Results for 'Leibniz’s law'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  15
    Leibniz: publications on natural philosophy.Richard Arthur, Jeffery K. McDonough, R. S. Woolhouse & Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (eds.) - 2023 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This is the first volume compiling English translations of Leibniz's journal articles on natural philosophy, presenting a selection of 26 articles, only three of which have appeared before in English translation. It also includes in full Leibniz's public controversies with De Catelan, Papin, and Hartsoeker. The articles include work in optics, on the fracture strength of materials, and on motion in a resisting medium, and Leibniz's pioneering applications of his calculus to these issues by construing them as mini-max and inverse (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Discourse on Metaphysics and the Monadology.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 1902 - Buffalo, N.Y.: Dover Publications. Edited by George R. Montgomery & Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.
    Two of Leibniz's most studied and often quoted works appear in this volume. Published in 1686, the Discourse on Metaphysics consists of the philosopher's explanation of individual perception as an expression of the rest of the universe from a unique perspective. The whole world--the best of all possible worlds, as he famously remarks--is thus contained in each individual substance. The Monadology, written in 1714, offers a concise synopsis of Leibniz's philosophy, establishing the laws of final causes, which underlie God's free (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  3. Leibniz' Anthology of Maimonides' Guide.R. Moses Ben Maimon, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Walter Hilliger & Lloyd Strickland (eds.) - 2022 - New York: Shehakol Inc..
    Maimonides’ Latin translation of Moreh Nevukhim | Guide for the Perplexed, was the most influential Jewish work in the last millennia (Di Segni, 2019; Rubio, 2006; Wohlman, 1988, 1995; Kohler, 2017). It marked the beginning of scholasticism, a daughter of Judaism raised by Jewish thinkers, according to historian Heinrich Graetz (Geschichte der Juden, L. 6, Leipzig 1861, p. xii). Printed by Gutenberg's first mechanical press, its influence in the West went as far as the Fifth Lateran Council (1512 — 1517) (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Self‐Differing, Aspects, and Leibniz's Law.Donald L. M. Baxter - 2018 - Noûs 52:900-920.
    I argue that an individual has aspects numerically identical with it and each other that nonetheless qualitatively differ from it and each other. This discernibility of identicals does not violate Leibniz's Law, however, which concerns only individuals and is silent about their aspects. They are not in its domain of quantification. To argue that there are aspects I will appeal to the internal conflicts of conscious beings. I do not mean to imply that aspects are confined to such cases, but (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  5. 'By Leibniz's law': Remarks on a fallacy.By Benjamin Schnieder - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (222):39–54.
    The article is an investigation of a certain form of argument that refers to Leibniz’s Law as its inference ticket (where Leibniz’s Law is understood as the thesis that if x=y.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  6. Analysis and Reform of Leibniz's Law of Sufficient Reason.Shi Jing - 2024 - International Journal of Philosophy 12 (2):16-21.
    Since Leibniz first put forward the sufficient reason law in his philosophical work "The Monadology" (1914), the issue of the law of sufficient reason has aroused heated discussions in the field of logic in our country. The question of whether the law of sufficient reason is the basic law of formal logic was particularly heated in the domestic logic circle in 1978-1980. Since then, there has been little discussion, but from the newly compiled formal logic textbooks published one after another, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Identity, Leibniz’s Law and Non-Transitive Reasoning.Pablo Cobreros, Paul Egré, David Ripley & Robert van Rooij - 2013 - Metaphysica 14 (2):253-264.
    Arguments based on Leibniz's Law seem to show that there is no room for either indefinite or contingent identity. The arguments seem to prove too much, but their conclusion is hard to resist if we want to keep Leibniz's Law. We present a novel approach to this issue, based on an appropriate modification of the notion of logical consequence.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8.  52
    Identity, Leibniz's Law and Non-transitive Reasoning.Pablo Cobreros, Paul Egré, David Ripley & Robert Rooij - 2013 - Metaphysica 14 (2):253-264.
