Results for 'waive rights'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  45
    Waiving legal rights in research.David B. Resnik & Efthimios Parasidis - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (7):475-478.
    The US federal research regulations prohibit informed consent, whether written or oral, from including provisions in which human subjects waive or appear to waive legal rights. We argue that policies that prevent human subjects from waiving legal rights in research can be ethically justified under the rationale of group, soft paternalism. These policies protect competent adults from making adverse decisions about health and legal matters that they may not understand fully. However, this rationale is less defensible (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  68
    To Waive or Not to Waive: The Right to Trial and Plea Bargaining. [REVIEW]Richard L. Lippke - 2008 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (2):181-199.
    Criminal defendants in many countries are faced with a dilemma: If they waive their right to trial and plead guilty, they typically receive charge or sentence reductions in exchange for having done so. If they exercise their right to trial and are found guilty, they often receive stiffer sanctions than if they had pled guilty. I characterize the former as ‘waiver rewards’ and the latter as ‘non-waiver penalties.’ After clarifying the two and considering the relation between them, I briefly (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  11
    Whether to Waive Parental Permission in HIV Prevention Research Among Adolescents: Ethical and Legal Considerations.Laurie J. Bauman, Claude Ann Mellins & Robert Klitzman - 2020 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 48 (1):188-201.
    Critical ethical questions arise concerning whether studies among adolescents of new behavioral and biomedical HIV preventive interventions such as Pre-Exposure Prophylaxis should obtain parental permission. This paper examines the relevant regulations and ethical guidance concerning waivers of parental permission, and arguments for and against such waivers. Opponents of such waivers may argue that adolescent decision-making is “too immature” and that parents always have rights to decide how to protect their children. Yet requiring parental permission may put adolescents at risk, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  18
    Waiving Jury Deliberation.Andrei Poama - 2020 - Social Theory and Practice 46 (1):181-204.
    This article argues that, given the current pervasive uncertainty about the reliability of jury deliberation, we ought to treat it with epistemic humility. I further argue that epistemic humility should be expressed and enforced by turning jury deliberation from a mandatory rule of the jury trial to a waivable right of the defendant. I consider two main objections to my argument: the first one concerns the putative self-defeatingness of humility attitudes; the second objection points to the burdensomeness of granting an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Right to be Punished?Adriana Placani & Stearns Broadhead - 2020 - European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 16 (1):53-74.
    It appears at least intuitively appropriate to claim that we owe it to victims to punish those who have wronged them. It also seems plausible to state that we owe it to society to punish those who have violated its norms. However, do we also owe punishment to perpetrators themselves? In other words, do those who commit crimes have a moral right to be punished? This work examines the sustainability of the right to be punished from the standpoint of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  6
    Update on Waiving Informed Consent in Emergency Research.Charles R. McCarthy - 1995 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 5 (4):385-386.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Update on Waiving Informed Consent in Emergency ResearchCharles R. McCarthyMadam: The closing statement of my article on Waiving Informed Consent in Emergency Research published in the June 1995 issue of the Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal was: "No doubt we shall hear more of this issue."Indeed, we have heard much more on this issue. (1) In May 1995, after my article had already gone to press, the Food and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  80
    Currents in Contemporary Bioethics: Waiving Informed Consent to Prenatal Screening and Diagnosis? Problems with Paradoxical Negotiation in Surrogacy Contracts.Katherine Drabiak-Syed - 2011 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 39 (3):559-564.
    Recently, an agonizing twist intersecting predictive genetic tests and surrogacy contracts made news headlines in Canada. The intended parents, a couple from British Columbia, instructed the surrogate mother with whom they were working to undergo First Trimester Screening and Chorionic Villi Sampling, which revealed the fetus likely had Down syndrome. The parents directed the surrogate to terminate the fetus or they would abdicate their parental claim upon birth. This story raised numerous legal and ethical questions relating to the transferability of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  18
    Requiring Consent vs. Waiving Consent for Medical Records Research: A Minnesota Law vs. the U.S. (HIPAA) Privacy Rule.Beverly Woodward & Dale Hammerschmidt - 2003 - Health Care Analysis 11 (3):207-218.
