Results for 'Descartes and the pineal gland'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  59
    Ana-materialism and the Pineal Eye: Becoming mouth-breast (or visual arts after Descartes, Bataille, Butler, Deleuze and Synthia with an ‘s’)'.Johnny Golding - 2012 - Philosophy of Photography 3 (1):99-120.
    Ana-materialism & the Pineal Eye provides a landmark interpretation of materialism, representation and the image using the Cartesian conceit of a pineal gland and its voracious sexually embedded appetites. Developing the argument via Bataille’s re-invention of the pineal gland as an all-seeing, all- devouring, (pineal) eye, Golding borrows this move to envision a different analytic approach to digital forms of ‘matter’ and artificial forms of ‘life’. From her critical engagement with Bataille, Deleuze and Butler, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  30
    Paradoxes of the Pineal: From Descartes to Georges Bataille.David Farrell Krell - 1987 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 21:215-228.
    Behind the third ventricle of the human brain a miniscule pedunculate bud, close to the optic thalamus, that is, to the two beds of optic nerves, a gland soft in substance yet containing gritty particles. Function: unknown. Because of its pine-cone shape it is called the conarium or pineal body, even though the recent photographs of it by Nilsson and Lindberg show it to be morphologically reminiscent of nothing so much as the plucked tail of a gamebird, which (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  17
    Paradoxes of the Pineal: From Descartes to Georges Bataille.David Farrell Krell - 1987 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 21:215-228.
    Behind the third ventricle of the human brain a miniscule pedunculate bud, close to the optic thalamus, that is, to the two beds of optic nerves, a gland soft in substance yet containing gritty particles. Function: unknown. Because of its pine-cone shape it is called the conarium or pineal body, even though the recent photographs of it by Nilsson and Lindberg show it to be morphologically reminiscent of nothing so much as the plucked tail of a gamebird, which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  26
    Berkeley's Gland Tour into Speculative Fiction Part 1: Homer, Descartes and Pope.Clare Marie Moriarty & Lisa Walters - 2023 - Philosophy Compass 18 (4):e12908.
    Berkeley is best known for his immaterialism and the texts that extol it—the Principles of Human Knowledge and Three Dialogues Between Hylas and Philonous. He made his case by treatise, then by dialogue, and this tendency towards stylistic experimentation did not end there; this paper explores an early speculative fiction project that pursued his theological and philosophical agendas. Berkeley used satire to challenge his “freethinking” philosophical opponents in “The Pineal Gland” story published in The Guardian in 1713. Echoing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. The Passions of the soul and Descartes’s machine psychology.Gary Hatfield - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (1):1-35.
    Descartes developed an elaborate theory of animal physiology that he used to explain functionally organized, situationally adapted behavior in both human and nonhuman animals. Although he restricted true mentality to the human soul, I argue that he developed a purely mechanistic (or material) ‘psychology’ of sensory, motor, and low-level cognitive functions. In effect, he sought to mechanize the offices of the Aristotelian sensitive soul. He described the basic mechanisms in the Treatise on man, which he summarized in the Discourse. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  6.  23
    The Explorations of Descartes and Ryle’s Idea of Mind: An Appraisal.Mishra R. - 2023 - Philosophy International Journal 6 (3):1-5.
    This paper attempts to explore the idea of mind on the basis of René Descartes and Gilbert Ryle’s vision. Descartes, a 17thcentury philosopher, developed a dualistic theory that posits the mind and body as distinct entities. According to him, the mind is an immaterial, non- extended entity with consciousness and rational thought, while the body is a material substance subject to physical laws. In contrast, 20th-century philosopher Ryle rejected the idea of a separate mental realm and argued for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Psychosomatics and the Pineal Gland.Simo Koppe - 2000 - In P. B. Andersen, Claus Emmeche, N. O. Finnemann & P. V. Christiansen (eds.), Downward Causation. Aarhus, Denmark: University of Aarhus Press. pp. 81.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  95
    Natural Geometry in Descartes and Kepler.Gary Hatfield - 2015 - Res Philosophica 92 (1):117-148.