    Arguments based on Leibniz's Law seem to show that there is no room for either indefinite or contingent identity. The arguments seem to prove too much, but their conclusion is hard to resist if we want to keep Leibniz's Law. We present a novel approach to this issue, based on an appropriate modification of the notion of logical consequence.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9. Wenchao li and Hans Poser.Leibniz'S. Positive View Of China - 2006 - Journal of Chinese Philosophy 33:17.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. The Leibniz’s Law Problem.Stephen Wright - 2010 - Metaphysica 11 (2):137-151.
    Stage theorists invoke the idea of counterpart relations to make sense of how objects are able to persist despite their claim that an object is identical with a single instantaneous stage. According to stage theorists, an object persists if and only if it has a later counterpart that bears the appropriate counterpart relation of identity to it. Whilst objects can and do persist, stages cannot and do not. This seems to amount to a refutation of Leibniz’s law. Stage theorists think (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11. Composition as identity, Leibniz’s Law, and slice-sensitive emergent properties.Phillip Bricker - 2019 - Synthese:4389-4409.
    Moderate composition as identity holds that there is a generalized identity relation, “being the same portion of reality,” of which composition and numerical identity are distinct species. Composition is a genuine kind of identity; but unlike numerical identity, it fails to satisfy Leibniz’s Law. A composite whole and its parts differ with respect to their numerical properties: the whole is one; the parts (collectively) are many. Moderate composition as identity faces the challenge: how, in the absence of Leibniz’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Arguments by Leibniz’s Law in Metaphysics.Ofra Magidor - 2011 - Philosophy Compass 6 (3):180-195.
    Leibniz’s Law (or as it sometimes called, ‘the Indiscerniblity of Identicals’) is a widely accepted principle governing the notion of numerical identity. The principle states that if a is identical to b, then any property had by a is also had by b. Leibniz’s Law may seem like a trivial principle, but its apparent consequences are far from trivial. The law has been utilised in a wide range of arguments in metaphysics, many leading to substantive and controversial conclusions. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  13.  73
    Quantification and Leibniz's law.Mark Richard - 1987 - Philosophical Review 96 (4):555-578.
    The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVI, No. 4 (October 1987). Categorically proves that Leibniz's Law (the principle that any instance of _for any x and y, if x=y, then if ...x..., then ..y..._ is true) is not a principle of which is true of natural language objectual quantification.
    No categories
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  14.  36
    Leibniz's law and belief.Robert J. Swartz - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (5):122-137.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. XII—Leibniz's Law and the Philosophy of Mind.Frank Jackson - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (3pt3):269-283.
    We draw some metaphysical conclusions about colour and belief from some epistemological commonplaces. It turns out that this requires us to challenge orthodoxy on the causal efficacy of mental properties and to rewrite the standard argument against dualism, but in a way which is good news for functionalists about the mind.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  29
    Leibniz's law and the antinomy of the liar.Vito F. Sinisi - 1969 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 30 (2):279-289.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  7
    XII-Leibniz's Law and the Philosophy of Mind.Frank Jackson - 2012 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 112 (3):269-283.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. The New Leibniz's Law Arguments for Pluralism.Bryan Frances - 2006 - Mind 115 (460):1007-1022.
    For years philosophers argued for the existence of distinct yet materially coincident things by appealing to modal and temporal properties. For instance, the statue was made on Monday and could not survive being flattened; the lump of clay was made months before and can survive flattening. Such arguments have been thoroughly examined. Kit Fine has proposed a new set of arguments using the same template. I offer a critical evaluation of what I take to be his central lines of reasoning.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  19. Relative identity and Leibniz's law.Leslie Stevenson - 1972 - Philosophical Quarterly 22 (87):155-158.
    The indiscernibility of identicals is incompatible with geach's theory of 'relative' identity, But consistent with the view that x is identical with y iff x is the same a as y, For some count-Noun 'a'. 'x is the same a as y' expresses identity only if x is an a, Otherwise it is merely an equivalence relation.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  20.  56
    Prior on Leibniz's Law.Jack Nelson - 1970 - Analysis 30 (3):92 - 94.
