Results for 'Law and Coercion'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  66
    Law and Coercion: Some Clarification.Lucas Miotto - 2021 - Ratio Juris 34 (1):74-87.
    The relationship between law and coercion has been, and still is, a central topic in legal philosophy. Despite this, discussion about it is immersed in confusion. Some philosophers have noticed this, but hardly any work has been done to attempt to solve or even identify the confusions. This paper aims to fill this gap. Here I propose distinctions and qualifications that help us clarify the relationship between law and coercion and avoid confusion. Building on the clarificatory work, I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  57
    Law and Coercion Introduction.Lucas Miotto - 2016 - Jurisprudence 7 (3):523-524.
  3.  12
    On law and coercion – once again: Coercion and the Nature of Law, by Kenneth Einar Himma, Oxford University Press, 2020, 288 pp., £50.00 (hardcover), ISBN 9780198854937.Miodrag Jovanovic - 2021 - Jurisprudence 12 (3):417-425.
    If one were to publish a book some hundred years ago, with the central claim that there was a necessary connection between law and coercion, one would have largely pushed on an open door. And to sa...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  92
    Law and Coercion.Robert C. Hughes - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (3):231-240.
    Though political philosophers often presuppose that coercive enforcement is fundamental to law, many legal philosophers have doubted this. This article explores doubts of two types. Some legal philosophers argue that given an adequate account of coercion and coerciveness, the enforcement of law in actual legal systems will generally not count as coercive. Others accept that actual legal systems enforce many laws coercively, but they deny that law has a necessary connection with coercion. There can be individual laws that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  5.  39
    Marx, law, and coercion.Edmund Wall - 2001 - Journal of Social Philosophy 32 (1):70–77.
  6.  32
    Williamson on law and coercion.W. J. Rees - 1970 - Ethics 81 (1):68-73.
  7.  46
    Hobbes on law and coercion.Colwyn Williamson - 1970 - Ethics 80 (2):146-155.
  8.  71
    The Forces of Law: Duty, Coercion, and Power.Leslie Green - 2016 - Ratio Juris 29 (2):164-181.
    This paper addresses the relationship between law and coercive force. It defends, against Frederick Schauer's contrary claims, the following propositions: The force of law consists in three things, not one: the imposition of duties, the use of coercion, and the exercise of social power. These are different and distinct. Even if coercion is not part of the concept of law, coercion is connected to law many important ways, and these are amply recognized in contemporary analytic jurisprudence. We (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  9.  90
    The Rights of States, the Rule of Law, and Coercion: Reflections on Pauline Kleingeld's Kant and Cosmopolitanism.Alyssa R. Bernstein - 2014 - Kantian Review 19 (2):233-249.
    Pauline Kleingeld argues that according to Kant it would be wrong to coerce a state into an international federation, due to the wrongness of paternalism. Although I agree that Kant opposes the waging of war as a means to peace, I disagree with Kleingeld's account of the reasons why he would oppose coercing a state into a federation. Since she does not address the broader question of the permissibility of interstate coercion, she does not properly address the narrower question (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  26
    The Nature of Law and Potential Coercion.Kara Woodbury-Smith - 2020 - Ratio Juris 33 (2):223-240.
    This paper argues for a novel understanding of the relationship between law and coercion. It firstly refutes Kenneth Himma’s claim that the authorisation of coercive enforcement mechanisms is a conceptually necessary feature of law. It then claims that the best way to understand the law is as coercion-apt. The “coercion-aptness” of law is clarified, in part, by appealing to an essential distinction between law and morality: Whereas it can be reasonable for the law to appeal to coercive (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  11. Law, Coercion and Folk Intuitions.Lucas Miotto, Guilherme F. C. F. Almeida & Noel Struchiner - 2023 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 43 (1):97-123.
    In discussing whether legal systems are necessarily coercive, legal philosophers usually appeal to thought experiments involving angels or other morally driven beings who need no coercion to organise their social lives. Such appeals have invited criticism. Critics have not only challenged the relevance of such thought experiments to our understanding of legal systems; they have also argued that, contrary to the intuitions of most legal philosophers, the ‘man on the Clapham Omnibus’ would not hold that there is law in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Authority and Coercion.Arthur Ripstein - 2004 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 32 (1):2-35.