    According to Kepler and Descartes, the geometry of the triangle formed by the two eyes when focused on a single point affords perception of the distance to that point. Kepler characterized the processes involved as associative learning. Descartes described the processes as a “ natural geometry.” Many interpreters have Descartes holding that perceivers calculate the distance to the focal point using angle-side-angle, calculations that are reduced to unnoticed mental habits in adult vision. This article offers a purely (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9. Descartes' physiology and its relation to his psychology.Gary Hatfield - 1992 - In John Cottingham (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Descartes. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 335--370.
    Descartes understood the subject matter of physics (or natural philosophy) to encompass the whole of nature, including living things. It therefore comprised not only nonvital phenomena, including those we would now denominate as physical, chemical, minerological, magnetic, and atmospheric; it also extended to the world of plants and animals, including the human animal (with the exception of those aspects of the human mind that Descartes assigned to solely to thinking substance: pure intellect and will). Descartes wrote extensively (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  10. Did Descartes have a Jamesian theory of the emotions?Gary Hatfield - 2007 - Philosophical Psychology 20 (4):413-440.
    Rene Descartes and William James had "body first" theories of the passions or emotions, according to which sensory stimulation causes a bodily response that then causes an emotion. Both held that this bodily response also causes an initial behavioral response (such as flight from a bear) without any cognitive intervention such as an "appraisal" of the object or situation. From here they differ. Descartes proposed that the initial processes that produce fear and running are entirely mechanical. Even human (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  11. Treatise of Man: French Text with Translation and Commentary, trans. Thomas Steele Hall.René Descartes - 1972 - Cambridge, Mass.: Newcomb Livraria Press.
    A translation by Thomas Steele Hall, an historian of physiology, of the 1664 edition of Descartes' L'Homme (ed. Claude Clerselier). Includes an introduction, review of Descartes' physiology, a synopsis of the first French edition, bibliographical materials (editions and sources of L'Homme), and extensive interpretive notes. Also incorporates the French text of 1664 of L'Homme. Forward by I. B. Cohen.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  12.  28
    Philosophy of Science and the Pineal Gland.T. McMullen - 1979 - Philosophy 54 (209):380 - 384.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Simplicity and the Seat of the Soul.Stephen Voss - 1993 - In Essays on the philosophy and science of René Descartes. New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter discusses Descartes thoughts on the seat of the soul or that part of the body which the soul is directly and intimately united. Descartes explains the simplicity principle: If the soul is simple, or indivisible, it can interact directly with only one object at once, thus indivisible. For example, if an animal's heart is taken and cut into pieces, the soul's indivisibility means that the soul cannot act directly upon the dissected parts of the heart. (...) also consistently identified the pineal gland as the seat of the soul— partly because it was mobile, durable, protected from outside influence, and accessible to the nerves. It also explains that the mind is not affected by all parts of the body, but only the brain and one small part of the brain only where a certain part of the brain is affected while other parts are doing other things. This chapter finally reveals that the simplicity principle of Descartes will have strong difficulties in the final analysis in relation to the truth of God. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14. Leibniz on Emotions and the Human Body.Markku Roinila - 2011 - In Breger Herbert, Herbst Jürgen & Erdner Sven (eds.), Natur Und Subjekt (Ix. Internationaler Leibniz-Kongress Vorträge). Leibniz Geschellschaft.
    Descartes argued that the passions of the soul were immediately felt in the body, as the animal spirits, affected by the movement of the pineal gland, spread through the body. In Leibniz the effect of emotions in the body is a different question as he did not allow the direct interaction between the mind and the body, although maintaining a psychophysical parallelism between them. -/- In general, he avoids discussing emotions in bodily terms, saying that general inclinations, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  40
    Early modern emotion and the economy of scarcity.Daniel M. Gross - 2001 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 34 (4):308-321.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Rhetoric 34.4 (2001) 308-321 [Access article in PDF] Early Modern Emotion and the Economy of Scarcity 1 - [PDF] Daniel M. Gross Where do we get the idea that emotion is kind of excess, something housed in our nature aching for expression? In part, I argue, from The Passions of the Soul (1649), wherein Descartes proposed the reductive psychophysiology of emotion that informs both romantic expressivism (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  39
    In defense off the pineal gland.Robert Teghtsoonian - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):224-225.