    Professor arthur prior has argued that because one thing can become two things we must abandon leibniz's law. ("time, Existence and identity" in 'papers on time and tense', Oxford, 1968). I argue that while it does often happen that one thing becomes two things, We need not say that in such cases one thing is identical with both the things it becomes. Fission need not be seen as preserving identity. Hence prior does not provide us with adequate reasons for abandoning (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Incarnation, Timelessness, and Leibniz's Law Problems.Thomas D. Senor - 2002 - In Gregory E. Ganssle & David M. Woodruff (eds.), God and Time: Essays on the Divine Nature. Oxford University Press.
  22. Comments on Mark Kalderon's “The Open Question Argument, Frege's Puzzle, and Leibniz's Law”.Peter Alward - unknown
    A standard strategy for defending a claim of non-identity is one which invokes Leibniz’s Law. (1) Fa (2) ~Fb (3) (∀x)(∀y)(x=y ⊃ (∀P)(Px ⊃ Py)) (4) a=b ⊃ (Fa ⊃ Fb) (5) a≠b In Kalderon’s view, this basic strategy underlies both Moore’s Open Question Argument (OQA) as well as (a variant formulation of) Frege’s puzzle (FP). In the former case, the argument runs from the fact that some natural property—call it “F-ness”—has, but goodness lacks, the (2nd order) property of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Interpreting the Infinitesimal Mathematics of Leibniz and Euler.Jacques Bair, Piotr Błaszczyk, Robert Ely, Valérie Henry, Vladimir Kanovei, Karin U. Katz, Mikhail G. Katz, Semen S. Kutateladze, Thomas McGaffey, Patrick Reeder, David M. Schaps, David Sherry & Steven Shnider - 2017 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 48 (2):195-238.
    We apply Benacerraf’s distinction between mathematical ontology and mathematical practice to examine contrasting interpretations of infinitesimal mathematics of the seventeenth and eighteenth century, in the work of Bos, Ferraro, Laugwitz, and others. We detect Weierstrass’s ghost behind some of the received historiography on Euler’s infinitesimal mathematics, as when Ferraro proposes to understand Euler in terms of a Weierstrassian notion of limit and Fraser declares classical analysis to be a “primary point of reference for understanding the eighteenth-century theories.” Meanwhile, scholars like (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  24. Feldman and Sommers on Leibniz's Law.George Englebretsen - 1984 - Diálogos. Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad de Puerto Rico 19 (43):91.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  9
    Natural law: historical, systematic and juridical approaches.José María Torralba, Mario Šilar, García Martínez & Alejandro Néstor (eds.) - 2008 - Newscastle upon Tyne, UK: Cambridge Scholars Press.
    Modern moral and political philosophy is in debt with natural law theory, both in its ancient and mediaeval elaborations. While the very notion of a natural law has proved highly controversial among 20th Century scholars, the last decades have witnessed a renewed interest in it. Indeed, the threats and challenges as result of multiculturalism, plural societies and global changes have generated a renewed attention to natural law theory. Clearly, it offers solid basis as possible framework to a better understanding of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  34
    On a Famous Counterexample to Leibniz's Law.Neil Feit - 1996 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96 (1):381-386.
    Neil Feit; Graduate Papers from the Joint Session 1995: On a Famous Counterexample to Leibniz's Law1, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 96, Issue.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  4
    Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz.R. S. Woolhouse - 2002 - In Steven Nadler (ed.), A Companion to Early Modern Philosophy. Malden, MA, USA: Blackwell. pp. 260–280.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introduction General Philosophical Background Substance Substances: Mental and Material Kingdom of Nature: Physics and Laws of Motion Union of Mind and Body: Pre‐established Harmony Kingdom of Nature and of Grace: Grades of Life Human Freedom in the Kingdom of Grace Sufficient Reason and Indiscernibility: Space and Time The Existence of God.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  17
    Neuzeit und Aufklärung, Studien zur Entstehung der neuzeitlichen Wissenschaft und Philosophie. [REVIEW]S. R. - 1973 - Review of Metaphysics 27 (1):148-148.