    The use of medical records in research can yield information that is difficult to obtain by other means. When such records are released to investigators in identifiable form, however, substantial privacy and confidentiality risks may be created. These risks become more common and more serious as medical records move to an electronic format. In 1996, the state of Minnesota enacted legislation with respect to consent requirements for the use of medical records in research. This legislation has been widely criticized because—it (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  25
    What’s yours is ours: waiving intellectual property protections for COVID-19 vaccines.Nancy S. Jecker & Caesar A. Atuire - 2021 - Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (9):595-598.
    This paper gives an ethical argument for temporarily waiving intellectual property protections for COVID-19 vaccines. It examines two proposals under discussion at the World Trade Organization : the India/South Africa proposal and the WTO Director General proposal. Section I explains the background leading up to the WTO debate. Section II rebuts ethical arguments for retaining current IP protections, which appeal to benefiting society by spurring innovation and protecting rightful ownership. It sets forth positive ethical arguments for a temporary waiver that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  35
    Privacy Rights Forfeiture.Mark Hanin - 2022 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 22 (2).
    Privacy rights can surely be waived. But can they also be forfeited? If so, why and under what conditions? This article takes up these questions by developing a novel theory of privacy rights forfeiture that draws inspiration from Judith Thomson’s canonical work on privacy. The paper identifies two species of forfeiture rooted in modes of negligent and reckless conduct and argues that both self-directed and other-regarding considerations play a role in grounding forfeiture. The paper also contributes to the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  35
    The right not to be a genetic parent?I. Glenn Cohen - manuscript
    Should the law recognize an individual's right not to be a genetic parent when genetic parenthood does not carry with it legal or gestational parenthood? If so, should we allow individuals to waive that right in advance, either by contract or a less formal means? How should the law's treatment of gestational and legal parenthood inform these questions? Developments in reproductive technology have brought these questions to the fore, most prominently in the preembryo disposition cases a number of courts (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Privacy Rights and Public Information.Benedict Rumbold & James Wilson - 2018 - Journal of Political Philosophy 27 (1):3-25.
    This article concerns the nature and limits of individuals’ rights to privacy over information that they have made public. For some, even suggesting that an individual can have a right to privacy over such information may seem paradoxical. First, one has no right to privacy over information that was never private to begin with. Second, insofar as one makes once-private information public – whether intentionally or unintentionally – one waives one’s right to privacy to that information. In this article, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  13.  48
    The 'Right' Not to know.D. E. Ost - 1984 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 9 (3):301-312.
    There is a common view in medical ethics that the patient's right to be informed entails, as well, a correlative right not to be informed, i.e., to waive one's right to information. This paper argues, from a consideration of the concept of autonomy as the foundation for rights, that there can be no such ‘right’ to refuse relevant information, and that the claims for such a right are inconsistent with both deontological and utilitarian ethics. Further, the right to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  14.  27
    Against the inalienable right to withdraw from research.Eric Chwang - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (7):370-378.
    In this paper I argue, against the current consensus, that the right to withdraw from research is sometimes alienable. In other words, research subjects are sometimes morally permitted to waive their right to withdraw. The argument proceeds in three major steps. In the first step, I argue that rights typically should be presumed alienable, both because that is not illegitimately coercive and because the general paternalistic motivation for keeping them inalienable is untenable. In the second step of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15.  17
    Human rights in industrial relations – the israeli approach.David A. Frenkel & Yotam Lurie - 2003 - Business Ethics, the Environment and Responsibility 12 (1):33–40.
    Basic human rights are supposed to protect people from abuse and harm. They are the means whereby we protect our humanity. One would expect, therefore, that basic human rights would be valid and sacred in any context, including industrial relations. However, the complexity of the employee–employer relationship obscures this issue, and it is not clear whether such rights can be protected or whether they are valid in the context of industrial relations. Since rights are relational, they (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  33
    The Right to Withdraw Consent to Research on Biobank Samples.Gert Helgesson & Linus Johnsson - 2005 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 8 (3):315-321.
    Ethical guidelines commonly state that research subjects should have a right to withdraw consent to participate. According to the guidelines we have studied, this right applies also to research on biological samples. However, research conducted on human subjects themselves differs in important respects from research on biological samples. It is therefore not obvious that the same rights should be granted research participants in the two cases. This paper investigates arguments for and against granting a right to withdraw consent to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17.  28
    Respecting rights … to death.N. Levy - 2006 - Journal of Medical Ethics 32 (10):608-611.
