Results for 'Bernard Voutat'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  13
    L’indignation est-elle un ressort de la scandalisation? Le « scandale des fiches » en Suisse.Rayner Hervé, Thétaz Fabien & Voutat Bernard - forthcoming - Éthique Publique.
    À partir d’une étude de cas portant sur le « scandale des fiches », qui mit en cause les pratiques de surveillance de la police politique suisse, nous montrons que, contrairement à ce qu’affirment nombre de travaux, l’ampleur du scandale ne peut-être déduite de celle de l’indignation pas plus que cette dernière ne peut être rapportée à la gravité supposée de transgressions. Un scandale n’émerge que si des acteurs, à partir de leur évaluation de la situation et de leurs perceptions (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Must a concern for the environment be centred on human beings.Bernard Williams - 1995 - In Making Sense of Humanity and Other Philosophical Papers. Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  3. Saint-Just's illusion.Bernard Williams - 1995 - In Making Sense of Humanity: And Other Philosophical Papers 1982–1993. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 135--152.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  4. How Free Does the Free Will Need To Be?Bernard Williams - 1995 - In Making Sense of Humanity: And Other Philosophical Papers 1982–1993. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  5. Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline.Bernard Williams - 2000 - Philosophy 75 (4):477-496.
    Philosophy should not try to assimilate itself to the aims of the sciences. Scientism stems from the false assumption that a representation of the world minimally based on local perspectives is what best serves self-understanding. Philosophy must concern itself with the history of our conceptions, and we must overcome the need to think that this history should ideally be vindicatory. There is no basic conflict between arguing within the framework of our ideas, reflectively making better sense of them, and understanding (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  6.  19
    Degrees That Are Not Degrees of Categoricity.Bernard Anderson & Barbara Csima - 2016 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (3):389-398.
    A computable structure $\mathcal {A}$ is $\mathbf {x}$-computably categorical for some Turing degree $\mathbf {x}$ if for every computable structure $\mathcal {B}\cong\mathcal {A}$ there is an isomorphism $f:\mathcal {B}\to\mathcal {A}$ with $f\leq_{T}\mathbf {x}$. A degree $\mathbf {x}$ is a degree of categoricity if there is a computable structure $\mathcal {A}$ such that $\mathcal {A}$ is $\mathbf {x}$-computably categorical, and for all $\mathbf {y}$, if $\mathcal {A}$ is $\mathbf {y}$-computably categorical, then $\mathbf {x}\leq_{T}\mathbf {y}$. We construct a $\Sigma^{0}_{2}$ set whose degree (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7.  62
    Rhetoric and Public Reasoning.Bernard Yack - 2006 - Political Theory 34 (4):417-438.
    This essay asks why Aristotle, certainly no friend to unlimited democracy, seems so much more comfortable with unconstrained rhetoric in political deliberation than current defenders of deliberative democracy. It answers this question by reconstructing and defending a distinctly Aristotelian understanding of political deliberation, one that can be pieced together out of a series of separate arguments made in the Rhetoric, the Politics, and the Nicomachean Ethics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  8. The myth of the civic nation.Bernard Yack - 1996 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 10 (2):193-211.
    Abstract The idea of a purely civic nationalism has attracted Western scholars, most of whom rightly disdain the myths that sustain ethnonationalist theories of political community. Civic nationalism is particularly attractive to many Americans, whose peculiar national heritage encourages the delusion that their mutual association is based solely on consciously chosen principles. But this idea misrepresents political reality as surely as the ethnonationalist myths it is designed to combat. And propagating a new political myth is an especially inappropriate way of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  9.  23
    Taking Freedom Seriously: Kantian Ethics versus the Ethics of Kant.Bernard Yack - 2023 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 35 (3):233-246.
    No understanding of morality has more zealous or influential defenders among academic philosophers than Kant’s. Yet as Michael Rosen demonstrates in The Shadow of God, there is a sense in which Kant’s critics take his conception of freedom more seriously nowadays than his defenders. As a result, contemporary versions of “Kantian ethics” often end up challenging what Rosen calls “the ethics of Kant,” not just the claims of rival moral theories. Rosen supports this surprising conclusion with some powerful arguments, showing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10. Hylomorphism.Bernard Williams - 1986 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 4:189-99.
  11.  54
    The Trick of the Disappearing Goal.Bernard Suits - 1989 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 16 (1):1-12.
  12.  98
    Who Needs Ethical Knowledge?Bernard Williams - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 35:213-222.
