Order:
Disambiguations
Kimberley Brownlee [54]Timothy L. Brownlee [9]Timothy Brownlee [8]Jo Brownlee [5]
Joanne Brownlee [3]Joanne M. Brownlee [3]Jo Lunn Brownlee [2]W. Elliot Brownlee [2]

Not all matches are shown. Search with initial or firstname to single out others.

  1. Conscience and Conviction: The Case for Civil Disobedience.Kimberley Brownlee - 2012 - Oxford University Press UK.
    Oxford Legal Philosophy publishes the best new work in philosophically-oriented legal theory. It commissions and solicits monographs in all branches of the subject, including works on philosophical issues in all areas of public and private law, and in the national, transnational, and international realms; studies of the nature of law, legal institutions, and legal reasoning; treatments of problems in political morality as they bear on law; and explorations in the nature and development of legal philosophy itself. The series represents diverse (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  2. Civil disobedience.Kimberley Brownlee & Candice Delmas - 2021 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  3.  34
    Being Sure of Each Other: An Essay on Social Rights and Freedoms.Kimberley Brownlee - 2020 - Oxford University Press.
    Brownlee rethinks human rights theory to reflect the fact that we are deeply social creatures. Our core social needs, for meaningful social inclusion, are more important than, and essential to, our civil, political, and economic needs. This grounds a right against social deprivation and a right to the resources to sustain other people.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  4. What a Home Does.David Jenkins & Kimberley Brownlee - 2022 - Law and Philosophy 41 (4):441-468.
    Analytic philosophy has largely neglected the topic of homelessness. The few notable exceptions, including work by Jeremy Waldron and Christopher Essert, focus on our interests in shelter, housing, and property rights, but ignore the key social functions that a home performs as a place in which we are welcomed, accepted, and respected. This paper identifies a ladder of home-related concepts which begins with the minimal notion of temporary shelter, then moves to persistent shelter and housing, and finally to the rich (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5. A Human Right Against Social Deprivation.Kimberley Brownlee - 2013 - Philosophical Quarterly 63 (251):199-222.
    Human rights debates neglect social rights. This paper defends one fundamentally important, but largely unacknowledged social human right. The right is both a condition for and a constitutive part of a minimally decent human life. Indeed, protection of this right is necessary to secure many less controversial human rights. The right in question is the human right against social deprivation. In this context, ‘social deprivation’ refers not to poverty, but to genuine, interpersonal, social deprivation as a persisting lack of minimally (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  6. The civil disobedience of Edward Snowden: A reply to William Scheuerman.Kimberley Brownlee - 2016 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 42 (10):965-970.
    This article responds to William Scheuerman’s analysis of Edward Snowden as someone whose acts fit within John Rawls’ account of civil disobedience understood as a public, non-violent, conscientious breach of law performed with overall fidelity to law and a willingness to accept punishment. It rejects the narrow Rawlsian notion in favour of a broader notion of civil disobedience understood as a constrained, conscientious and communicative breach of law that demonstrates opposition to law or policy and a desire for lasting change. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  7. Ethical Dilemmas of Sociability.Kimberley Brownlee - 2016 - Utilitas 28 (1):54-72.
    There is a tension between our need for associative control and our need for social connections. This tension creates ethical dilemmas that we can call each-we dilemmas of sociability. To resolve these dilemmas, we must prioritize either negative moral rights to dissociate or positive moral rights to social inclusion. This article shows that we must prioritize positive social rights. This has implications both for personal morality and for political theory. As persons, we must attend to each other's basic social needs. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  8.  45
    Two Tales of Civil Disobedience: A Reply to David Lefkowitz.Kimberley Brownlee - 2018 - Res Publica 24 (3):291-296.
  9. Features of a paradigm case of civil disobedience.Kimberley Brownlee - 2004 - Res Publica 10 (4):337-351.
    The purpose of this paper is not to define civil disobedience, but to identify a paradigm case of civil disobedience and the features exemplified in it. After noting the benefits of this methodological approach, the paper proceeds with an examination of two key, interconnected features: conscientiousness and communication. First, a link is made between the conscientious aspect of civil disobedience and moral consistency; a civil disobedient demonstrates a conscientious commitment to certain values through her willingness to condemn, and to dissociate (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  10.  95
    I- The Lonely Heart Breaks: On the Right to Be a Social Contributor.Kimberley Brownlee - 2016 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 90 (1):27-48.