    Ravelingien et al1 argue that, given the restrictions that must be imposed on recipients of xenotransplanted organs, we should conduct clinical trials of xenotransplantation only on patients in a persistent vegetative state. I argue that there is no ethical barrier to using terminally ill patients instead. Such patients can choose to waive their rights to the liberties that xenotransplantation would probably restrict; it is surely rational to prefer to waive your rights rather than to die, and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  15
    Xenograft recipients and the right to withdraw from a clinical trial.Christopher Bobier, Daniel J. Hurst, Daniel Rodger & Adam Omelianchuk - 2024 - Bioethics 38 (4):308-315.
    Preclinical xenotransplantation research using genetically engineered pigs has begun to show some promising results and could one day offer a scalable means of addressing organ shortage. While it is a fundamental tenet of ethical human subject research that participants have a right to withdraw from research once enrolled, several scholars have argued that the right to withdraw from xenotransplant research should be suspended because of the public health risks posed by xenozoonotic transmission. Here, we present a comprehensive critical evaluation of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  9
    Human rights in industrial relations - the Israeli approach.David A. Frenkel & Yotam Lurie - 2003 - Business Ethics: A European Review 12 (1):33-40.
    Basic human rights are supposed to protect people from abuse and harm. They are the means whereby we protect our humanity. One would expect, therefore, that basic human rights would be valid and sacred in any context, including industrial relations. However, the complexity of the employee–employer relationship obscures this issue, and it is not clear whether such rights can be protected or whether they are valid in the context of industrial relations. Since rights are relational, they (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  46
    Privacy, Interests, and Inalienable Rights.Adam D. Moore - 2018 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 5 (2):327-355.
    Some rights are so important for human autonomy and well-being that many scholars insist they should not be waived, traded, or abandoned. Privacy is a recent addition to this list. At the other end of the spectrum is the belief that privacy is a mere unimportant interest or preference. This paper defends a middle path between viewing privacy as an inalienable, non-waivable, non-transferrable right and the view of privacy as a mere subjective interest. First, an account of privacy is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21. Rights: Beyond interest theory and will theory? [REVIEW]Rowan Cruft - 2004 - Law and Philosophy 23 (4):347 - 397.
    It is common for philosophers and legal theorists to bemoan the proliferation of the language of rights in popular discourse.1 In a wide range of contemporary public political and ethical debates, disputants are quick to appeal to the existence of rights that support their position – the ‘human rights’ of innocent victims of war, animals’ noninterference rights, individuals’ and businesses’ rights to economic freedom. It is often maintained, with some plausibility, that these public disputes involve (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  22.  81
    The Right to Life, Voluntary Euthanasia, and Termination of Life on Request.Elias Moser - 2017 - Philosophy Study 7 (8):445-454.
    In this article, the logical implications of a right to life are examined. It is first argued that the prohibition of Termination of life on request confers an inalienable right to life. A right is inalienable if it cannot legitimately be waived or transferred. Since voluntary euthanasia entails waiver of the right to life, the inalienability yields that it cannot be justified. Therefore, any ethical position that is in favor of voluntary euthanasia has to argue that the right to life (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  65
    Children’s rights and the non-identity problem.Erik Magnusson - 2019 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (5):580-605.
    Can appealing to children’s rights help to solve the non-identity problem in cases of procreation? A number of philosophers have answered affirmatively, arguing that even if children cannot be harmed by being born into disadvantaged conditions, they may nevertheless be wronged if those conditions fail to meet a minimal standard of decency to which all children are putatively entitled. This paper defends the tenability of this view by outlining and responding to five prominent objections that have been raised against (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  17
    ‘IP’ Moral Rights Breaches are Deception Offences, Not Property Offences: Correcting a Category Error.James McKeahnie - 2016 - Res Publica 22 (2):193-207.
    In March of 2014 Nature Publishing Group, responsible for the publication of journals such as Nature and ScientificAmerican, was subject to criticism for its requirement that contributing authors waive their moral rights in relation to their published articles. Some of the rights included under the umbrella term ‘moral rights’ are the right to have any copies of one’s work reproduced accurately and without alteration; the right to the accurate attribution of one’s work under one’s own name; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  54
    Informed consent: Patient's right or patient's duty?Richard T. Hull - 1985 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 10 (2):183-198.