    An old question, still much discussed in moral philosophy, is whether there is any ethical knowledge. It is closely related, by simple etymology, to the question of cognitivism in ethics. Despite the fact that the terms ‘cognitivism’ and ‘objectivism’ seem sometimes to be used interchangeably, I take it that the question whether there can be ethical knowledge is not the same as the question whether ethical outlooks can be objective. A sufficient reason for this is that an ethical outlook might (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  13. Ethics and the Fabric of the World.Bernard Williams - 1998 - In James Rachels (ed.), Ethical theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  14.  62
    Truth, Politics, and Self-Deception.Bernard Williams - forthcoming - Social Research: An International Quarterly.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15.  29
    On the Mathematical Method and Correspondence with Exner: Translated by Paul Rusnock and Rolf George.Bernard Bolzano (ed.) - 2004 - BRILL.
    The Prague Philosopher Bernard Bolzano (1781-1848) has long been admired for his groundbreaking work in mathematics: his rigorous proofs of fundamental theorems in analysis, his construction of a continuous, nowhere-differentiable function, his investigations of the infinite, and his anticipations of Cantor's set theory. He made equally outstanding contributions in philosophy, most notably in logic and methodology. One of the greatest mathematician-philosophers since Leibniz, Bolzano is now widely recognised as a major figure of nineteenth-century philosophy. Praised by Husserl as “one (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  16. Ethics.Bernard Williams - 1995 - In A. C. Grayling (ed.), Philosophy: a guide through the subject. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  17. The Analogy of City and Soul in Plato's Republic.Bernard Williams - 1999 - In Gail Fine (ed.), Plato, Volume 2: Ethics, Politics, Religious and the Soul. Oxford University Press. pp. 255-264.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  17
    Revisiting The Longing for Total Revolution.Bernard Yack - 2021 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 33 (2):248-264.
    ABSTRACT This paper reconsiders the arguments of my book, The Longing for Total Revolution, in response to the thoughtful analyses collected in this symposium. It restates the book’s main genealogical and critical arguments about the philosophical sources of uniquely modern forms of social discontent, while distinguishing those arguments from recent attempts to uncover the deeper, theological sources of discontent. It focuses, in particular, on the role played in modern social discontent by the group of thinkers I describe as the “Kantian (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. A mistrustful animal.Bernard Williams - 2009 - In Alex Voorhoeve (ed.), Conversations on ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  20. .Bernard Williams - 1973 - In Deciding to believe. Cambridge [Eng.]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 136-151.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  21. Plato.Bernard Williams - 1997 - New York: Routledge.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  22.  6
    Antigone in Hertfordshire: Moral Conflict and Moral Pluralism in Forster’s Howards End.Bernard Yack - 2020 - Res Publica 26 (4):489-504.
    This paper uses E. M. Forster’s novel Howards End to help articulate what I describe as a moral pluralist approach to moral conflict. Moral pluralism, I argue here, represents a way of responding to the moral conflicts we encounter in our lives, rather than the mere acknowledgment of their inevitability, as suggested by value pluralists like Isaiah Berlin. The tragic view of moral conflict epitomized by Sophocles’ Antigone and endorsed by most theories of value pluralism, tells us that we must (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  97
    Can Bayes' Rule be Justified by Cognitive Rationality Principles?Bernard Walliser & Denis Zwirn - 2002 - Theory and Decision 53 (2):95-135.
    The justification of Bayes' rule by cognitive rationality principles is undertaken by extending the propositional axiom systems usually proposed in two contexts of belief change: revising and updating. Probabilistic belief change axioms are introduced, either by direct transcription of the set-theoretic ones, or in a stronger way but nevertheless in the spirit of the underlying propositional principles. Weak revising axioms are shown to be satisfied by a General Conditioning rule, extending Bayes' rule but also compatible with others, and weak updating (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  24.  16
    A dictionary of scholastic philosophy.Bernard J. Wuellner - 1956 - Milwaukee,: Bruce Pub. Co..
    The scholastic philosopher is interested in definition for a different reason than the lexicographer and linguist. The philosopher is trying to learn things. Fe defines, after investigating reality, in an attempt to describe reality clearly and to sum up some aspect of his understanding of reality. Hence, we find our scholastic philosophers adopting as a main feature of their method this insistence on defining, on precise and detailed explanation of their definitions, and on proving that their definitions da correctly express (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25.  14
    A Bounded Jump for the Bounded Turing Degrees.Bernard Anderson & Barbara Csima - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (2):245-264.