    I am grateful to Donald Ainslie, Lisa Austin, Michael Blake, Abraham Drassinower, David Dyzenhaus, George Fletcher, Robert Gibbs, Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Sari Kisilevsky, Dennis Klimchuk, Christopher Morris, Scott Shapiro, Horacio Spector, Sergio Tenenbaum, Malcolm Thorburn, Ernest Weinrib, Karen Weisman, and the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs for comments, and audiences in the UCLA Philosophy Department and Columbia Law School for their questions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  13. Kant on Rights and Coercion in International Law: Implications for Humanitarian Military Intervention.Alyssa R. Bernstein - 2007 - Philosophy 38 (2):237.
  14.  26
    Pressure and coercion in the care for the addicted: ethical perspectives.M. J. P. A. Janssens - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (5):453-458.
    The use of coercive measures in the care for the addicted has changed over the past 20 years. Laws that have adopted the “dangerousness” criterion in order to secure patients’ rights to non-intervention are increasingly subjected to critique as many authors plead for wider dangerousness criteria. One of the most salient moral issues at stake is whether addicts who are at risk of causing danger to themselves should be involuntarily admitted and/or treated. In this article, it is argued that the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  15.  5
    Ruling Bodies: A Study of Coercion and Punishment in Plato's Republic, Laws, and Gorgias.Robin Varma - 2022 - Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books.
    This book examines how Plato theorized about coercion and punishment in the Republic, the Laws, and the Gorgias. It highlights a problem in the way we understand coercion in modern politics, and then offers a new framework and context for thinking about this.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Coercion and the nature of law.Grant Lamond - 2001 - Legal Theory 7 (1):35-57.
    It is a commonplace that coercion forms part of the nature of law: Law is inherently coercive. But how well founded is this claim, and what would it mean for coercion to be part of the of law? This article suggests that the claim is grounded in our current conception of law. The main focus of the article, however, is upon two major lines of argument that attempt to establish a link between law and coercion: one based (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  17. Behavioral law and economics : The assault on consent, will, and dignity.Mark D. White - 2010 - In Christi Favor, Gerald Gaus & Julian Lamont (eds.), Essays on Philosophy, Politics & Economics: Integration & Common Research Projects. Stanford Economics and Finance.
    In "Behavioral Law and Economics: The Assault on Consent, Will, and Dignity," Mark D. White uses the moral philosophy of Immanuel Kant to examine the intersection of economics, psychology, and law known as "behavioral law and economics." Scholars in this relatively new field claim that, because of various cognitive biases and failures, people often make choices that are not in their own interests. The policy implications of this are that public and private organizations, such as the state and employers, can (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18. Authority and Coercion Beyond the State? The Limited Applicability of Legitimacy Standards for Extraterritorial Border Controls.Ludvig Beckman - forthcoming - Jus Cogens:1-20.
    Extraterritorial border controls prevent migrants from arriving at the territory of the state and effectively undermine rights to apply for asylum and protections against non-refoulement. As a result, a wealth of scholarship argues that external border controls are illegitimate exercises of state power. This paper challenges two versions of this argument, first, the claim that carrier-sanctions are illegitimate because they subject migrants to morally impermissible forms of coercion and, second, the claim that carrier-sanctions are illegitimate because they subject migrants (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Obligation and coercion.H. L. A. Hart - 1966 - In Martin P. Golding (ed.), The nature of law. New York,: Random House.
  20.  72
    Persuasion and coercion: A critical review of philosophical and empirical approaches. [REVIEW]Penny Powers - 2007 - HEC Forum 19 (2):125-143.
  21.  22
    Law and courts' impact on development and democratization.Catalina Smulovitz - 2010 - In Peter Cane & Herbert M. Kritzer (eds.), The Oxford handbook of empirical legal research. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The definition and measurement of the impact of laws and courts is a subject of disagreement and uncertainties. In this article, law is understood as a public, general, and binding command enforceable through state coercion. Assessments on the effects of laws on democracy and development focus on changes in specific social indicators. The evaluation of impact relates to the availability and reliability of judicial statistics and the impact of laws depends on political and social conditions. The interaction of laws (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Law and the Entitlement to Coerce.Robert C. Hughes - 2013 - In Wilfrid J. Waluchow & Stefan Sciaraffa (eds.), Philosophical foundations of the nature of law. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 183.