    The rule that a patient should give a free, fully-informed consent to any therapeutic intervention is traditionally thought to express merely a right of the patient against the physician, and a duty of the physician towards the patient. On this view, the patient may waive that right with impugnity, a fact sometimes expressed in the notion of a right not to know. This paper argues that the rule also expresses a duty of the patient towards the physician and a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  26. Biobank research and the right to privacy.Lars Øystein Ursin - 2008 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 29 (4):267-285.
    What is privacy? What does privacy mean in relation to biobanking, in what way do the participants have an interest in privacy, (why) is there a right to privacy, and how should the privacy issue be regulated when it comes to biobank research? A relational view of privacy is argued for in this article, which takes as its basis a general discussion of several concepts of privacy and attempts at grounding privacy rights. In promoting and protecting the rights (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27.  41
    Search, Seizure, and Immunity: Second-Order Normative Authority and Rights.Stephen E. Henderson & Kelly Sorensen - 2013 - Criminal Justice Ethics 32 (2):108-125.
    A paradigmatic aspect of a paradigmatic kind of right is that the rights holder is the only one who can alienate it. When individuals waive rights, the normative source of that waiving is normally taken to be the individual herself. This moral feature?immunity?is usually in the background of discussions about rights. We bring it into the foreground here, with specific attention to a recent U.S. Supreme Court decision, Kentucky v. King (2011), concerning search and seizure (...). An entailment of the Court's decision is that, at least in some cases, a right can be removed by the intentional actions of the very party against whom the right supposedly protects the rights holder. We argue that the Court's decision is mistaken. The police officers in the case were not morally permitted, and should not be legally permitted, to intentionally create the very circumstances that result in the removal of an individual's right against forced, warrantless search and seizure. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  18
    Mill and the right to remain uninformed.Mark Strasser - 1986 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 11 (3):265-278.
    In a recent article in the Journal of Medicine and Philosophy , David Ost (1984) claims that patients do not have a right to waive their right to information. He argues that patients cannot make informed rational decisions without full information and thus, a right to waive information would involve a right to avoid one's responsibility to act as an autonomous moral agent. In support of his position, Ost cites a passage from Mill. Yet, a correct interpretation of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Notes on a utilitarian justification of rights: The strategy of pre-commitment.William Boardman - unknown
    To begin with, we need to separate off the easy talk of “rights” in which they seem automatically to correspond with a person’s duties or obligations. It is of course true that since I have a duty not to wreak murder or mayhem on you, you have the corresponding right that I not do these things. But so far, the talk of “rights” is simply an alternative way to speak of someone else’s duties; the special or unique point (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  38
    Non-Identity: Solving the Waiver Problem for Future People’s Rights.Rudolf Schuessler - 2016 - Law and Philosophy 35 (1):87-105.
    In a familiar interpretation, the Non-Identity Problem claims that persons whose existence depends on a seemingly harmful action cannot in fact be harmed through such an action. It is often objected that the persons in question can nevertheless be wronged through a violation of their rights. However, this objection seems to fail because these persons would readily waive any violated right in order to come into existence. The present article will analyze this Waiver Counter Argument in detail and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  38
    Legal Pluralism and International Human Rights Law: Inherently Incompatible, Mutually Reinforcing or Something in Between?Helen Quane - 2013 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (4):675-702.
    The relationship between legal pluralism and international human rights law is a complex and multi-faceted one. To fully appreciate the nature of this relationship, one has to desegregate the various forms of legal pluralism and analyse whether in their existence or operation they are compatible with international human rights law. This article undertakes such an exercise drawing on the jurisprudence of global and regional human rights bodies. In doing so, it goes beyond a mechanical audit of legal (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Should Endangered Species Have Standing? Toward Legal Rights for Listed Species.J. Baird Callicott & William Grove-Fanning - 2009 - Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (2):317-352.