  17.  44
    Mysterious Mixtures: Descartes on Mind and Body.Richard Davies - 2015 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 4 (1):47-78.
    As is well known, Descartes’ doctrine on the relations of mind and body involves at least the following two theses: the real distinction of mind and body is compatible with their substantial union; and the siting of the mind at the tip of the pineal gland is compatible with its presence throughout the body. Th is essay seeks to perform three main tasks. One is to suggest that, so far as Descartes is concerned, the doctrine that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  20
    The ageing pineal gland and its physiological consequences.Russel J. Reiter - 1992 - Bioessays 14 (3):169-175.
    Melatonin, the chief hormone of the pineal gland, is produced and secreted into the blood in a circadian manner with maximal production always occurring during the dark phase of the light dark cycle. Whereas the 24h rhythm of melatonin production is very robust in young animals including humans, the cycle deteriorates during ageing. The rhythm of melatonin can be substantially preserved during ageing by restricting the food intake of experimental animals; this same treatment increases the life span of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  65
    The self and its brain: A critical examination of The Face in the Mirror.Alain Morin - 2003 - Science and Consciousness Review 1.
    Where is the self located in the brain? This is a question that has intrigued philosophers and scientists for quite some time. Four centuries ago, the French philosopher René Descartes thought that the self resided in the pineal gland, a small structure centrally positioned in the lower brain.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Symposium: Descartes on perceptual cognition.John Sutton - 2000 - In Stephen Gaukroger, John Andrew Schuster & John Sutton (eds.), Descartes' Natural Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 524-527.
    Descartes, the textbooks say, divided human beings, or at least their minds, from the natural world. This is not just the consequence of metaphysical dualism, but of the concomitant indirect ‘ideas’ theory of perception. On the standard view, the soul must dimly infer the nature of the external world from the meagre, fragmentary, and often misleading input which is causally transmitted from objects through the nervous system to the brain and, ultimately, to the pineal gland. The metaphysical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  10
    Ana-materialism and the Pineal Eye: Becoming mouth-breast.Johnny Golding - 2012 - Philosophy of Photography 3 (1):99-120.
    Ana-materialism & the Pineal Eye provides a landmark interpretation of materialism, representation and the image using the Cartesian conceit of a pineal gland and its voracious sexually embedded appetites. Developing the argument via Bataille’s re-invention of the pineal gland as an all-seeing, all- devouring, eye, Golding borrows this move to envision a different analytic approach to digital forms of ‘matter’ and artificial forms of ‘life’. From her critical engagement with Bataille, Deleuze and Butler, Golding shows (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. A Hylomorphic Interpretation of Descartes’s Theory of Mind-Body Union.Justin Skirry - 2001 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 75:267-283.
    I contend that Descartes’s view of mind-body union is not a Platonic view in which the soul uses the body as its vehicle, but hylomorphic in that mind and body form a single unit. I argue that Descartes’s view is most like Ockham’s, and therefore Descartes is entitled to maintain a hylomorphic theory to the same extent that Ockham is. I argue further that the soul is the substantial form of human being, and that mind and body (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  16
    A Hylomorphic Interpretation of Descartes’s Theory of Mind-Body Union.Justin Skirry - 2001 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 75:267-283.
    I contend that Descartes’s view of mind-body union is not a Platonic view in which the soul uses the body as its vehicle, but hylomorphic in that mind and body form a single unit. I argue that Descartes’s view is most like Ockham’s, and therefore Descartes is entitled to maintain a hylomorphic theory to the same extent that Ockham is. I argue further that the soul is the substantial form of human being, and that mind and body (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  6
    Connect: how to find clarity and expand your consciousness with pineal gland meditation.Ilchi Lee - 2015 - Gilbert, AZ: Best Life Media.
    In "Connect: how to find clarity and expand your consciousness with pineal gland meditation", Lee shows how to connect to your authentic self through the pineal gland in your brain. Activate your pineal gland through the meditations rooted in an ancient Korean tradition that Iichi Lee describes in this book. You'll experience clarity instead of emotion, compassion rather than judgment, and wholeness in place of separation. This book will help you find the solutions you (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  53
    Understanding brain, mind and soul: Contributions from neurology and neurosurgery.S. K. Pandya - 2011 - Mens Sana Monographs 9 (1):129.
