Results for 'Whewell '

(not author) ( search as author name )
309 found
Order:
  1. Whewell’s hylomorphism as a metaphorical explanation for how mind and world merge.Ragnar van der Merwe - 2023 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 54 (1):19-38.
    William Whewell’s 19th century philosophy of science is sometimes glossed over as a footnote to Kant. There is however a key feature of Whewell’s account worth noting. This is his appeal to Aristotle’s form/matter hylomorphism as a metaphor to explain how mind and world merge in successful scientific inquiry. Whewell’s hylomorphism suggests a middle way between rationalism and empiricism reminiscent of experience pragmatists like Steven Levine’s view that mind and world are entwined in experience. I argue however (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2. William Whewell, Cluster Theorist of Kinds.Zina B. Ward - 2023 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 13 (2):362-386.
    A dominant strand of philosophical thought holds that natural kinds are clusters of objects with shared properties. Cluster theories of natural kinds are often taken to be a late twentieth-century development, prompted by dissatisfaction with essentialism in philosophy of biology. I will argue here, however, that a cluster theory of kinds had actually been formulated by William Whewell (1794-1866) more than a century earlier. Cluster theories of kinds can be characterized in terms of three central commitments, all of which (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  48
    William Whewell’s philosophy of architecture and the historicization of biology.Aleta Quinn - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 1 (59):11-19.
    William Whewell’s work on historical science has received some attention from historians and philosophers of science. Whewell’s own work on the history of German Gothic church architecture has been touched on within the context of the history of architecture. To a large extent these discussions have been conducted separately. I argue that Whewell intended his work on Gothic architecture as an attempt to (help) found a science of historical architecture, as an exemplar of historical science. I proceed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  4.  66
    Whewell on classification and consilience.Aleta Quinn - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 1 (64):65-74.
    In this paper I sketch William Whewell’s attempts to impose order on classificatory mineralogy, which was in Whewell’s day (1794e1866) a confused science of uncertain prospects. Whewell argued that progress was impeded by the crude reductionist assumption that all macroproperties of crystals could be straightforwardly explained by reference to the crystals’ chemical constituents. By comparison with biological classification, Whewell proposed methodological reforms that he claimed would lead to a natural classification of minerals, which in turn would (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  5.  12
    William Whewell and John Stuart Mill on the Relationship Between Law and Morality.Metin Aydin - 2021 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 25 (1):49-71.
    This article focuses on the relationship between morality and law through the debate between William Whewell (1794-1866) and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873), two important moral philosophers of 19th century Britain. Whewell belongs to a tradition maintaining that the basic moral principles can be known intuitively through an inherent faculty such as moral sense or conscience. In the meantime, Whewell argues that the process of knowing these basic principles intuitively is not an irrational process and that the reason (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. William Whewell on the Consilience of Inductions.Larry Laudan - 1971 - The Monist 55 (3):368-391.
    Most contributions to Whewell scholarship have tended to stress the idealistic, antiempirical temper of Whewell’s philosophy. Thus, the only two monograph-length studies on Whewell, Blanché’s Le Rationalisme de Whewell and Marcucci’s L’ ‘Idealismo’ Scientifico di William Whewell, are, as their titles suggest, concerned primarily with Whewell’s departures from classical British empiricism. Particularly in his famous dispute with Mill, it has proved tempting to parody Whewell’s position in the debate by treating it as a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  7.  24
    Whewell's Philosophy of Discovery and the Archetype of the Vertebrate Skeleton: The Role of German Philosophy of Science in Richard Owen's Biology.Phillip R. Sloan - 2003 - Annals of Science 60 (1):39-61.
    (2003). Whewell's Philosophy of Discovery and the Archetype of the Vertebrate Skeleton: The Role of German Philosophy of Science in Richard Owen's Biology. Annals of Science: Vol. 60, No. 1, pp. 39-61.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8.  21
    William Whewell: A Composite Portrait.Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.) - 1991 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    William Whewell was a giant of Victorian intellectual culture. His influence, whether recognized or forgotten, is palpable in areas as diverse as moral philosophy, mineralogy, architecture, the politics of education, physics, engineering, and theology. Recent studies of the place of the sciences in nineteenth-century Britain have repeatedly indicated the significance of Whewell's sweeping and critical proposals for a reformed account of scientific knowledge and moral values. However, until now there has been no detailed study of the context and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  9.  38
    William Whewell's Theory of Scientific Method.Robert E. Butts (ed.) - 1969 - University of Pittsburgh Press.