    This work is largely the author’s Habilitationsschrift presented at Erlangen. There are three major parts: the first describes ancient and modern forms of scientific reason, the development of which he calls a first and a second Enlightenment; the second explores more deeply certain elements in modern science such as the laws of motion, experimentation, forms of calculation, gravity and force; the third studies rational methodology, including issues of epistemology and artificial languages. The author accepts Kant’s and Nietzsche’s criticism of earlier (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. “A Complete Denial of the Continuous”? Leibniz's Law of Continuity.Richard Tw Arthur - unknown
  30.  24
    Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy (review).Christopher S. Celenza - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (2):207-208.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Hellenistic and Early Modern PhilosophyChristopher S. CelenzaJon Miller and Brad Inwood, editors. Hellenistic and Early Modern Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2003. Pp. xii + 330. Cloth, $60.00.There are at least two ways of writing the history of philosophy: the first and most common among those self-identified as "philosophers" treats philosophers of the past as if they were in live dialogue with the present. Only the text (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  27
    Act Identity, Referential Opacity, And Leibniz's Law.Michael Wreen - 1984 - Philosophical Inquiry 6 (2):144-148.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. 1. Monadology § 17 Leibniz presents the example of a mill in a number of letters and essays which are concerned with the issue of whether there could be thinking machines. 2 However its appearance in § 17 of the M onadolo gy has drawn by far the most attention from recent philosophers. 3 Let us begin. [REVIEW]Stepping Back Inside Leibniz'S. Milv - 1998 - The Monist 81 (4):553-572.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  16
    Leibniz’s syncategorematic infinitesimals.Richard T. W. Arthur - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (5):553-593.
    In contrast with some recent theories of infinitesimals as non-Archimedean entities, Leibniz’s mature interpretation was fully in accord with the Archimedean Axiom: infinitesimals are fictions, whose treatment as entities incomparably smaller than finite quantities is justifiable wholly in terms of variable finite quantities that can be taken as small as desired, i.e. syncategorematically. In this paper I explain this syncategorematic interpretation, and how Leibniz used it to justify the calculus. I then compare it with the approach of Smooth Infinitesimal (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34.  56
    Leibniz’s syncategorematic infinitesimals II: their existence, their use and their role in the justification of the differential calculus.David Rabouin & Richard T. W. Arthur - 2020 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 74 (5):401-443.
    In this paper, we endeavour to give a historically accurate presentation of how Leibniz understood his infinitesimals, and how he justified their use. Some authors claim that when Leibniz called them “fictions” in response to the criticisms of the calculus by Rolle and others at the turn of the century, he had in mind a different meaning of “fiction” than in his earlier work, involving a commitment to their existence as non-Archimedean elements of the continuum. Against this, we show that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Leibniz’s doctrine of toleration: philosophical, theological and pragmatic reasons.Maria Rosa Antognazza - 2013 - In J. Parkin & T. Stanton (eds.), Natural Law and Toleration in the Early Enlightenment. Oxford University Press. pp. 139-164.
    Leibniz is not commonly numbered amongst canonical writers on toleration. One obvious reason is that, unlike Locke, he wrote no treatise specifically devoted to that doctrine. Another is the enormous amount of energy which he famously devoted to ecclesiastical reunification. Promoting the reunification of Christian churches is an objective quite different from promoting the toleration of different religious faiths – so different, in fact, that they are sometimes even construed as mutually exclusive. Ecclesiastical reunification aims to find agreement at least (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  21
    Leibniz’s Analysis of Change: Vague States, Physical Continuity, and the Calculus.Richard Arthur - unknown
    One of the most puzzling features of Leibniz’s deep metaphysics is the apparent contradiction between his claims that the law of continuity holds everywhere, so that in particular, change is continuous in every monad, and that “changes are not really continuous,” since successive states contradict one another. In this paper I try to show in what sense these claims can be understood as compatible. My analysis depends crucially on Leibniz’s idea that enduring states are “vague,” and abstract away (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Leibniz's syncategorematic infinitesimals, smooth infinitesimal analysis, and Newton's proposition.Richard Arthur - manuscript
    In contrast with some recent theories of infinitesimals as non-Archimedean entities, Leibniz’s mature interpretation was fully in accord with the Archimedean Axiom: infinitesimals are fictions, whose treatment as entities incomparably smaller than finite quantities is justifiable wholly in terms of variable finite quantities that can be taken as small as desired, i.e. syncategorematically. In this paper I explain this syncategorematic interpretation, and how Leibniz used it to justify the calculus. I then compare it with the approach of Smooth Infinitesimal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Leibniz's Optics and Contingency in Nature.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2010 - Perspectives on Science 18 (4):432-455.