    This paper uncovers a distinctively social type of injustice that lies in the kinds of wrongs we can do to each other specifically as social beings. In this paper, social injustice is not principally about unfair distributions of socio-economic goods among citizens. Instead, it is about the ways we can violate each other’s fundamental rights to lead socially integrated lives in close proximity and relationship with other people. This paper homes in on a particular type of social injustice, which we (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  11.  47
    Acting Defensively for the Sake of Our Attacker.Kimberley Brownlee - 2019 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 16 (2):105-130.
    Despite worries about paternalism, when we are unjustifiably attacked, we are morally warranted, and sometimes required, to act in self-defense for the sake of our attacker to prevent him from committing this morally defiling act. Similarly, when a third party is unjustifiably attacked and we can assist without undue cost, we are morally warranted, and sometimes required, to act in third-party defense for the sake of the attacker as well as the victim, to prevent the attacker from committing this morally (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12. The communicative aspects of civil disobedience and lawful punishment.Kimberley Brownlee - 2007 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 1 (2):179-192.
    A parallel may be drawn between the communicative aspect of civil disobedience and the communicative aspect of lawful punishment by the state. In punishing an offender, the state seeks to communicate both its condemnation of the crime committed and its desire for repentance and reformation on the part of the offender. Similarly, in civilly disobeying the law, a disobedient seeks to convey both her condemnation of a certain law or policy and her desire for recognition that a lasting change in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  13. Moral aspirations and ideals.Kimberley Brownlee - 2010 - Utilitas 22 (3):241-257.
    My aim is to vindicate two distinct and important moral categories – ideals and aspirations – which have received modest, and sometimes negative, attention in recent normative debates. An ideal is a conception of perfection or model of excellence around which we can shape our thoughts and actions. An aspiration, by contrast, is an attitudinal position of steadfast commitment to, striving for, or deep desire or longing for, an ideal. I locate these two concepts in relation to more familiar moral (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14. Disability and Disadvantage.Kimberley Brownlee & Adam Cureton (eds.) - 2009 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Introduction ADAM CURETON AND KIMBERLEY BROWNLEE Disability and disadvantage are interrelated topics that raise important and sometimes overlooked issues in ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  15. Penalizing public disobedience.Kimberley Brownlee - 2008 - Ethics 118 (4):711-716.
  16. Social deprivation and criminal justice.Kimberley Brownlee - 2012 - In Francois Tanguay-Renaud & James Stribopoulos (eds.), Rethinking Criminal Law Theory: New Canadian Perspectives in the Philosophy of Domestic, Transnational, and International Criminal Law. Hart Publishing.
    This article challenges the use of social deprivation as a punishment, and offers a preliminary examination of the human rights implications of exile and solitary confinement. The article considers whether a human right against coercive social deprivation is conceptually redundant, as there are recognised rights against torture, extremely cruel, inhumane, or degrading treatment as well as rights to basic health care, education, and security, which might encompass what this right protects. The article argues that the right is not conceptually redundant, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17. Reasons and ideals.Kimberley Brownlee - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 151 (3):433-444.
    This paper contributes to the debate on whether we can have reason to do what we are unable to do. I take as my starting point two papers recently published in Philosophical Studies , by Bart Streumer and Ulrike Heuer, which defend the two dominant opposing positions on this issue. Briefly, whereas Streumer argues that we cannot have reason to do what we are unable to do, Heuer argues that we can have reason to do what we are unable to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  18.  26
    On the Ethics of Interacting.Kimberley Brownlee - forthcoming - Journal of Applied Philosophy.
    Ordinary interactions are the primary vehicle through which we show respect, give social pleasure, and grease the wheels of healthy sociality. When we do an interactional wrong to someone, we not only convey disrespect by disregarding their interactional needs, but also cause them social pain and erode healthy social relations. Interactional ethics – the study of the ethics of interacting – concerns both our conduct within our interactions and our broader interactional style. The existing philosophical literature in this area has (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  25
    Personal epistemology in pre-service teachers: belief changes throughout a teacher education course.Sue Walker, Joanne M. Brownlee, Beryl E. Exley, Annette Woods & Chrystal Whiteford - 2011 - In Jo Brownlee, Gregory J. Schraw & Donna Berthelsen (eds.), Personal epistemology and teacher education. New York: Routledge.