    Treatment of diseases of the brain by drugs or surgery necessitates an understanding of its structure and functions. The philosophical neurosurgeon soon encounters difficulties when localising the abstract concepts of mind and soul within the tangible 1300-gram organ containing 100 billion neurones. Hippocrates had focused attention on the brain as the seat of the mind. The tabula rasa postulated by Aristotle cannot be localised to a particular part of the brain with the confidence that we can localise spoken speech to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. A Revolutionary New Metaphysics, Based on Consciousness, and a Call to All Philosophers.Lorna Green - manuscript
    June 2022 A Revolutionary New Metaphysics, Based on Consciousness, and a Call to All Philosophers We are in a unique moment of our history unlike any previous moment ever. Virtually all human economies are based on the destruction of the Earth, and we are now at a place in our history where we can foresee if we continue on as we are, our own extinction. As I write, the planet is in deep trouble, heat, fires, great storms, and record flooding, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  25
    The distributed pineal gland.Martha J. Farah - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):209-209.
  28.  14
    The pineal family of aromatic amine N‐acetyltransferases.David C. Klein, Pierre Voisin & M. A. Aryan Namboodiri - 1985 - Bioessays 3 (5):217-220.
    The mammalian pineal gland contains two types of N‐acetyltransferases which act on aromatic amines. One type preferentially acetylates arylamines such as phenetidine and aniline, whereas the other preferentially acetylates arylalkylamines such as tryptamine and phenylethylamine. The two enzymes can be distinguished by (1) molecular size, (2) regulation, and (3) inactivation characteristics. Arylalkylamine N‐acetyltransferase is involved in the regulation of melatonin synthesis in the pineal gland. A specific function of pineal arylamine N‐acetyltransferase has not been established; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  6
    Naturally Supernatural.James Blackmon & Galen A. Foresman - 2013-09-05 - In Galen A. Foresman (ed.), Supernatural and Philosophy. Wiley. pp. 151–168.
    A ghost is a supernatural being that is typically described as capable of appearing to, speaking to, and even doing harm to a person. But it is also described as a being that you cannot touch or affect in the usual ways. Lots of things seem weird at first, but humans don't think of them as supernatural. It's easy to see how material things interact with each other. After all, they are, by their very essence as things filling space, things (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  98
    More About Hume's Debt to Spinoza.Wim Klever - 1993 - Hume Studies 19 (1):55-74.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:More About Hume's Debt to Spinoza Wim Klever In a recent contribution to the question of Hume's relationship to SpinozaIadvocatedamoreorlessSpinozisticinterpretationofthefirst bookofA Treatise ofHumanNature.1 Ofthe Understanding, sowasmy claim, is not only very close to De natura et origine mentis (Ethica, second part) as far as its main affirmations are concerned; the convergence ofexternal and internal evidence makes it also probable that there is a remarkable influence from the one's work (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  31.  29
    The Search for the New Pineal Gland Brain Life and Personhood.Mario Moussa & Thomas A. Shannon - 1992 - Hastings Center Report 22 (3):30-37.
  32.  32
    Morphology and histochemical characteristics human pineal gland acervuli during the aging.Svetlana Antić, Ivan Jovanović, Natalija Stefanović, Snežana Pavlović, Gorana Rančić & Slađana Ugrenović - 2004 - Facta Universitatis, Series: Linguistics and Literature 11 (2):63-67.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  38
    Experience and Justification: in Search of the Epistemic Pineal Gland.Hamid Vahid - 1994 - Philosophica 53 (1):91-104.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Sensation: Ideas as Brain Patterns.Desmond M. Clarke - 2003 - In Descartes’s Theory of Mind. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    The Cartesian explanation of sensation includes a speculative account of how external and internal phenomena transmit information to the brain by triggering flows of animal spirits from the pineal gland. The distinctive patterns in the flow of spirits are called ‘ideas’. There is no reason to think that ideas resemble the realities that cause them. All animals have sensations in this sense, and exhibit corresponding behaviour.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Anton Wilhelm Amo: The African Philosopher in 18th Europe.Dwight Lewis - 2018 - Blog of The American Philosophical Association.