    Leibniz’s mature philosophical understanding of the laws of nature emerges rather suddenly in the late 1670’s to early 1680’s and is signaled by his embrace of three central theses.1 The first, what I’ll call the thesis of Contingency, suggests that the laws of nature are not only contingent, but, in some sense, paradigmatically contingent; they are supposed to provide insight into the very nature of contingency as Leibniz comes to understand it. The second, what I’ll call the thesis of (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  39. Leibniz's two realms revisited.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2008 - Noûs 42 (4):673-696.
    Leibniz speaks, in a variety of contexts, of there being two realms—a "kingdom of power or efficient causes" and "a kingdom of wisdom or final causes." This essay explores an often overlooked application of Leibniz's famous "two realms doctrine." The first part turns to Leibniz's work in optics for the roots of his view that nature can be seen as being governed by two complete sets of equipotent laws, with one set corresponding to the efficient causal order of the world, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  40.  52
    Leibniz’s Méditation sur la notion commune de la justice, 1703-2003.Patrick Riley - 2003 - The Leibniz Review 13:67-81.
    Leibniz’s Méditation sur la notion commune de la justice is his most important writing on justice as “wise charity” and “universal benevolence” ; we now observe the 300th anniversary of its composition, and a reproduction of part of Leibniz’s manuscript appears in the Appendix to this article. But Leibniz’s essay might with equal justice be called, “Meditation on the Common Notion of Platonism”—for the Méditation opens with a nearly-verbatim paraphrase of Euthyphro 9e-10e, moves on to reduce Hobbes (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  14
    Leibniz’s Méditation sur la notion commune de la justice, 1703-2003.Patrick Riley - 2003 - The Leibniz Review 13:67-81.
    Leibniz’s Méditation sur la notion commune de la justice is his most important writing on justice as “wise charity” and “universal benevolence” ; we now observe the 300th anniversary of its composition, and a reproduction of part of Leibniz’s manuscript appears in the Appendix to this article. But Leibniz’s essay might with equal justice be called, “Meditation on the Common Notion of Platonism”—for the Méditation opens with a nearly-verbatim paraphrase of Euthyphro 9e-10e, moves on to reduce Hobbes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42. Leibniz's philosophy of physics.Jeffrey K. McDonough - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    entry for the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP) This entry will attempt to provide a broad overview of the central themes of Leibniz’s philosophy of physics, as well as an introduction to some of the principal arguments and argumentative strategies he used to defend his positions. It tentatively includes sections entitled, The Historical Development of Leibniz’s Physics, Leibniz on Matter, Leibniz’s Dynamics, Leibniz on the Laws of Motion, Leibniz on Space and Time. A bibliography arranged by topic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43. Leibniz's complete propositional logic.Hector-Neri Castañeda - 1990 - Topoi 9 (1):15-28.
    I have shown (to my satisfaction) that Leibniz's final attempt at a generalized syllogistico-propositional calculus in the Generales Inquisitiones was pretty successful. The calculus includes the truth-table semantics for the propositional calculus. It contains an unorthodox view of conjunction. It offers a plethora of very important logical principles. These deserve to be called a set of fundamentals of logical form. Aside from some imprecisions and redundancies the system is a good systematization of propositional logic, its semantics, and a correct account (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  94
    Disinterested Love: Understanding Leibniz's Reconciliation of Self- and Other-Regarding Motives.Gregory Brown - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (2):265-303.