  20.  37
    Can the law help us to be moral?Kimberley Brownlee & Richard Child - 2018 - Jurisprudence 9 (1):31-46.
    The moral value of law can take many forms. It is instrumentally valuable when it coordinates interaction, provides moral advice and leadership, models the virtues, and motivates us to be moral. It is intrinsically valuable when it constitutes the collective moral conscience of citizens, embodies an ideal form of communal life, and expresses the moral integrity of the community. We analyse all of these potential values of law and assess their moral significance. In doing so, we are careful to distinguish (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  20
    The Offender's Part in the Dialogue.Kimberley Brownlee - 2011 - In Rowan Cruft, Matthew H. Kramer & Mark R. Reiff (eds.), Crime, punishment, and responsibility: the jurisprudence of Antony Duff. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 54.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  56
    Personal epistemology and teacher education.Jo Brownlee, Gregory J. Schraw & Donna Berthelsen (eds.) - 2011 - New York: Routledge.
    This edited volume examines the role of personal epistemology in teaching across early childhood, primary, secondary and tertiary contexts, and the implications for teacher education, incorporating the most up-to-date research and ...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  23.  17
    Freedom of Association: It's Not What You Think.Kimberley Brownlee - 2015 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 35 (2):267-282.
    This article shows that associative freedom is not what we tend to think it is. Contrary to standard liberal thinking, it is neither a general moral permission to choose the society most acceptable to us nor a content-insensitive claim-right akin to the other personal freedoms with which it is usually lumped such as freedom of expression and freedom of religion. It is at most (i) a highly restricted moral permission to associate subject to constraints of consent, necessity and burdensomeness; (ii) (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  12
    Freedom of Association.Kimberley Brownlee - 2016 - In Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Kimberley Brownlee & David Coady (eds.), A Companion to Applied Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley. pp. 356–369.
    This chapter explores the contours of our freedoms to enter into and leave particular associations with particular people. The chapter highlights the fact that often our associations with each other are morally complex and, indeed, morally wrong. This moral complexity stems partly from the fact that associations are necessarily intersubjective: they affect the social needs, claims, and freedoms of at least two people. When our associations are morally wrong, we must determine whether they can be protected nonetheless by our sphere (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25. Punishment.Christopher Bennett & Kimberley Brownlee - 2020 - In John Tasioulas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law. New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  34
    Alienation and Recognition in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit.Timothy L. Brownlee - 2015 - Philosophical Forum 46 (4):377-396.
    This article considers the contribution that Hegel’s concept of “alienation” (Entfremdung) makes to his theory of reciprocal intersubjective recognition in the Phenomenology of Spirit. I show that Hegel presents a powerful criticism of what I call the “automatic” model of recognition—I treat Stephen Darwall’s conception of reciprocal recognition as exemplary—where individuals merit recognition from others in virtue of some generic self-standing trait, and recognition requires responding appropriately to that feature. This model of recognition is alienating since it entails understanding the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  54
    What’s virtuous about the law?Kimberley Brownlee - 2015 - Legal Theory 21 (1):1-17.
    Debates about our moral relation to the law typically focus on the moral force of law. Often, the question asked is: Do we have a moral duty to follow the law? Recently, that question has been given a virtue-ethical formulation: Is there a virtue in abiding by the law? This paper considers our moral relation to the law in terms of virtue but focuses on a different question from the traditional ones. The question here is: Can the law model virtue (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  8
    Teaching for Active Citizenship: Research Insights From the Fields of Teaching Moral Values and Personal Epistemology in Early Years Classrooms.Joanne Lunn Brownlee, Susan Walker, Eva Johansson & Laura Scholes - 2016 - Routledge.
    There is strong social and political interest in active citizenship and values in education internationally. Active citizenship requires children to experience and internalize moral values for human rights, developing their own opinions and moral responsibility. While investment in young children is recognised as an important factor in the development of citizenship for a cohesive society, less is known about how early years teachers can encourage this in the classroom. This book will present new directions on how teachers can promote children's (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  26
    The Human Right to Adequate Social Inclusion: A Reply to Critics.Kimberley Brownlee - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (2):491-506.