    William Whewell is considered one of the most important nineteenth-century British philosophers of science and a contributor to modern philosophical thought, particularly regarding the problem of induction and the logic of discovery. In this volume, Robert E. Butts offers selections from Whewell's most important writings, and analysis of counter-claims to his philosophy.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  10.  29
    William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid nineteenth century Britain.Richard Yeo - 1979 - Annals of Science 36 (5):493-516.
    (1979). William Whewell, natural theology and the philosophy of science in mid nineteenth century Britain. Annals of Science: Vol. 36, No. 5, pp. 493-516.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  11. William Whewell's Theory of Scientific Method.Robert Butts - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (3):311-312.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  12.  85
    William Whewell, the plurality of worlds, and the modern solar system.Michael J. Crowe - 2016 - Zygon 51 (2):431-449.
    Astronomers of the first half of the nineteenth century viewed our solar system entirely differently from the way twentieth-century astronomers viewed it. In the earlier period the dominant image was of a set of planets and moons, both of which kinds of bodies were inhabited by intelligent beings comparable to humans. By the early twentieth century, science had driven these beings from every planet in our system except the Earth, leaving our solar system as more or less desolate regions for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  63
    William Whewell’s Semantic Account of Induction.Corey Dethier - 2018 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 8 (1):141-156.
    William Whewell’s account of induction differs dramatically from the one familiar from twentieth-century debates. I argue that Whewell’s induction can be usefully understood by comparing the difference between his views and more standard accounts to contemporary debates between semantic and syntactic views of theories: rather than understanding inductive inference as capturing a relationship between sentences or propositions, Whewell understands it as a method for constructing a model of the world. The difference between this view and the more (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  47
    William Whewell and John Stuart Mill: Their Controversy About Scientific Knowledge.E. W. Strong - 1955 - Journal of the History of Ideas 16 (1/4):209.
  15.  47
    Whewell’s Cosilience of Inductions and Predictions.Mary Hesse - 1971 - The Monist 55 (3):520-524.
    In his paper “William Whewell on the Consilience of Inductions” Professor Laudan has suggested that Whewell’s use of “consilience of inductions” is not the same as mine in my paper of that title. Suppose we have a theory T which entails three empirical laws L1, L2, L3. L1 is supposed already confirmed by direct evidence of its instances, but we have as yet no direct evidence for L2 or for L3. Then Laudan distinguishes two problems: Whewell’s problem: (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  16. William Whewell Philosopher of Sciences.Menachem Fisch & Robert C. Richardson - 1994 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 16 (1):155.
  17.  49
    Whewell, Necessity and The Inductive Sciences: A Philosophical-Systematic Survey.Steffen Ducheyne - 2009 - South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (4):333-358.
    In this paper Whewell’s concept of necessity is scrutinized and its historical development is outlined (ca. 1833-1860). Particular attention will be paid to how Whewell interpreted the laws of the inductive sciences as being necessary since the laws of nature are concretizations of the Fundamental Ideas which can be partially described by Axioms.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  18
    Whewell’s Cosilience of Inductions and Predictions.Mary Hesse - 1971 - The Monist 55 (3):520-524.
    In his paper “William Whewell on the Consilience of Inductions” Professor Laudan has suggested that Whewell’s use of “consilience of inductions” is not the same as mine in my paper of that title. Suppose we have a theory T which entails three empirical laws L1, L2, L3. L1 is supposed already confirmed by direct evidence of its instances, but we have as yet no direct evidence for L2 or for L3. Then Laudan distinguishes two problems: Whewell’s problem: (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  19.  28
    Interpreting Whewell.Andrew Belsey - 1974 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 5 (1):49.
  20.  4
    William Whewell and the Concept of Scientific Revolution.I. Bernard Cohen - 1976 - In R. S. Cohen, P. K. Feyerabend & M. Wartofsky (eds.), Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos. Reidel. pp. 55--63.
  21.  48
    Whewell and Mill on the Relation Between Philosophy of Science and History of Science.John Losee - 1983 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 14 (2):113.
  22.  75
    Whewell's Consilience of Inductions–An Evaluation.Menachem Fisch - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (2):239-255.