    While he was in the employ of the Elector of Mainz, between 1668 and 1671, Leibniz produced a series of important studies in natural law. One of these, dated between 1670 and 1671, is especially noteworthy since it contains Leibniz's earliest sustained attempt to develop an account of justice. Central to this account is the notion of what Leibniz would later come to call `disinterested love', a notion that remained essentially unchanged in Leibniz's work from this period to the end (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  45. The Immanent Contingency of Physical Laws in Leibniz’s Dynamics.Tzuchien Tho - 2019 - In Rodolfo Garau & Pietro Omodeo (eds.), Contingency and Natural Order in Early Modern Science. Springer Verlag. pp. 289-316.
    This paper focuses on Leibniz’s conception of modality and its application to the issue of natural laws. The core of Leibniz’s investigation of the modality of natural laws lays in the distinction between necessary, geometrical laws on the one hand, and contingent, physical laws of nature on the other. For Leibniz, the contingency of physical laws entailed the assumption of the existence of an additional form of causality beyond mechanical or efficient ones. While geometrical truths, being necessary, do (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  44
    Leibniz's Political and Moral Philosophy in the "Novissima Sinica", 1699-1999.Patrick Riley - 1999 - Journal of the History of Ideas 60 (2):217.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Leibniz’s Political and Moral Philosophy in the Novissima Sinica, 1699–1999Patrick RileyThe Preface to Leibniz’s Novissima Sinica 1 contains an important but highly compressed and abbreviated quintessence of his theory of justice or jurisprudence universelle—a version so compressed and abbreviated that one must have a broader and fuller understanding of this universal jurisprudence before one can entirely appreciate what Leibniz has to say about Christian charity, Platonism, and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47.  50
    Leibniz's Theory of Time.Soshichi Uchii - unknown
    I have developed an informational interpretation of Leibniz’s metaphysics and dynamics, but in this paper I will concentrate on his theory of time. According to my interpretation, each monad is an incorporeal automaton programed by God, and likewise each organized group of monads is a cellular automaton governed by a single dominant monad. The activities of these produce phenomena, which must be “coded appearances” of these activities; God determines this coding. A crucially important point here is that we have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  27
    Leibniz's Naturalized Philosophy of Mind by Larry M. Jorgensen.Ursula Goldenbaum - 2021 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 59 (4):684-686.
    Larry Jorgensen aims to show that "Leibniz offers a fully natural theory of mind", recommending Leibniz to our contemporary discussion of naturalism. Readers of Leibniz will, however, hesitate to call him a naturalist. After all, he considered natural laws to be subordinated rules below general divine laws and rejected explaining the soul's action by bodily motion. Jorgensen does have a point, though, when he refers to Leibniz's frequent pleas for natural explanations and his continuity principle.Jorgensen's project unfolds in four parts. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  34
    Leibniz's Universal Jurisprudence: Justice as the Charity of the Wise (review).Susanna Goodin - 1998 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 36 (3):470-471.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Leibniz’s Universal Jurisprudence: Justice as the Charity of the Wise by Patrick RileySusanna GoodinPatrick Riley. Leibniz’s Universal Jurisprudence: Justice as the Charity of the Wise. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996. Pp. xiii + 338. Cloth, $39.95.Leibniz’s political views are often downplayed, if not simply ignored, by philosophers focusing on his metaphysical accounts of substance and force. That Leibniz himself does not view these two areas (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Leibniz’s Infinitesimals: Their Fictionality, Their Modern Implementations, and Their Foes from Berkeley to Russell and Beyond. [REVIEW]Mikhail G. Katz & David Sherry - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (3):571-625.
    Many historians of the calculus deny significant continuity between infinitesimal calculus of the seventeenth century and twentieth century developments such as Robinson’s theory. Robinson’s hyperreals, while providing a consistent theory of infinitesimals, require the resources of modern logic; thus many commentators are comfortable denying a historical continuity. A notable exception is Robinson himself, whose identification with the Leibnizian tradition inspired Lakatos, Laugwitz, and others to consider the history of the infinitesimal in a more favorable light. Inspite of his Leibnizian sympathies, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000