    Anton Wilhelm Amo (c. 1700 – c. 1750) – born in West Africa, enslaved, and then gifted to the Duke of Braunschweig-Wolfenbüttel – became the first African to earn a Ph.D. in philosophy at a European university. He went on to teach philosophy at the Universities of Halle and Jena. On the 16th of April, 1734, at the University of Wittenberg, he defended his dissertation, De Humanae Mentis Apatheia (On the Impassivity of the Human Mind), in which Amo investigates the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  28
    Berkeley's Gland Tour into Speculative Fiction Part 2: Margaret Cavendish and Berkeley's Attitudes Towards Women.Clare Marie Moriarty & Lisa Walters - 2023 - Philosophy Compass 18 (4):e12909.
    In Part 1, we explored how Berkeley drew from Homeric literature and used literary techniques such as satire to challenge his “freethinking” philosophical opponents in “The Pineal Gland” story published in The Guardian in 1713. Echoing the grand tours Berkeley undertook in subsequent years, Part 1 and 2 both present a “gland tour” of some motivations, influences and legacies of Berkeley's text. In particular, Part 2, explores a line of literary influence beginning with Margaret Cavendish and extending (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  51
    The pineal gland up-dated.Virgil C. Aldrich - 1970 - Journal of Philosophy 67 (19):700-710.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  43
    The Pineal Gland.J. Z. Young - 1973 - Philosophy 48 (183):70 - 74.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  7
    The infinite mindfield: the quest to find the gateway to higher consciousness.Anthony Peake - 2013 - London: Watkins Publishing.
    For thousands of years voyagers of inner space - spiritual seekers, shamans and mystics - have returned from their inner travels reporting another level of reality that is more real than the one we inhabit in 'waking life'. Others have claimed that under the influence of mysterious substances, known as entheogens, the everyday human mind can be given glimpses of this multidimensional realm of existence that is usually hidden from us by our five basic senses. Using information from the leading (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. The self.John Gregg - manuscript
    One of the most certain truths in the world is Descartes' "I think, therefore I am". Descartes was so certain of the existence of some kind of essential _self_ that others have coined the term "Cartesian theater" to describe the sense that we all have of being the audience enjoying the rich play of our experiences. We tend to believe in an enduring self, independent of our individual percepts. Sometimes this virtual "self" in our mind, sitting in the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  26
    Enlightening the brain: Linking deep brain photoreception with behavior and physiology.António M. Fernandes, Kandice Fero, Wolfgang Driever & Harold A. Burgess - 2013 - Bioessays 35 (9):775-779.
    Vertebrates respond to light with more than just their eyes. In this article, we speculate on the intriguing possibility that a link remains between non‐visual opsins and neurohormonal systems that control neuronal circuit formation and activity in mammals. Historically, the retina and pineal gland were considered the only significant light‐sensing tissues in vertebrates. However over the last century, evidence has accumulated arguing that extra‐ocular tissues in vertebrates influence behavior through non‐image‐forming photoreception. One such class of extra‐ocular light detectors (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  26
    Enlightening the brain: Linking deep brain photoreception with behavior and physiology.António M. Fernandes, Kandice Fero, Wolfgang Driever & Harold A. Burgess - 2013 - Bioessays 35 (9):775-779.
    Vertebrates respond to light with more than just their eyes. In this article, we speculate on the intriguing possibility that a link remains between non‐visual opsins and neurohormonal systems that control neuronal circuit formation and activity in mammals. Historically, the retina and pineal gland were considered the only significant light‐sensing tissues in vertebrates. However over the last century, evidence has accumulated arguing that extra‐ocular tissues in vertebrates influence behavior through non‐image‐forming photoreception. One such class of extra‐ocular light detectors (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  64
    Descartes and the Buddha—a rapprochement?Galen Strawson - 2023 - In Christian Coseru (ed.), Reasons and Empty Persons: Mind, Metaphysics, and Morality: Essays in Honor of Mark Siderits. Springer. pp. 63-86.