    Many assume that whenever government is entitled to make a law, it is entitled to enforce that law coercively. I argue that the justification of legal authority and the justification of governmental coercion come apart. Both in ideal theory and in actual human societies, governments are sometimes entitled to make laws that they are not entitled to enforce coercively.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23. Customary law with private means of resolving disputes and dispensing justice: a description of a modern system of law and order without state coercion.Bruce L. Benson - 1990 - Journal of Libertarian Studies 9 (2):25-42.
  24.  27
    Abortion, Brain Death, and Coercion.Michael Nair-Collins - 2023 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 20 (3):359-365.
    A “universalist” policy on brain death holds that brain death is death, and neurologic criteria for death determination are rightly applied to all, without exemptions or opt outs. This essay argues that advocates of a universalist brain death policy defend the same sort of coercive control of end-of-life decision-making as “pro-life” advocates seek to achieve for reproductive decision-making, and both are grounded in an illiberal political philosophy. Those who recognize the serious flaws of this kind of public policy with respect (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  35
    Law and Psychiatry: The Problems That Will Not Go Away.Thomas Szasz - 1990 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 11 (3-4):557-564.
    The practice of psychiatry rests on two pillars: mental illness and involuntary mental hospitalization. Each of these elements justifies and reinforces the other. Traditionally, psychiatric coercion was unidirectional, consisting of the forcible incarceration of the individual in an insane asylum. Today, it is bidirectional, the forcible eviction of the individual from the mental hospital supplementing his or her prior forcible incarceration in it. So intimate are the connections between psychiatry and coercion that noncoercive psychiatry, like noncoercive slavery, is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Markets, Sweatshops, and Coercion.Michael Kates - 2015 - Georgetown Journal of Law and Public Policy 13.
  27.  5
    Coercion and Responsibility in Islam: A Study in Ethics and Law.Mairaj U. Syed - 2016 - Oxford University Press UK.
    In Coercion and Responsibility in Islam, Mairaj Syed explores how classical Muslim theologians and jurists from four intellectual traditions argue about the thorny issues that coercion raises about responsibility for one's action. This is done by assessing four ethical problems: whether the absence of coercion or compulsion is a condition for moral agency; how the law ought to define what is coercive; coercion's effect on the legal validity of speech acts; and its effects on moral and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  13
    Coercion and the Nature of Law.Kenneth Einar Himma - 2020 - Oxford University Press.
    This book makes a systematic defence of the Coercion Thesis in law, arguing that coercion or enforcement mechanisms are not only a necessary feature of legal systems, but a conceptually necessary feature of legal systems.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  34
    Process values, international law, and justice.Paul B. Stephan - 2006 - Social Philosophy and Policy 23 (1):131-152.
    A focus on the lawmaking process, I submit, permits us to explore a particular dimension of justice, namely the relationship between law and liberty. Laws that reflect the arbitrary whims of the lawmaker are presumptively unjust, because they constrain liberty for no good reason. A strategy for making arbitrary laws less likely involves recognizing checks on the lawmaker's powers and grounding those checks in processes that allow the governed to express their disapproval. The system of checks and balances employed in (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  58
    Kant, International Law, and the Problem of Humanitarian Intervention.Antonio Franceschet - 2010 - Journal of International Political Theory 6 (1):1-22.
    International law has one principal mechanism for settling the legality of humanitarian interventions, the United Nations Security Council's power to authorise coercion. However, this is hardly satisfactory in practice and has failed to provide a more secure juridical basis for determining significant conflicts among states over when humanitarian force is justified. This article argues that, in spite of Immanuel Kant's limited analysis of intervention, and his silence on humanitarian intervention, his political theory provides the elements of a compelling analysis (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31. Consent, Coercion, and Sexual Autonomy.Jeffrey Gauthier - 1999 - In Keith Burgess-Jackson (ed.), A Most Detestable Crime: New Philosophical Essays on Rape. Oxford University Press. pp. 71-91.
    Feminist legal scholarship has questioned the usefulness of non-consent as a criterion for rape. Under conditions of generalized sexual oppression, consent may not be an adequate for absence of coercion. I defend this argument and propose that rape law reform can be usefully informed by state protection of workers in the capitalist labor market, where it is assumed that the parties occupy an unequal bargaining position.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  41
    Respect for Autonomy: Its Demands and Limits in Biobanking. [REVIEW]Iain Law - 2011 - Health Care Analysis 19 (3):259-268.