    The paper attempts to elucidate and evaluate William Whewell's notion of a "consilience of inductions." In section I Whewellian consilience is defined and shown to differ considerably from what latter-day writers talk about when they use the term. In section II a primary analysis of consilience is shown to yield two types of consilient processes, one in which one of the lower-level laws undergoes a conceptual change (the case aptly discussed in Butts [1977]), and one in which the explanatory (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  23.  39
    Whewell on necessity.Harold T. Walsh - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (2):139-145.
    It is generally not recognized that Whewell's conception of necessary truth evolved only gradually; his early statements are misleading. For this reason, and because of certain peculiarities in his expository style over his publishing history, he is commonly thought to have used the term "necessary" in the sense of "absolutely necessary". I argue that, on the contrary, the term is essentially relational in his mature view. This conclusion leads, in turn, to a re-interpretation of his doctrine of "fundamental ideas". (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  71
    Whewell and mill on induction.Harold T. Walsh - 1962 - Philosophy of Science 29 (3):279-284.
    Much of the Mill-Whewell dispute was purely verbal, but much was not. Mill did not understand Whewell; the true character of the non-verbal aspect of the controversy emerges only upon adequate analysis of Whewell's actual position. Such analysis shows that Mill's objections to Whewell were misdirected, although suggestive of other which might, if prosecuted, carry. Ultimately, the dispute has to do with the given; neither man gives an adequate account of it. For this reason, the controversy (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Whewell’s tidal researches: scientific practice and philosophical methodology.Steffen Ducheyne - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (1):26-40.
    Primarily between 1833 and 1840, William Whewell attempted to accomplish what natural philosophers and scientists since at least Galileo had failed to do: to provide a systematic and broad-ranged study of the tides and to attempt to establish a general scientific theory of tidal phenomena. I document the close interaction between Whewell’s philosophy of science and his scientific practice as a tidologist. I claim that the intertwinement between Whewell’s methodology and his tidology is more fundamental than has (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26.  4
    W. Whewell: Induction and Deduction in Novum Organon Renovatum.А. С Омолоева & А. Е Симбирцева - 2023 - Siberian Journal of Philosophy 20 (4):113-126.
    The paper aims to expose the induction – deduction relation within W. Whewell’s treatise «Novum Organon Renovatum». Since Aristotle’s time. induction and deduction have been interpreted as independent and even «opposite» inferences (ways of connecting premises and conclusions), but this intuition is violated in W. Whewell’s works. Based on contemporary practice of some specific natural sciences W. Whewell quite reasonably concludes that “Aristotle overlooks a step which is of far more importance to our knowledge, namely, the invention (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. Whewell on moral philosophy.J. S. Mill - 1987 - In John Stuart Mill (ed.), Utilitarianism and Other Essays. Penguin Books.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  28.  13
    Whewell's Philosophy of Induction. By Marion Rush Stoll. (Lancaster, Pa, Lancaster Press, Ic. 1929. Pp. iv + 125.).A. Wolf - 1931 - Philosophy 6 (21):135-.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  18
    Review Essays: Whewell’s Philosophy under Dispute.Ron Curtis - 2009 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 39 (3):495-506.
    William Whewell tried to explain how scientific knowledge of necessary and certain truth was possible by tracing it to ideas that arose not out of experience but had an independent origin in the mind. Although Whewell has generally been regarded as an a priorist in some sense and as a proponent of hypothetico-deductivism, Snyder tries to show that he can be assimilated to the twentieth-century inductivist mainstream. She fails to make her case, however, in part because she fails (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  54
    William Whewell and The Argument from Design.Michael Ruse - 1977 - The Monist 60 (2):244-268.
    The section on the Argument from Design in collections of readings in the philosophy of religion usually begins with an expository selection drawn from Archdeacon William Paley’s Natural Theology, and follows with a critical selection drawn from David Hume’s Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion. Only from the footnotes does the student learn that Hume’s Dialogues was published over twenty years before Paley’s Natural Theology. Probably the student will feel that Hume’s devastating critique of the Argument must strike every reasonable person with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  31.  71
    Whewell on the ultimate problem of philosophy.Margaret Morrison - 1997 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 28 (3):417-437.