    This Reply offers my answers to Cheshire Calhoun’s, Elizabeth Brake’s, and Monika Betzler’s wonderful contributions to the Criminal Law and Philosophy symposium on Being Sure of Each Other (2020). Their contributions focus respectively on the conceptual and normative foundations of my defence of our human rights to have adequate social inclusion, the harms that might flow from recognising such rights as human rights, and the impact such rights can have on our most intimate relations. My replies aim both to clarify (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  47
    A Network Approach to Compliance: A Complexity Science Understanding of How Rules Shape Behavior.Malouke Esra Kuiper, Monique Chambon, Anne Leonore de Bruijn, Chris Reinders Folmer, Elke Hindina Olthuis, Megan Brownlee, Emmeke Barbara Kooistra, Adam Fine, Frenk van Harreveld, Gabriela Lunansky & Benjamin van Rooij - 2023 - Journal of Business Ethics 184 (2):479-504.
    To understand how compliance develops both in everyday and corporate environments, it is crucial to understand how different mechanisms work together to shape individuals’ (non)compliant behavior. Existing compliance studies typically focus on a subset of theories (i.e., rational choice theories, social theories, legitimacy theories, capacity theories, and opportunity theories) to understand how key variables from one or several of these theories shape individual compliance. The present study provides a first integrated understanding of compliance, rooted in complexity science, in which key (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Normative Principles and Practical Ethics: A Response to O’Neill.Kimberley Brownlee - 2009 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 26 (3):231-237.
    abstract This article briefly examines Onora O'Neill's account of the relation between normative principles and practical ethical problems with an eye to suggesting that philosophers of practical ethics have reason to adopt fairly high moral ambitions to be edifying and instructive both as educators and as advisors on public policy debates.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  50
    Reply to Critics.Kimberley Brownlee - 2016 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (4):721-739.
    This article responds to the four contributors to the book symposium on Conscience and Conviction: The Case for Civil Disobedience. Those four contributors are Thomas Hill Jr, David Lefkowitz, William Smith, and Daniel Weinstock. Hill examines the concepts of conviction and conscience ; Smith discusses conviction and then analyses the right to civil disobedience and my humanistic arguments for it ; Weinstock explores democratic challenges for civil disobedience ; and Lefkowitz assesses the merits of a legal demands-of-conviction excuse for civil (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  25
    Ethicality and the Movement of Recognition in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit in advance.Timothy L. Brownlee - forthcoming - International Philosophical Quarterly.
    In this paper I consider the contribution that Hegel’s discussion of ethicality makes to his account of recognition in the Phenomenology of Spirit. While the famous relation of lord and bondsman might prompt us to think of all failures of recognition as failures of reciprocity, Hegel’s account of ethicality shows that it is possible for forms of social life to be structured so that no one is recognized. This failure of recognition is unique since its source does not lie in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Do we have a human right to the political determinants of health?Kimberley Brownlee - 2015 - In Rowan Cruft, S. Matthew Liao & Massimo Renzo (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  18
    On Gardner on Law in General.Kimberley Brownlee - 2015 - Jurisprudence 6 (3):567-573.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  40
    The Competent Judge Problem.Kimberley Brownlee - 2015 - Ratio 29 (3):312-326.
    We face an epistemic problem in competently judging some types of experience. The problem arises when an experience either defies our efforts to assess its quality, such as a traumatic event, or compromises our abilities to assess quality in general, such as starvation. In the latter type of case, the competent judge problem is actually a paradox since the experience undermines our competence to judge at the same time that it gives us competence to judge it against other experiences. The (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  5
    Patient Decision Aids: A Case for Certification at the National Level in the United States.Glyn Elwyn, John W. Williams, Robert J. Volk, Dawn Stacey, Shannon Brownlee & Urbashi Poddar - 2015 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 26 (4):306-311.
