paul Yonga & Chris Zielinski - forthcoming - Public Health Ethics:phad022.
    Over 200 health journals call on the United Nations, political leaders, and health professionals to recognise that climate change and biodiversity loss are one.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  13
    Time to Treat the Climate and Nature Crisis as One Indivisible Global Health Emergency.Kamran Abbasi, Parveen Ali, Virginia Barbour, Thomas Benfield, Kirsten Bibbins-Domingo, Gregory E. Erhabor, Stephen Hancocks, Richard Horton, Laurie Laybourn-Langton, Robert Mash, Peush Sahni, Wadeia Mohammad Sharief, Paul Yonga & Chris Zielinski - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics 23 (12):1-4.
    Over 200 health journals call on the United Nations, political leaders, and health professionals to recognise that climate change and biodiversity loss are one indivisible crisis and must be tackle...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Whose Self-Determination? Barriers to Access to Emergency Hormonal Contraception in Italy.Emanuela Ceva & Sofia Moratti - 2013 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23 (2):139-167.
    It is a standard requirement of democratic theory that all members of society be treated with equal respect as capable of self-determination (Christiano 2004; Dworkin 1977; Gutmann and Thompson 2004; Patten 2011; Waldron 1999). The fulfillment of this requirement is problematic vis-à-vis conscientious dissenters. Conscientious dissenters refuse to comply with legally enforced duties when compliance risks jeopardizing their moral integrity, because the required behavior would compromise their loyalty to (some of) their moral commitments. Coercing conscientious dissenters into behavior they deem (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 982