    We define the bounded jump of $A$ by $A^{b}=\{x\in \omega \mid \exists i\leq x[\varphi_{i}\downarrow \wedge\Phi_{x}^{A\upharpoonright \!\!\!\upharpoonright \varphi_{i}}\downarrow ]\}$ and let $A^{nb}$ denote the $n$th bounded jump. We demonstrate several properties of the bounded jump, including the fact that it is strictly increasing and order-preserving on the bounded Turing degrees. We show that the bounded jump is related to the Ershov hierarchy. Indeed, for $n\geq2$ we have $X\leq_{bT}\emptyset ^{nb}\iff X$ is $\omega^{n}$-c.e. $\iff X\leq_{1}\emptyset ^{nb}$, extending the classical result that $X\leq_{bT}\emptyset '\iff (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26. Aristotle on the good: A formal sketch.Bernard A. O. Williams - 1962 - Philosophical Quarterly 12 (49):289-296.
  27.  85
    Aristotle on the Function of Man: Fallacies, Heresies and Other Entertainments.Bernard Suits - 1974 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (1):23 - 40.
    It has long been believed that if man had a special function appropriate to him, and that if we could discover what it was, then we would be in a perfect position to solve all of the basic problems of ethics. For if we were, for example, shovels, and knew ourselves to be shovels, then we would also know that to spend our lives in digging would best serve our fundamental interests, realize our highest aspirations, and be in every respect (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28. Les classifications des sciences mathématiques en Grèce ancienne.Bernard Vitrac - 2005 - Archives de Philosophie 2 (2):269-301.
    Cet article étudie les principales classifications grecques anciennes des sciences mathématiques. Je souligne le rôle joué par Platon dans cette topique.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  29. 12 Truth and Truthfulness.Bernard Williams - 2007 - In Julian Baggini & Jeremy Stangroom (eds.), What More Philosophers Think. Continuum.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30.  63
    The Costs of Procreation.Bernard G. Prusak - 2011 - Journal of Social Philosophy 42 (1):61-75.
  31.  11
    Dictionary of scholastic philosophy.Bernard J. Wuellner - 1956 - Milwaukee,: Bruce Pub. Co..
    The scholastic philosopher is interested in definition for a different reason than the lexicographer and linguist. The philosopher is trying to learn things. Fe defines, after investigating reality, in an attempt to describe reality clearly and to sum up some aspect of his understanding of reality. Hence, we find our scholastic philosophers adopting as a main feature of their method this insistence on defining, on precise and detailed explanation of their definitions, and on proving that their definitions da correctly express (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32. Abductive logics in a belief revision framework.Bernard Walliser, Denis Zwirn & Hervé Zwirn - 2004 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 14 (1):87-117.
    Abduction was first introduced in the epistemological context of scientific discovery. It was more recently analyzed in artificial intelligence, especially with respect to diagnosis analysis or ordinary reasoning. These two fields share a common view of abduction as a general process of hypotheses formation. More precisely, abduction is conceived as a kind of reverse explanation where a hypothesis H can be abduced from events E if H is a good explanation of E. The paper surveys four known schemes for abduction (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33.  24
    Bounded low and high sets.Bernard A. Anderson, Barbara F. Csima & Karen M. Lange - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (5-6):507-521.
    Anderson and Csima :245–264, 2014) defined a jump operator, the bounded jump, with respect to bounded Turing reducibility. They showed that the bounded jump is closely related to the Ershov hierarchy and that it satisfies an analogue of Shoenfield jump inversion. We show that there are high bounded low sets and low bounded high sets. Thus, the information coded in the bounded jump is quite different from that of the standard jump. We also consider whether the analogue of the Jump (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  39
    Learning Versus Evolution: From Biology to Game Theory.Bernard Walliser - 2011 - Biological Theory 6 (4):311-319.
    Two main schemes explain how a system adapts to its environment. Evolutionary models are grounded on three usual processes (variation, transmission, selection) acting at the population level. Learning models are concerned with the endogenous search for a better performance at the individual level. The first ones were initially favored by biology and the second well illustrated by game theory. The article examines first how game theory went to evolution and how biology later considered learning. It shows some examples of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  35.  12
    Human evolution.Bernard Wood - 1996 - Bioessays 18 (12):945-954.