    Patient decision aids enable patients to be better informed about the potential benefits and harms of their healthcare options. Certification of patient decision aids at the national level in the United States is a critical step towards responsible governance—primarily as a quality measure that increases patients’ safety, as mandated in the U.S. Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act (PPACA). Certification would provide a verification process to identify conflicts of interest that may otherwise bias the scientific evidence presented in decision aids. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  2
    Civil Disobedience.Kimberley Brownlee - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  24
    Value for the future and preventive health behavior.Gretchen B. Chapman, Noel T. Brewer, Elliot J. Coups, Susan Brownlee, Howard Leventhal & Elaine A. Levanthal - 2001 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 7 (3):235.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  17
    Are There Any Right or Wrong Answers in Teaching Philosophy?Gordon Tait, Clare O'Farrell, Sarah Davey Chesters, Joanne Brownlee, Rebecca Spooner-Lane & Elizabeth Curtis - 2012 - Teaching Philosophy 35 (4):367-381.
    This article assesses undergraduate teaching students’ assertion that there are no right and wrong answers in teaching philosophy. When asked questions about their experiences of philosophy in the classroom for primary children, their unanimous declaration that teaching philosophy has ‘no right and wrong answers’ is critically examined across the three sub-disciplinary areas to which they were generally referring, namely, pedagogy, ethics, and epistemology. From a pedagogical point of view, it is argued that some teach­ing approaches may indeed be more effective (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  30
    " Are there any right or wrong answers in teaching philosophy": ethics, epistemology, and philosophy in the classroom.Gordon Tait, Clare D. O'Farrell, Sarah Davey Chesters, Joanne M. Brownlee, Rebecca S. Spooner-Lane & Elizabeth M. Curtis - 2012 - Teaching Philosophy 35 (4).
  42.  21
    Conscience, conviction, and moral autonomy in Fichte’s ethics.Timothy L. Brownlee - 2022 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 30 (4):626-645.
    According to Kant, a certain kind of knowledge is essential to the achievement of moral autonomy. In order for an action to be obligatory, it must be possible for me to know not only what I have a...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. An Examination of Moral Theory and Personal Relationships.Kimberley Brownlee - 2001 - Prolegomena.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  36
    Being Social: The Philosophy of Social Human Rights.Kimberley Brownlee, Adam Neal & David Jenkins (eds.) - 2022 - Oxford University Press.
    This pioneering collection of original essays aims to remedy the neglect of social needs and rights in human rights theory and practice by exploring the social dimensions of the human-rights minimum.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  83
    Conscience and Religion in Hegel's Later Political Philosophy.Timothy Brownlee - 2011 - The Owl of Minerva 43 (1/2):41-73.
    In recent years, commentators have devoted increasing attention to Hegel’s conception of conscience. Prominent interpreters like Frederick Neuhouser have even argued that many points of contact can be found between Hegel’s conceptions of conscience and moral subjectivity and historical and contemporary liberalism. In this paper, I offer an interpretation of an under-examined 1830 addition to the Philosophy of Spirit concerning the relation between religion and the state which proves particularly resistant to the kind of liberal interpretation of conscience which Neuhouser (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  71
    Distant Strangers: Ethics, Psychology, and Global Poverty.Kimberley Brownlee - 2016 - Philosophical Quarterly 66 (262):172–175.
  47.  46
    Digging Up, Dismantling, and Redesigning the Criminal Law.Kimberley Brownlee - 2013 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 7 (1):169-178.
    The criminal law raises wonderfully thorny foundational questions. Some of these questions are conceptual: What is a plausible conception of crime ? What is a plausible conception of criminal law ? Some of these questions are genealogical: What are the historical and genealogical roots of the criminal law in a particular jurisdiction? Other questions are evaluative: What are the political and moral values on which a given conception of criminal law depends? What kind of rational reconstruction, if any, could the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  23
    Ethicality and the Movement of Recognition in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit.Timothy L. Brownlee - 2016 - International Philosophical Quarterly 56 (2):187-201.
    In this paper I consider the contribution that Hegel’s discussion of ethicality makes to his account of recognition in the Phenomenology of Spirit. While the famous relation of lord and bondsman might prompt us to think of all failures of recognition as failures of reciprocity, Hegel’s account of ethicality shows that it is possible for forms of social life to be structured so that no one is recognized. This failure of recognition is unique since its source does not lie in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  26
    Hegel’s Defense of Toleration.Timothy Brownlee - 2012 - In Angelica Nuzzo (ed.), Hegel on Religion and Politics. State University of New York Press. pp. 79-98.
  50.  6
    Hegel’s Defense of Toleration.Timothy Brownlee - 2013 - Proceedings of the Hegel Society of America 21:79-98.
1 — 50 / 97