    Descartes’s conception of the mind is nothing like what most people suppose. I believe it may have interesting affinities with certain Asian—even Buddhist!—conceptions of the mind. I’m not qualified to comment on the Asian side, so I’m going to describe what I take to be his position and invite others to judge.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  37
    Descartes and the puzzle of sensory representation (review).Richard A. Watson - 2010 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (4):526-527.
    Descartes and the Puzzle of Sensory Representation is an intensely polemical attack on many recent expositions of sensory representation in Descartes, and a defense of De Rosa’s own Descriptive-Causal Account of Sensory Representation. For Descartes, she says, there are two kinds of ideas, sensible and intelligible, both of which have presentational and referential content. The presentational content of sensible ideas consists of touches, tastes, sounds, odors, and colored visual images that are obscure and confused, in that there (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  33
    Descartes and the Aristotelian Framework of Sensory Perception1.Joseph W. Hwang - 2011 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 35 (1):111-148.
    The primary aim of this paper is to provide a new account of Descartes’s positive philosophical view on sensory perception, and to do so in a way that will establish a hitherto unnoticed continuity between his thought and that of his scholastic Aristotelian predecessors on the topic of sensory perception. I will argue that the basic framework of the scholastic Aristotelian view on sensory perception (as traditionally understood) is operative within Descartes's own view, and then reveal some insights (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. N, N-DIMETHYLTRYPTAMINE AND BIOLOGICAL REDUCTIVE ACCOUNTS FOR RELIGIOUS AND SPIRITUAL EXPERIENCES.Shaun Smith - forthcoming - Liberty University Digital Commons.
    There is unquestionably a plethora of details and mysteries regarding the mind and the body. However, with the advent of psychopharmacology (the study of how psychedelics inform or alter brain states) there are more issues at hand. Do psychedelics allow us to access deeper areas of our consciousness? Are we having a spiritual experience under the influence of psychedelics? Dr. Rick Strassman does not want to continue asking these rather conspiratorial-like questions. Instead, Dr. Strassman believes that there is one special, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  42
    Descartes and the Passionate Mind.Deborah J. Brown - 2006 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Descartes is often accused of having fragmented the human being into two independent substances, mind and body, with no clear strategy for explaining the apparent unity of human experience. Deborah Brown argues that, contrary to this view, Descartes did in fact have a conception of a single, integrated human being, and that in his view this conception is crucial to the success of human beings as rational and moral agents and as practitioners of science. The passions are pivotal (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  48.  44
    Descartes and the Bologna affair.Gideon Manning - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Science 47 (1):1-13.
    Descartes is well known as a mathematician and natural philosopher. However, none of Descartes's biographers has described the invitation he received in 1633 to fill a chair in theoretical medicine at the University of Bologna, or the fact that he was already sufficiently known and respected for his medical knowledge that the invitation came four years before his first publication. In this note I authenticate and contextualize this event, which I refer to as the ‘Bologna affair’. I transcribe (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  49.  29
    Descartes and the Dutch: Early Reactions to Cartesian Philosophy, 1637-1650.Theo Verbeek - 1992 - Southern Illinois University Press.
    Theo Verbeek provides the first book-length examination of the initial reception of Descartes’s written works. Drawing on his research of primary materials written in Dutch and Latin and found in libraries all over Europe, even including the Soviet Union, Theo Verbeek opens a period of Descartes’s life and of the development of Cartesian philosophy that has been virtually closed since Descartes’s death. Verbeek’s aim is to provide as complete a picture as possible of the discussions that accompanied (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  50. Descartes and the Phenomenological Tradition.Wayne M. Martin - 2008 - In Martin Wayne (ed.).
    The spectre of Descartes figured as a perpetual presence in much of twentieth century philosophy, but nearly always as an emblem for positions to be avoided. Cartesian foundationalism in epistemology, the ontological dualism of mind and body, the associated conception of the mind as a substance, and as a “thing that thinks” – all these have figured in recent philosophy as positions to be refuted or simply renounced, the absurda in one or another reductio argument. But for one prominent (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000