    The Endangered Species Act of 1973 (ESA) is America's strongest environmental law. Its citizen-suit provisionany personawards implicit intrinsic value, de facto standing, and operational legal rights (sensu Christopher D. Stone) to listed species. Accordingly, some cases had gone forward in the federal courts in the name of various listed species between 1979 (Palila v. Hawaii Dept. of Land & Natural Resources) and 2004 (Cetacean Community v. Bush), when the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals ruled that animals could not sue (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  21
    Should endangered species have standing? Toward legal rights for listed species: J. Baird Callicott and William Grove-fanning.J. Baird Callicott - 2009 - Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (2):317-352.
    The Endangered Species Act of 1973 is America's strongest environmental law. Its citizen-suit provision—permitting “any person” whomsoever to sue on behalf of a threatened or endangered species—awards implicit intrinsic value, de facto standing, and operational legal rights to listed species. Accordingly, some cases had gone forward in the federal courts in the name of various listed species between 1979 and 2004, when the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals ruled that animals could not sue in their own name. Because the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  41
    Medical privacy and the public's right to vote: What presidential candidates should disclose.Robert Streiffer, Alan P. Rubel & Julie R. Fagan - 2006 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 31 (4):417 – 439.
    We argue that while presidential candidates have the right to medical privacy, the public nature and importance of the presidency generates a moral requirement that candidates waive those rights in certain circumstances. Specifically, candidates are required to disclose information about medical conditions that are likely to seriously undermine their ability to fulfill what we call the "core functions" of the office of the presidency. This requirement exists because (1) people have the right to be governed only with their (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Philippa R. Smith.Cicero Get it Right - 1995 - In Jonathan Powell (ed.), Cicero the philosopher: twelve papers. New York: Clarendon Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Katharina Nieswandt, Concordia University. Authority & Interest in the Theory Of Right - 2019 - In Toh Kevin, Plunkett David & Shapiro Scott (eds.), Dimensions of Normativity: New Essays on Metaethics and Jurisprudence. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Declaration on anthropology and human rights (1999).Committe for Human Rights & American Anthropological Association - 2009 - In Mark Goodale (ed.), Human rights: an anthropological reader. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Index to Volume Fifty-Six.Wim De Reu & Right Words Seem Wrong - 2006 - Philosophy East and West 56 (4):709-714.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Index to Volume Fifty-SixArticlesBernier, Bernard, National Communion: Watsuji Tetsurō's Conception of Ethics, Power, and the Japanese Imperial State, 1 : 84-105Between Principle and Situation: Contrasting Styles in the Japanese and Korean Traditions of Moral Culture, Chai-sik Chung, 2 : 253-280Buxton, Nicholas, The Crow and the Coconut: Accident, Coincidence, and Causation in the Yogavāiṣṭha, 3 : 392-408Chan, Sin Yee, The Confucian Notion of Jing (Respect), Sin Yee Chan, 2 : (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Roland N. Mckean.Some Changing Property Rights - forthcoming - Contemporary Issues in Business Ethics.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. The Liberal Paradox.Some Interpretations When Rights - 1996 - Analyse & Kritik 18:38-53.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Animal liberation or animal rights?, Peter Singer.Moral Rights - 1987 - The Monist 70 (1).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  26
    Right to Private Property.Welfare Rights as Compensation - 2012 - In T. Williamson (ed.), Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond. Wiley-Blackwell.
  43.  24
    Agent-Relativity, Reason, and Value, ROBERT M. STEWART.Eric Rights - 1993 - The Monist 76 (2).
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Carlos S. Nino.Liberal Rights - 1989 - Law and Philosophy 8:37-52.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  12
    From Conflict to Confluence of Interest.Intellectual Property Rights - 2010 - In Thomas H. Murray & Josephine Johnston (eds.), Trust and integrity in biomedical research: the case of financial conflicts of interest. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. John Baden and Richard Stroup.Property Rights - forthcoming - Contemporary Issues in Business Ethics.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Public ai= I= airs quarterly.Private Property Rights - 2002 - Public Affairs Quarterly 16:231.
  48. Raymond plant.Welfare Rights - 1988 - In J. Donald Moon (ed.), Responsibility, Rights, and Welfare: The Theory of the Welfare State. Westview Press. pp. 55.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Timothy F. Murphy.A. Patient'S. Right To Know - 1994 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 19 (4-6):553-569.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  11
    James gs Wilson.Taxonomy of Rights Hohfeld’S. - 2007 - In Richard E. Ashcroft (ed.), Principles of Health Care Ethics. Wiley.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000