    The common ancestor of modern humans and the great apes is estimated to have lived between 5 and 8 Myrs ago, but the earliest evidence in the human, or hominid, fossil record is Ardipithecus ramidus, from a 4.5 Myr Ethiopian site. This genus was succeeded by Australopithecus, within which four species are presently recognised. All combine a relatively primitive postcranial skeleton, a dentition with expanded chewing teeth and a small brain. The most primitive species in our own genus, Homo habilis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  36. On Semantics for Characterizing Sentences.Bernard Nickel - unknown
    The paper presents semantics for a subset of generics, so-called “characterizing sentences”. It is argued that claims about the relationship between the truth of characterizing sentences and claims about the distribution of properties among individuals can be viewed independently of considerations about logical form. Some extant approaches are presented and criticized, and a positive analysis of characterizing sentences in terms of normality is introduced and defended. The main innovation is that a notion of normality enters into the analysis in two (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37. Identity and Identities.Bernard Williams - 1997 - In H. Harris (ed.), Identity. Oxford University Press. pp. 1-11.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38. Acts and omissions, doing and not doing.Bernard Williams - 1995 - In Rosalind Hursthouse, Gavin Lawrence & Warren Quinn (eds.), Virtues and Reasons: Philippa Foot and Moral Theory: Essays in Honour of Philippa Foot. Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 331--40.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39. Left-Wing Wittgenstein, Right-Wing Marx.Bernard Williams - 1992 - Common Knowledge 1 (1):33.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  40.  14
    Sartre: The Philosopher of the Twentieth Century.Bernard-Henri Levy - 2003 - Malden, MA: Polity.
    'A whole man, made of all men, worth all of them, and any one of them worth him.' This was how Jean-Paul Sartre characterized himself at the end of his autobiographical study, Words. And Bernard-Henri Levy shows how Sartre cannot be understood without taking into account his relations with the intellectual forebears and contemporaries, the lovers and friends, with whom he conducted a lifelong debate. His thinking was essentially a tumultuous dialogue with his whole age and himself. He learned (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  13
    Scientific Method: Optimizing Applied Research Decisions.Bernard R. Grunstra - 1965 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 25 (4):594-595.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  43
    Automorphisms of the truth-table degrees are fixed on a cone.Bernard A. Anderson - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):679-688.
    Let $D_{tt} $ denote the set of truth-table degrees. A bijection π: $D_{tt} \to \,D_{tt} $ is an automorphism if for all truth-table degrees x and y we have $ \leqslant _{tt} \,y\, \Leftrightarrow \,\pi (x)\, \leqslant _{tt} \,\pi (y)$ . We say an automorphism π is fixed on a cone if there is a degree b such that for all $x \geqslant _{tt} b$ we have π(x) = x. We first prove that for every 2-generic real X we have (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  28
    Regina quondam….Bernard McGinn - 2008 - Speculum 83 (4):817-839.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  21
    Effects of the instructional sets to remember and to forget on short-term retention: Studies of rehearsal control and retrieval inhibition (repression).Bernard Weiner & Henry Reed - 1969 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 79 (2p1):226.
  45.  9
    Responsibility for social transgressions: An attributional analysis.Bernard Weiner - 2001 - In Bertram F. Malle, Louis J. Moses & Dare A. Baldwin (eds.), Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition. MIT Press. pp. 331--344.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46.  11
    Que savons-nous des femmes diacres?Phyllis Zagano & Bernard Pottier - 2018 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 74 (3):437-445.
    Pope Francis’s decision to establish a Commission for the Study of the Diaconate of Women in August 2016 reemphasizes the question : what do we know about women deacons? We know they existed. There is ample literary, epigraphical, and historical evidence that women deacons ministered in the West at least to the 12th century, and longer in the East. That they existed presents three questions : What do we know about the liturgical ceremonies bishops used to create women deacons? What (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  44
    Russell’s Two Lectures in China on Mathematical Logic.Lianghua Zhou & Bernard Linsky - 2018 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 38 (1):52-68.
    In 1921 Bertrand Russell delivered two lectures on mathematical logic at Peking University. Manuscripts for the lectures have not been found, but two sets of Chinese notes, which were based on a simultaneous oral translation of Russell’s lecturing, were published. The notes are translated into English based on the best readings of both sets. An introduc­tion and notes with a glossary discuss the background and content of the lectures as well as the linguistic difficulties in translating logical terms.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  8
    Seeing and KnowingCaravaggio. His Incongruity and His FamePiero della Francesca. The Ineloquent in ArtThe Arch of Constantine or the Decline of Form.Paul Zucker & Bernard Berenson - 1955 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 13 (4):539.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. Morality and the emotions: an inaugural lecture.Bernard Williams - 1966 - London,: Bedford College.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50. Piety and Power in Thirteenth-Century Catalonia.Bernard Septimus - 1979 - In Isadore Twersky (ed.), Studies in medieval Jewish history and literature. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 199--209.
1 — 50 / 1000