    This paper argues that the demands of respect for autonomy in the context of biobanking are fewer and more limited than is often supposed. It discusses the difficulties of agreeing a concept of autonomy from which duties can easily be derived, and suggests an alternative way to determine what respect for autonomy in a biobanking context requires. These requirements, it argues, are limited to provision of adequate information and non-coercion. While neither of these is in itself negligible, this is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  33
    Coercion, Interrogation, and Prisoners of War.Nathan Lake & Jonathan Trerise - 2022 - Journal of Military Ethics 21 (2):151-161.
    The law of armed conflict prevents the coerced extraction of information from Prisoners of War (PoWs). We claim, however, that the letter of that law involves too broad a concept of coercion. On a natural reading, there is a sense in which any extraction of information—by any method—is coercive. We respect the notion that PoWs ought not be treated poorly, but we argue “coercion” should not be understood so broadly. With respect to its use in international law, we (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  11
    Nine. Coercion and the law: Conclusion.Alan Wertheimer - 1990 - In Coercion. Princeton University Press. pp. 170-176.
  35.  88
    Coercion, Consent and the Forced Marriage Debate in the UK.Sundari Anitha & Aisha Gill - 2009 - Feminist Legal Studies 17 (2):165-184.
    An examination of case law on forced marriage reveals that in addition to physical force, the role of emotional pressure is now taken into consideration. However, in both legal and policy discourse, the difference between arranged and forced marriage continues to be framed in binary terms and hinges on the concept of consent: the context in which consent is constructed largely remains unexplored. By examining the socio-cultural construction of personhood, especially womanhood, and the intersecting structural inequalities that constrain particular groups (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  71
    Sympathy for the Devil(s)? Personality and Legal Coercion in Kant's Doctrine of Law.Bernd Ludwig - 2015 - Jurisprudence 6 (1):25-44.
    The central concept in Kant's _Doctrine of Law_ is the concept of a _person_. This very concept is intimately connected with Kant's theory of transcendental freedom and thus with his Transcendental Idealism. Hence the conceptual framework of the _Doctrine of Law_ and with it the 'Universal Principle of Right' are inseparably connected to Kant's _critical_ moral philosophy and require especially the moral law as their foundation. But nevertheless this does not entail that legal coercion requires the personality of those (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  64
    From Angels to Humans: Law, Coercion, and the Society of Angels Thought Experiment.Lucas Miotto - 2020 - Law and Philosophy 40 (3):277-303.
    Whether legal systems are necessarily coercive raises normative concerns. Coercion carries a presumption of illegitimacy and a special justificatory burden. If legal systems are necessarily coercive, coerciveness necessarily taints our legal institutions. Traditionally, legal systems have been regarded as contingently coercive. This view is mainly supported by the society of angels thought experiment. For the past few years, however, this traditional view has been under attack. Critics have challenged the reliability of the thought experiment and have urged us to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Part Seven : Epistemology and Sexual Consent. Epistemic Responsibility in Sexual Coercion and Self-Defense Law / Hallie Liberto ; Sexual Consent and Epistemic Agency / Jennifer Lackey ; The Epistemology of Consent.Alexander A. Guerrero - 2021 - In Jennifer Lackey (ed.), Applied Epistemology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
  39. Kant's Theory of Juridical Duties and Their Legislation: An Examination of the Relationship of Law and Morality According to "Metaphysik der Sitten".Sven Arntzen - 1988 - Dissertation, The Johns Hopkins University
    Kant has made an attempt in his Doctrine of Law to show that the principles of natural Law are a priori principles of pure practical reason. He considers this a necessary step towards establishing the obligating force of positive legislation within a legal system. It is not obvious, however, that Law, which recognizes external coercion as a possible incentive for the compliance with its duties, can be reconciled with pure practical reason, which through the categorical imperative commands that one (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  14
    Kant's theory of law: proceedings of the special workshop "Kant's Concept of Law" held at the 26th World Congress of the International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy in Belo Horizonte, 2013.Jean-Christophe Merle & Alexandre Travessoni Gomes Trivisonno (eds.) - 2015 - [Baden-Baden]: Nomos.
    This volume presents an extended version of the contributions presented at the workshop "Kant's Concept of Law" held at the 26th World Congress of the International Association for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy (IVR) in 2013. It handles issues of applied legal philosophy in Kant's Doctrine of Right such as ownership, the alleged right of necessity, the right of resistance and the right of revolution. With each of these applied issues, the focus lies, on the one hand, on the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  12
    “The Role of Coercion in Law: The Case of International Law.”.Sandra Raponi - 2016 - Washington University Jurisprudence Review 8 (1).