  32. William Whewell: Omniscientist.Michael Ruse - 1991 - In Menachem Fisch & Simon Schaffer (eds.), William Whewell: A Composite Portrait. Clarendon Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  33.  53
    Whewell's elements of morality.Alan Donagan - 1974 - Journal of Philosophy 71 (19):724-736.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  34
    Whewell and the Scientists: Science and Philosophy of Science in 19th Century Britain.Laura Snyder - 2002 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 9:81-94.
    What is the relation between science and philosophy of science? Specifically, does it matter whether a philosopher of science knows much about science or is actually engaged in scientific research? William Whewell is an obvious person to consider in relation to this question. Whewell was actively engaged in science in several important ways, some of which have not been previously noted. He conducted research in a number of scientific fields, he devised new terminology for the new discoveries made (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  7
    William Whewell: A Composite Portrait.James W. Allard - 1992 - Philosophical Books 33 (3):144-146.
  36.  50
    The Whewell-Faraday exchange on the application of the concepts of momentum and inertia to electromagnetic phenomena.Ronald Anderson - 1994 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (4):577-594.
  37.  35
    Wittgenstein's Whewell's Court Lectures: Cambridge, 1938 – 1941, from the Notes by Yorick Smythies.Volker A. Munz & Bernhard Ritter (eds.) - 2017 - Chichester, UK: Wiley Blackwell.
    Wittgenstein’s Whewell’s Court Lectures contains previously unpublished notes from lectures given by Ludwig Wittgenstein between 1938 and 1941. The volume offers new insight into the development of Wittgenstein’s thought and includes some of the finest examples of Wittgenstein’s lectures in regard to both content and reliability.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  38. William Whewell (1794-1866).Malcolm Forster - manuscript
    Whewell, William (b Lancaster, England, 24 May 1794; d Cambridge, England, 6 March 1866) Born the eldest son of a carpenter, William Whewell rose to become Master of Trinity College, Cambridge and a central figure in Victorian science. After attending the grammar school at Heversham in Westmorland, Whewell entered Trinity College, Cambridge and graduated Second Wrangler. He became a Fellow of the College in 1817, took his M.A. degree in 1819, and his D.D. degree in 1844.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  27
    Whewell on the classification of the sciences.Raphaël Sandoz - 2016 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 60:48-54.
  40.  10
    William Whewell philosopher of science.David Knight - 1992 - History of European Ideas 14 (3):460-461.
  41. William Whewell on the History of Science.Richard Yeo - 1987 - Metascience 5:25.
  42.  11
    Whewells philosophy of induction..H. R. Smart & Marion Rush Stoll - 1929 - [n.p.]: Lancaster Press.
  43.  23
    William Whewell: Theory of Scientific Method.Robert E. Butts (ed.) - 1989 - Hackett Publishing.
    This volume includes Whewell's seminal studies of the logic of induction (with his critique of Mill's theory), arguments for his realist view that science discovers necessary truths about nature, and exercises in the epistemology and ontology of science. The book sets forth a coherent statement of a historically important philosophy of science whose influence has never been greater: every one of Whewell's fundamental ideas about the philosophy of science is presented here.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  44.  30
    William Whewell.Laura J. Snyder - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  45.  20
    William Whewell and John Stuart Mill on the Methodology of Political Economy.Samuel Hollander - 1983 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 14 (2):127.
  46. Herschel, Whewell, Stuart Mill e l'«analogia della natura».P. Casini - 1981 - Rivista di Filosofia 21 (3):372-91.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Defining Science. William Whewell, Natural Knowledge, and Public Debate in Early Victorian Britain.R. Yeo & G. Cantor - 1995 - Annals of Science 52 (1):88-89.
  48.  9
    Whewell's metaphorical usage of light and the ultimate reality underlying it.Steffen Ducheyne - 2008 - Semiotica 2008 (172):269-278.
    In this article, I seek to study Whewell as writer of philosophical doctrines by focusing on his frequent usage of the metaphor of light, which symbolized (human) knowledge. It is my primary claim that Whewell choose to visually illustrate his doctrine of Fundamental Ideas, which are the bearers of ultimate reality and meaning in Whewell's epistemology, by means some key metaphors that made reference to light.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  50
    Whewell's philosophy of scientific discovery. I.C. J. Ducasse - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):56-69.
  50.  17
    Whewell's Philosophy of Scientific Discovery. I.C. J. Ducasse - 1951 - Philosophical Review 60 (1):56-69.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
1 — 50 / 309