    Critics of international law argue that it is not really law because it lacks a supranational system of coercive sanctions. International legal scholars and lawyers primarily refute this by demonstrating that international law is in fact enforced, albeit in decentralized and less coercive ways. I will focus instead on the presumption behind this skeptical view—the idea that law must be coercively enforced. First, I argue that coercive enforcement is not conceptually necessary for law or legal obligations. Second, I consider the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Coercion, Threats, and the Puzzle of Blackmail.Grant Lamond - 1996 - In A. P. Simester & A. T. H. Smith (eds.), Harm and culpability. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 215-38.
    This paper discusses the puzzle of blackmail, i.e. the way in which the threat of an otherwise legally permissible action can in some cases constitute blackmail. It argues that the key to understanding blackmail is in terms of coercion and threats, and the effect such threats have on the validity of a victim’s consent. The nature of coercion and of coercive threats is considered in detail to support the thesis that threats are prima facie impermissible, though often justified (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  43.  8
    Public Reason, Coercion, and Overlapping Consensus.Ezequiel Spector - forthcoming - Moral Philosophy and Politics.
    The idea of public reason involves a standard of legitimacy that requires that laws and institutions be acceptable to all reasonable people, regardless of their conceptions of the good. Many philosophers have argued that public reason should be understood as an answer to the question of how to justify state coercion. However, some authors have criticized this traditional account because it overlooks noncoercive state actions that seem appropriate topics of public reason. More recently, some philosophers have defended the traditional (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  35
    Coercion and Obligation as Exercises of Authority.Steve Coyne - 2016 - Jurisprudence 7 (3):575-592.
    How do exercises of authority different from requests, threats and advice? It is common to answer this question by emphasising the role of obligation, or the role of justified coercion, to the exclusion of the other. Using a distinction between an office of authority and an exercise of authority, I develop a taxonomy of such views of authority and present arguments against each of them. In place of these views, I argue for a symmetrical view of obligation and (...) within legal authority. On my view, authority is a conformance of one’s will to another’s will that the subject could recognise as consistent with the law’s respect for her, and this implies that obligation and coercion can equally be exercises of authority. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  9
    Harmful Thoughts: Essays on Law, Self, and Morality.Meir Dan-Cohen - 2002 - Princeton University Press.
    In these writings by one of our most creative legal philosophers, Meir Dan-Cohen explores the nature of the self and its response to legal commands and mounts a challenge to some prevailing tenets of legal theory and the neighboring moral, political, and economic thought. The result is an insider's critique of liberalism that extends contemporary liberalism's Kantian strand, combining it with postmodernist ideas about the contingent and socially constructed self to build a thoroughly original perspective on some of the most (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  46.  47
    The Jurisprudence Annual Lecture 2010 Freedom, Coercion, Necessary Goods and the Rule of Law.Raymond Plant - 2011 - Jurisprudence 2 (1):1-16.
    This paper focuses on the idea of the rule of law as found in neo-liberal political and legal theory. The central argument is that it is not possible to produce an account of the rule of law and its basic building blocks in such theories—namely freedom, rights and justice—without reference to a set of shared substantive values. The crucial argument is that if freedom is understood negatively, as the absence of coercion, it is not in fact possible to produce (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  6
    Coercion.Grant Lamond - 1996 - In Dennis M. Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Blackwell. pp. 642–653.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Coercion Law References.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  11
    Kant on Law and Justice.Arthur Ripstein - 2009 - In Thomas E. Hill (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Kant's Ethics. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 159–178.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Innate Right Private Right Coercion From Private Right to Public Right Public Right Crime and the Right to Punish Conclusion Bibliography.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  9
    Political justice: foundations for a critical philosophy of law and the state.Otfried Höffe - 1995 - Cambridge, MA, USA: Blackwell.
    Otfried Höffe is one of the foremost political philosophers in Europe today. In this major work, already a classic in continental Europe, he re-examines philosophical discourse on justice - from Classical Greece to the present day. Höffe confronts what he sees as the two major challenges to any theory of justice: the legal, positivist claim that there are no standards of justice external to legal systems; and the anarchist claim that justice demands the rejection and abolition of all legal and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  20
    A Substitute for Coercion – Kant and Rawls on Compliance with International Laws of Justice.Faviola Rivera Castro - 2013 - In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. Boston: de Gruyter. pp. 905-914.
1 — 50 / 1000